Switch to: References

Citations of:

Animate vision

Artificial Intelligence 48 (1):57-86 (1991)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The redness of red. Introduction to an interview with J. Kevin O'Regan.Jakub R. Matyja - 2011 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies 2 (2):17-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Afordancje dla robotów: krótki przegląd.Robert St Amant, Arpan Chakraborty & Thomas E. Horton - 2014 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies 5 (1):133-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Embodied Cognition View: The Return of Body as Subject in Cognitive Science Research.Bo Chen, Wei Chen & Jun Ding - 2019 - Journal of Human Cognition 3 (1):54-75.
    The view of embodied cognition believes that cognition is embodied in nature, only the dynamics involved in the interaction between cognitive activities and the nervous system, body and environment, only by closely linking the correct evaluation of time-dependent and relationship, then only can make a correct understanding of cognitive activities. The core concepts of body and environment involved in embodied cognition are different from the body and environment in the usual sense. In terms of research methods, dynamic research methods that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hitting the nail on the head.Daniel C. Dennett - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):35-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ucieleśnione poznanie — założenia, tezy i wyzwania.Andrzej Dąbrowski - 2021 - Argument: Biannual Philosophical Journal 11 (1).
    Embodied cognition: assumptions, theses and challenges: The paper aims at providing a concise presentation of the concept of embodied cognition that emerged in the cognitive sciences a few decades ago and has gained great popularity among empirically and philosophically informed researchers. The term “embodied cognition” is used by the author in two senses. The narrow sense implies that the body plays an important role in the process of cognition. In the broad sense “embodied cognition” is to characterize the general tendency (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is a colour space?Jules Davidoff - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Color is as color does.James L. Dannemiller - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemological strata and the rules of right reason.Robert C. Cummins, Pierre Poirier & Martin Roth - 2004 - Synthese 141 (3):287 - 331.
    It has been commonplace in epistemology since its inception to idealize away from computational resource constraints, i.e., from the constraints of time and memory. One thought is that a kind of ideal rationality can be specified that ignores the constraints imposed by limited time and memory, and that actual cognitive performance can be seen as an interaction between the norms of ideal rationality and the practicalities of time and memory limitations. But a cornerstone of naturalistic epistemology is that normative assessment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Dynamical Challenge.Andy Clark - 1997 - Cognitive Science 21 (4):461-481.
    Recent studies such as Thelen and Smith, Kelso, Van Gelder, Beer, and others have presented a forceful case for a dynamical systems approach to understanding cognition and adaptive behavior. These studies call into question some foundational assumptions concerning the nature of cognitive scientific explanation and the role of notions such as internal representation and computation. These are exciting and important challenges. But they must be handled with care. It is all to easy in this debate to lose sight of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Spreading the joy? Why the machinery of consciousness is (probably) still in the head.Andy Clark - 2009 - Mind 118 (472):963-993.
    Is consciousness all in the head, or might the minimal physical substrate for some forms of conscious experience include the goings on in the (rest of the) body and the world? Such a view might be dubbed (by analogy with Clark and Chalmers’s ( 1998 ) claims concerning ‘the extended mind’) ‘the extended conscious mind’. In this article, I review a variety of arguments for the extended conscious mind, and find them flawed. Arguments for extended cognition, I conclude, do not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Reasons, robots and the extended mind.Andy Clark - 2001 - Mind and Language 16 (2):121-145.
    A suitable project for the new Millenium is to radically reconfigure our image of human rationality. Such a project is already underway, within the Cognitive Sciences, under the umbrellas of work in Situated Cognition, Distributed and De-centralized Cogition, Real-world Robotics and Artificial Life1. Such approaches, however, are often criticized for giving certain aspects of rationality too wide a berth. They focus their attention on on such superficially poor cousins as.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   75 citations  
  • Reductionism and subjectivism defined and defended.Austen Clark - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):32-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • An embodied cognitive science?Andy Clark - 1999 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 3 (9):345-351.
    The last ten years have seen an increasing interest, within cognitive science, in issues concerning the physical body, the local environment, and the complex interplay between neural systems and the wider world in which they function. --œPhysically embodied, environmentally embedded--� approaches thus loom large on the contemporary cognitive scientific scene. Yet many unanswered questions remain, and the shape of a genuinely embodied, embedded science of the mind is still unclear. I begin by sketching a few examples of the approach, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Embodiment and the Philosophy of Mind.Andy Clark - 1998 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 43:35-51.
    Cognitive science is in some sense the science of the mind. But an increasingly influential theme, in recent years, has been the role of the physical body, and of the local environment, in promoting adaptive success. No right-minded cognitive scientist, to be sure, ever claimed that body and world were completely irrelevant to the understanding of mind. But there was, nonetheless, an unmistakeable tendency to marginalize such factors: to dwell on inner complexity whilst simplifying or ignoring the complex inner-outer interplays (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Dreaming the Whole Cat: Generative Models, Predictive Processing, and the Enactivist Conception of Perceptual Experience.Andy Clark - 2012 - Mind 121 (483):753-771.
    Does the material basis of conscious experience extend beyond the boundaries of the brain and central nervous system? In Clark 2009 I reviewed a number of ‘enactivist’ arguments for such a view and found none of them compelling. Ward (2012) rejects my analysis on the grounds that the enactivist deploys an essentially world-involving concept of experience that transforms the argumentative landscape in a way that makes the enactivist conclusion inescapable. I present an alternative (prediction-and-generative-model-based) account that neatly accommodates all the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • Busting Out: Predictive Brains, Embodied Minds, and the Puzzle of the Evidentiary Veil.Andy Clark - 2017 - Noûs 51 (4):727-753.
    Biological brains are increasingly cast as ‘prediction machines’: evolved organs whose core operating principle is to learn about the world by trying to predict their own patterns of sensory stimulation. This, some argue, should lead us to embrace a brain-bound ‘neurocentric’ vision of the mind. The mind, such views suggest, consists entirely in the skull-bound activity of the predictive brain. In this paper I reject the inference from predictive brains to skull-bound minds. Predictive brains, I hope to show, can be (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Understanding dynamic scenes.A. Chella, M. Frixione & S. Gaglio - 2000 - Artificial Intelligence 123 (1-2):89-132.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A cognitive architecture for artificial vision.A. Chella, M. Frixione & S. Gaglio - 1997 - Artificial Intelligence 89 (1-2):73-111.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Visual surveillance in a dynamic and uncertain world.Hilary Buxton & Shaogang Gong - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 78 (1-2):431-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Keeping Track of Invisible Individuals While Exploring a Spatial Layout with Partial Cues: Location-based and Deictic Direction-based Strategies.Nicolas Bullot - 2008 - Philosophical Psychology 21 (1):15-46.
    In contrast to Constructivist Views, which construe perceptual cognition as an essentially reconstructive process, this article recommends the Deictic View, which grounds perception in perceptual-demonstrative reference and the use of deictic tracking strategies for acquiring and updating knowledge about individuals. The view raises the problem of how sensory-motor tracking connects to epistemic and integrated forms of tracking. To study the strategies used to solve this problem, we report a study of the ability to track distal individuals when only their directions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Nonreductionism, content and evolutionary explanation.Justin Broackes - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Procedures and Strategies: Context-dependence in Creativity.Ingar Brinck - 1999 - Philosophica 64 (2):33-47.
    Recently, it has been suggested that at least somekinds of mental representation are strongly context-dependent. Not only what is represented, but also how, depends on the context and the subject's interaction with it. Theories about situated cognition stress the importance of the subject's bodily presence and physical activity in the environment for representing and thinking. What does this mean for creativity? Context-dependence can, it seems, both impede and support creativity. Is creativity a higher-level cognitive function, or does it mainly rely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Handbook of Evolutionary Thinking in the Sciences.Thomas Heams, Philippe Huneman, Guillaume Lecointre & Marc Silberstein (eds.) - 2015 - Springer.
    The Darwinian theory of evolution is itself evolving and this book presents the details of the core of modern Darwinism and its latest developmental directions. The authors present current scientific work addressing theoretical problems and challenges in four sections, beginning with the concepts of evolution theory, its processes of variation, heredity, selection, adaptation and function, and its patterns of character, species, descent and life. The second part of this book scrutinizes Darwinism in the philosophy of science and its usefulness in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Problems with explaining the perceptual environment.Aaron Ben-Ze'ev - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):30-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction.Randall D. Beer - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 72 (1-2):173-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   127 citations  
  • Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist challenge in cognitive science.William Bechtel - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (3):295-317.
    Advocates of dynamical systems theory (DST) sometimes employ revolutionary rhetoric. In an attempt to clarify how DST models differ from others in cognitive science, I focus on two issues raised by DST: the role for representations in mental models and the conception of explanation invoked. Two features of representations are their role in standing-in for features external to the system and their format. DST advocates sometimes claim to have repudiated the need for stand-ins in DST models, but I argue that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   85 citations  
  • Looking down, around, and up: Mechanistic explanation in psychology.William Bechtel - 2009 - Philosophical Psychology 22 (5):543-564.
    Accounts of mechanistic explanation have emphasized the importance of looking down—decomposing a mechanism into its parts and operations. Using research on visual processing as an exemplar, I illustrate how productive such research has been. But once multiple components of a mechanism have been identified, researchers also need to figure out how it is organized—they must look around and determine how to recompose the mechanism. Although researchers often begin by trying to recompose the mechanism in terms of sequential operations, they frequently (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   69 citations  
  • Multiple Realizability Revisited: Linking Cognitive and Neural States.William Bechtel - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (2):175-207.
    The claim of the multiple realizability of mental states by brain states has been a major feature of the dominant philosophy of mind of the late 20th century. The claim is usually motivated by evidence that mental states are multiply realized, both within humans and between humans and other species. We challenge this contention by focusing on how neuroscientists differentiate brain areas. The fact that they rely centrally on psychological measures in mapping the brain and do so in a comparative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   197 citations  
  • Conclusions from color vision of insects.Werner Backhaus & Randolf Menzel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):28-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • A limited objectivism defended.Edward Wilson Averill - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phenomenal Consciousness and the Sensorimotor Approach. A Critical Account.Dell’Anna Alessandro & Paternoster Alfredo - 2013 - Open Journal of Philosophy 3 (4):435.
    The paper discusses some recent suggestions offered by the so-called sensorimotor (or enactivist) theorists as to the problem of the explanatory gap, that is, the alleged impossibility of accounting for phenomenal consciousness in any scientific theory. We argue in the paper that, although some enactivist theorists’ suggestions appear fresh and eye-opening, the claim that the explanatory gap is (dis)solved is much overstated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • More than mere coloring: The art of spectral vision.Kathleen A. Akins & John Lamping - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computational research on interaction and agency.Philip E. Agre - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 72 (1-2):1-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Heidegger and the romantics: the literary invention of meaning.Pol Vandevelde - 2012 - New York: Routledge.
    <P>While there are many books on the romantics, and many books on Heidegger, there has been no book exploring the connection between the two. Pol Vandevelde’s new study forges this important link. </P> <P>Vandevelde begins by analyzing two models that have addressed the interaction between literature and philosophy: early German romanticism (especially Schlegel and Novalis), and Heidegger’s work with poetry in the 1930s. Both models offer an alternative to the paradigm of mimesis, as exemplified by Aristotle’s and Plato’s discussion of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Ontogeny and ontology: Ontophyletics and enactive focal vision.Barry Lia - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):43-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Structure of Sensorimotor Explanation.Alfredo Vernazzani - 2018 - Synthese (11):4527-4553.
    The sensorimotor theory of vision and visual consciousness is often described as a radical alternative to the computational and connectionist orthodoxy in the study of visual perception. However, it is far from clear whether the theory represents a significant departure from orthodox approaches or whether it is an enrichment of it. In this study, I tackle this issue by focusing on the explanatory structure of the sensorimotor theory. I argue that the standard formulation of the theory subscribes to the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Multiple Sensory‐Motor Pathways Lead to Coordinated Visual Attention.Chen Yu & Linda B. Smith - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (S1):5-31.
    Joint attention has been extensively studied in the developmental literature because of overwhelming evidence that the ability to socially coordinate visual attention to an object is essential to healthy developmental outcomes, including language learning. The goal of this study was to understand the complex system of sensory-motor behaviors that may underlie the establishment of joint attention between parents and toddlers. In an experimental task, parents and toddlers played together with multiple toys. We objectively measured joint attention—and the sensory-motor behaviors that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Visual stuff and active vision.Wayne Wright - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (2):129-149.
    This paper examines the status of unattended visual stimuli in the light of recent work on the role of attention in visual perception. Although the question of whether attention is required for visual experience seems very interesting, this paper argues that there currently is no good reason to take a stand on the issue. Moreover, it is argued that much of the allure of that question stems from a continued attachment to the defective ‘inner picture view’ of experience and a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An ecological approach to cognitive (im)penetrability.Rob Withagen & Claire F. Michaels - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (3):399-400.
    We offer an ecological (Gibsonian) alternative to cognitive (im)penetrability. Whereas Pylyshyn explains cognitive (im)penetrability by focusing solely on computations carried out by the nervous system, according to the ecological approach the perceiver as a knowing agent influences the entire animal-environmental system: in the determination of what constitutes the environment (affordances), what constitutes information, what information is detected and, thus, what is perceived.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meaning making and the mind of the externalist.Robert A. Wilson - 2010 - In Richard Menary (ed.), The Extended Mind. MIT Press. pp. 167--188.
    This paper attempts to do two things. First, it recounts the problem of intentionality, as it has typically been conceptualized, and argues that it needs to be reconceptualized in light of the radical form of externalism most commonly referred to as the extended mind thesis. Second, it provides an explicit, novel argument for that thesis, what I call the argument from meaning making, and offers some defense of that argument. This second task occupies the core of the paper, and in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Reinforcement learning of non-Markov decision processes.Steven D. Whitehead & Long-Ji Lin - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 73 (1-2):271-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The dynamics of perception and action.William H. Warren - 2006 - Psychological Review 113 (2):358-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Knowing what we can do: actions, intentions, and the construction of phenomenal experience.Dave Ward, Tom Roberts & Andy Clark - 2011 - Synthese 181 (3):375-394.
    How do questions concerning consciousness and phenomenal experience relate to, or interface with, questions concerning plans, knowledge and intentions? At least in the case of visual experience the relation, we shall argue, is tight. Visual perceptual experience, we shall argue, is fixed by an agent’s direct unmediated knowledge concerning her poise (or apparent poise) over a currently enabled action space. An action space, in this specific sense, is to be understood not as a fine-grained matrix of possibilities for bodily movement, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Ways of coloring the ecological approach.Johan Wagemans & Charles M. M. de Weert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):54-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The ethnocentricity of colour.J. van Brakel - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):53-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Modeling visual attention via selective tuning.John K. Tsotsos, Scan M. Culhane, Winky Yan Kei Wai, Yuzhong Lai, Neal Davis & Fernando Nuflo - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 78 (1-2):507-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Behaviorist intelligence and the scaling problem.John K. Tsotsos - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 75 (2):135-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • In Honor of Michael K. Tanenhaus for Receiving the 2018 Rumelhart Prize.John C. Trueswell - 2021 - Topics in Cognitive Science 13 (2):304-308.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ways of coloring: Comparative color vision as a case study for cognitive science.Evan Thompson, Adrian Palacios & Francisco J. Varela - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):1-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   73 citations  
  • Representation Recovers Information.Chris Thornton - 2009 - Cognitive Science 33 (8):1383-1412.
    Early agreement within cognitive science on the topic of representation has now given way to a combination of positions. Some question the significance of representation in cognition. Others continue to argue in favor, but the case has not been demonstrated in any formal way. The present paper sets out a framework in which the value of representation use can be mathematically measured, albeit in a broadly sensory context rather than a specifically cognitive one. Key to the approach is the use (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations