Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The Scientific Image.William Demopoulos & Bas C. van Fraassen - 1982 - Philosophical Review 91 (4):603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1762 citations  
  • Models and methodologies in current theoretical high-energy physics.James T. Cushing - 1982 - Synthese 50 (1):5 - 101.
    A case study of the development of quantum field theory and of S-matrix theory, from their inceptions to the present, is presented. The descriptions of science given by Kuhn and by Lakatos are compared and contrasted as they apply to this case study. The episodes of the developments of these theories are then considered as candidates for competing research programs in Lakatos' methodology of scientific research programs. Lakatos' scheme provides a reasonable overall description and a plausible assessment of the relative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Model-structures and model-objects.Henry Byerly - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (2):135-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Causality and Chance in Modern Physics.David Bohm - 1960 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 10 (40):321-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   98 citations  
  • Two concepts of constraint: Adaptationism and the challenge from developmental biology.Ron Amundson - 1994 - Philosophy of Science 61 (4):556-578.
    The so-called "adaptationism" of mainstream evolutionary biology has been criticized from a variety of sources. One, which has received relatively little philosophical attention, is developmental biology. Developmental constraints are said to be neglected by adaptationists. This paper explores the divergent methodological and explanatory interests that separate mainstream evolutionary biology from its embryological and developmental critics. It will focus on the concept of constraint itself; even this central concept is understood differently by the two sides of the dispute.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   86 citations  
  • Theoretical models.Peter Achinstein - 1965 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 16 (62):102-120.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - New York, NY, USA: Harcourt, Brace & World.
    Introduction: Science and Common Sense Long before the beginnings of modern civilization, men ac- quired vast funds of information about their environment. ...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   484 citations  
  • Why did Einstein's programme supersede lorentz's? (II).Elie Zahar - 1973 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24 (3):223-262.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Wrong theory—Right experiment: The significance of the Stern-Gerlach experiments.Friedel Weinert - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26 (1):75-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Wrong theory—Right experiment: The significance of the Stern-Gerlach experiments.Friedel Weinert - 1995 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 26 (1):75-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Vicissitudes of laboratory life.Friedel Weinert - 1992 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (3):423-429.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Duhem‐Quine thesis revisited.F. Weinert - 1995 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9 (2):147 – 156.
    Abstract The Duhem?Quine thesis is generally presented as the radical underdetermi? nation of a theory by experimental evidence. But there is a much?neglected second aspect, i.e. the coherence or interrelatedness of the conceptual components of a theory. Although both Duhem and Quine recognised this aspect, they failed to see its consequences: it militates against the idea of radical underdetermination. Because scientific theories are coherent conceptual systems, empirical evidence penetrates, as it were, the periphery and allows the localisation of central, not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On Growth and Form. [REVIEW]E. N. - 1945 - Journal of Philosophy 42 (20):557-558.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   186 citations  
  • The Philosophy of the Social Sciences.Robert C. Stalnaker - 1973 - Philosophical Review 82 (1):126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Models and theories.Marshall Spector - 1965 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 16 (62):121-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Models in physics.Michael Redhead - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (2):145-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   102 citations  
  • Simplicity in scientific theories.H. R. Post - 1960 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 11 (41):32-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics: In Praise of Conservative Induction.H. R. Post - 1971 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 2 (3):213.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • Review of Andrew Pickering: The Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency, and Science_; Jed Z. Buchwald: _Scientific practice: theories and stories of doing physics[REVIEW]Andrew Pickering & David Chart - 1996 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (3):479-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Fact and Method.Richard W. Miller - 1991 - Journal of Philosophy 88 (3):159-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   78 citations  
  • Galilean Idealization.Ernan McMullin - 1985 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 (3):247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   311 citations  
  • Induction and scientific realism: Einstein versus Van Fraassen part three: Einstein, aim-oriented empiricism and the discovery of special and general relativity.Nicholas Maxwell - 1993 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (2):275-305.
    In this paper I show that Einstein made essential use of aim-oriented empiricism in scientific practice in developing special and general relativity. I conclude by considering to what extent Einstein came explicitly to advocate aim-oriented empiricism in his later years.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Does orthodox quantum theory undermine, or support, scientific realism?Nicholas Maxwell - 1994 - Philosophical Quarterly 44 (171):139-157.
    It is usually taken for granted that orthodox quantum theory poses a serious problem for scientific realism, in that the theory is empirically extraordinarily successful, and yet has instrumentalism built into it. This paper stand this view on its head. I argue that orthodox quantum theory suffers from a number of serious (if not always noticed) defects precisely because of its inbuilt instrumentalism. This defective character of orthdoox quantum theory thus undermines instrumentalism, and supports scientific realism. I go on to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The computational and confirmational differences between the social and the physical sciences.Ronald Laymon - 1993 - Philosophia 22 (3-4):241-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Cartwright and the Lying Laws of Physics.Ronald Laymon - 1989 - Journal of Philosophy 86 (7):353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Einstein's attitude towards experiments: Testing relativity theory 1907–1927.Klaus Hentschel - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 23 (4):593-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Instrument and Reality: The Case of Terrestrial Magnetism and the Northern Lights (Aurora Borealis).Willem Hackmann - 1995 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 38:29-51.
    In recent years there has been an increasing focus on the role of instruments in the study of nature, both by historians and by philosophers of science, and even by a few art historians who are interested by the images produced by these devices.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World.Ronald N. Giere - 1988 - Philosophical Review 97 (3):444.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   355 citations  
  • Explaining Science.Ronald Giere - 1991 - Noûs 25 (3):386-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   291 citations  
  • Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. [REVIEW]Jeffrey S. Poland - 1988 - Philosophical Review 100 (4):653-656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   585 citations  
  • Review of H ow Experiments End.Ian Hacking - 1990 - Journal of Philosophy 87 (2):103-106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   183 citations  
  • How Experiments End.Peter Galison - 1988 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 39 (3):411-414.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   208 citations  
  • Ontological constraints and understanding quantum phenomena.Henry J. Folse - 1996 - Dialectica 50 (2):121-136.
    The question of whether an «understanding» of quantum phenomena is possible, as raised by Cushing , is considered in terms of a possible revision of basic ontological assumptions which would make rational the pursuit of such an understanding. It is argued that the quantum theory imposes new constraints on ontology which force us to revise classical presuppositions about attributing properties to physical systems, about locality and individuality, and about interaction and space‐like separability. Through such ontological revision, it is argued, one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The analysis of particle tracks: A case for trust in the unity of physics.Brigitte Falkenburg - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (3):337-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The analysis of particle tracks: A case for trust in the unity of physics.Brigitte Falkenburg - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27 (3):337-371.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Semantic Conception of Theories and Scientific Realism.Frederick Suppe - 1989 - University of Illinois Press.
    Frederick Suppe has come to enjoy a position of undisputed leadership in the post-positivistic philosophy of science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   212 citations  
  • The Structure of Scientific Theories.Frederick Suppe - 1977 - Critica 11 (31):138-140.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   294 citations  
  • The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation.Ernest Nagel - 1961 - Mind 72 (287):429-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   282 citations  
  • Models as a Tool for Theory Construction: Some Strategies of Preliminary Physics.Stephan Hartmann - 1995 - In William Herfel, Władysław Krajewski, Ilkka Niiniluoto & Ryszard Wójcicki (eds.), Theories and Models in Scientific Processes. Rodopi. pp. 49-67.
    Theoretical models are an important tool for many aspects of scientific activity. They are used, i.a., to structure data, to apply theories or even to construct new theories. But what exactly is a model? It turns out that there is no proper definition of the term "model" that covers all these aspects. Thus, I restrict myself here to evaluate the function of models in the research process while using "model" in the loose way physicists do. To this end, I distinguish (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Models and Analogies in Science.Mary B. Hesse - 1966 - Philosophy and Rhetoric 3 (3):190-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   411 citations  
  • The Mangle of Practice.Andrew Pickering & Jed Z. Buchwald - 1996 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (3):479-482.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   216 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Physical Science.Arthur Eddington - 1940 - Mind 49 (196):455-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Philosophy of Physical Science.Arthur Eddington - 1940 - Revue de Métaphysique et de Morale 47 (4):413-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • The Structure and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics.R. I. G. Hughes, James T. Cushing & Ernan Mcmullin - 1991 - Synthese 86 (1):99-122.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   80 citations  
  • On the Constitution of Atoms and Molecules, Part I.Niels Bohr - 1913 - Philosophical Magazine 26:1--25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • Mind and body.Hilary Putnam - 1981 - In Reason, Truth and History. Cambridge University Press.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   250 citations