Switch to: Citations

Add references

You must login to add references.
  1. The syntax of predication.John Bowers - 1993 - Linguistic Inquiry 24:591--656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • On Quantifier Domain Restriction.Jason Stanley & Zoltán Gendler Szabó - 2000 - Mind and Language 15 (2-3):219--61.
    In this paper, we provide a comprehensive survey of the space of possible analyses of the phenomenon of quantifier domain restriction, together with a set of considerations which militate against all but our own proposal. Among the many accounts we consider and reject are the ‘explicit’ approach to quantifier domain restric‐tion discussed, for example, by Stephen Neale, and the pragmatic approach to quantifier domain restriction proposed by Kent Bach. Our hope is that the exhaustive discussion of this special case of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   392 citations  
  • Saving substitutivity in simple sentences.Joseph G. Moore - 1999 - Analysis 59 (2):91–105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • A model theory for propositional attitudes.Richmond H. Thomason - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (1):47 - 70.
    My chief aim has been to convey the thought that the application of model theoretic techniques to natural languages needn't force a distortion of intentional phenomena. I hope that at least I have succeeded in accomplishing this.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • (1 other version)Context and logical form.Jason Stanley - 2000 - Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (4):391--434.
    In this paper, I defend the thesis that alleffects of extra-linguistic context on thetruth-conditions of an assertion are traceable toelements in the actual syntactic structure of thesentence uttered. In the first section, I develop thethesis in detail, and discuss its implications for therelation between semantics and pragmatics. The nexttwo sections are devoted to apparent counterexamples.In the second section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of true non-sentential assertions.In the third section, I argue that there are noconvincing examples of what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   352 citations  
  • Implicit comparison classes.Peter Ludlow - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (4):519 - 533.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Introduction to Propositions and Attitudes.Nathan Salmon & Scott Soames - 1988 - In Nathan U. Salmon & Scott Soames (eds.), _Propositions and Attitudes_. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 1-15.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • (1 other version)Intention.G. E. M. Anscombe - 1957 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57:321-332.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1050 citations  
  • Quantification and context.Marga Reimer - 1998 - Linguistics and Philosophy 21 (1):95-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Enlightened semantics for simple sentences.G. Forbes - 1999 - Analysis 59 (2):86-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Substitution, simple sentences, and sex scandals.Jennifer M. Saul - 1999 - Analysis 59 (2):106-112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Simple Sentences, Substitutions, and Mistaken Evaluations.David Braun & Jennifer Saul - 2002 - Philosophical Studies 111 (1):1 - 41.
    Many competent speakers initially judge that (i) is true and (ii) isfalse, though they know that (iii) is true. (i) Superman leaps more tallbuildings than Clark Kent. (ii) Superman leaps more tall buildings thanSuperman. (iii) Superman is identical with Clark Kent. Semanticexplanations of these intuitions say that (i) and (ii) really can differin truth-value. Pragmatic explanations deny this, and say that theintuitions are due to misleading implicatures. This paper argues thatboth explanations are incorrect. (i) and (ii) cannot differ intruth-value, yet (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Did Clinton lie?Joseph G. Moore - 2000 - Analysis 60 (3):250-254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • How much substitutivity?Graeme Forbes - 1997 - Analysis 57 (2):109–113.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • (1 other version)On semantics.James Higginbotham - 1985 - Linguistic Inquiry 16:547--593.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   142 citations  
  • Groups, II.Fred Landman - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (6):723 - 744.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Reply to Forbes.Jennifer M. Saul - 1997 - Analysis 57 (2):114–118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Underlying states and time travel.Terence Parsons - 2000 - In James Higginbotham, Fabio Pianesi & Achille C. Varzi (eds.), Speaking of events. New York: Oxford University Press.
    I begin by sketching a theory about the semantics of verbs in event sentences, and the evidence on which that theory is based. In the second section, I discuss the evidence for extending that theory to state sentences, including copulative sentences with adjectives and nouns; the evidence for this extension of the theory is not very good. In the third section, I discuss new evidence based on considerations of talk about time travel; that evidence is apparently quite good. I conclude (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations