Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Inventing the Scientific Revolution.James A. Secord - 2023 - Isis 114 (1):50-76.
    As a master narrative for understanding the emergence of the modern world, the concept of a seventeenth-century scientific revolution has been central to the history of science. It is generally believed that this key analytical framework was created in Europe and became widely used for the first time during the Cold War through the writings of Herbert Butterfield and Alexander Koyré. This view, however, is mistaken. The scientific revolution is largely a product of debates about social reconstruction in the United (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • We Have Never Been Whiggish (About Phlogiston)1.Hasok Chang - 2009 - Centaurus 51 (4):239-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Always or Never: Two Approaches to Ceteris Paribus. [REVIEW]Toni Vogel Carey - 2012 - Erkenntnis 77 (3):317-333.
    The Scientific Revolution spawned not just one methodology, but two. We have emphasized Bacon's inductivism at the expense of Galileo's more abstract, sophisticated method of successive approximation, and so have failed to appreciate Galileo's contribution to the ceteris paribus problem in philosophy of science. My purpose here is to help redress this imbalance. I first briefly review the old unsolved problems, and then point out the Baconian basis of ceteris paribus, as this clause is conventionally understood, and its history from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science and religion: Seeking a common horizon.Frank E. Budenholzer - 1984 - Zygon 19 (3):351-368.
    The thought of Bernard Lonergan provides an epistemological position that is both true to the exigencies of modern science and yet open to the possibility of God and revealed religion. In this paper I outline Lonergan's “transcendental method,” which describes the basic pattern of operations involved in any act of human knowing, and discuss how Lonergan uses this cognitional theory as a basis for an epistemological position of critical realism. Then I explain how his approach handles some philosophical problems raised (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Modelling the history of early modern natural philosophy: the fate of the art-nature distinction in the Dutch universities.Andrea Sangiacomo - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (1):46-74.
    The ‘model approach’ facilitates a quantitative-oriented study of conceptual changes in large corpora. This paper implements the ‘model approach’ to investigate the erosion of the traditional art-nature distinction in early modern natural philosophy. I argue that a condition for this transformation has to be located in the late scholastic conception of final causation. I design a conceptual model to capture the art-nature distinction and formulate a working hypothesis about its early modern fate. I test my hypothesis on a selected corpus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Science, Tradition, and the Science of Tradition.Joseph Mali - 1989 - Science in Context 3 (1):143-173.
    The ArgumentScience consists in progress by innovation. Scientists, however, are committed to all kinds of traditions that persist or recur in society regardless of intellectual and institutional changes. Merton's thesis about the origins of the scientific revolution in seventeenth-century England offers a sociohistorical confirmation of this revisionist view: the emergence of a highly rational scientific method out of the religious-ethical sentiments of the English Puritans implies that scientific knowledge does indeed grow out of – and not really against – customary (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Popper and the 7th Approximation: The Problem of Taxonomy.Bennison Gray - 1980 - Dialectica 34 (2):129-154.
    SummaryThe conspicuous role of taxonomy and debates about taxonomy in the well‐established physical science of pedology throws into question the Popperian rejection of definition and classification.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Experiment in Cartesian Courses: The Case of Professor Burchard de Volder.Tammy Nyden - 2010 - The Circulation of Science and Technology.
    In 1675, Burchard de Volder became the first university physics professor to introduce the demonstration of experiments into his lectures and to create a special university classroom, The Leiden Physics Theatre, for this specific purpose. This is surprising for two reasons: first, early pre-Newtonian experiment is commonly associated with Italy and England, and second, de Volder is committed to Cartesian philosophy, including the view that knowledge gathered through the senses is subject to doubt, while that deducted from first principles is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Facts, Concepts, and Theories: The Shape of Psychology's Epistemic Triangle.Armando Machado, Orlando Lourenço & Francisco J. Silva - 2000 - Behavior and Philosophy 28 (1/2):1 - 40.
    In this essay we introduce the idea of an epistemic triangle, with factual, theoretical, and conceptual investigations at its vertices, and argue that whereas scientific progress requires a balance among the three types of investigations, psychology's epistemic triangle is stretched disproportionately in the direction of factual investigations. Expressed by a variety of different problems, this unbalance may be created by a main operative theme—the obsession of psychology with a narrow and mechanical view of the scientific method and a misguided aversion (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Going Public: Good Scientific Conduct.Gitte Meyer & Peter Sandøe - 2012 - Science and Engineering Ethics 18 (2):173-197.
    The paper addresses issues of scientific conduct regarding relations between science and the media, relations between scientists and journalists, and attitudes towards the public at large. In the large and increasing body of literature on scientific conduct and misconduct, these issues seem underexposed as ethical challenges. Consequently, individual scientists here tend to be left alone with problems and dilemmas, with no guidance for good conduct. Ideas are presented about how to make up for this omission. Using a practical, ethical approach, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • History, origin myth and ideology: 'Discovery of social psychology.Franz Samelson - 1974 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 4 (2):217–232.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Computational models and empirical constraints.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (1):98-128.
    It is argued that the traditional distinction between artificial intelligence and cognitive simulation amounts to little more than a difference in style of research - a different ordering in goal priorities and different methodological allegiances. Both enterprises are constrained by empirical considerations and both are directed at understanding classes of tasks that are defined by essentially psychological criteria. Because of the different ordering of priorities, however, they occasionally take somewhat different stands on such issues as the power/generality trade-off and on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   96 citations  
  • Sociology and common sense.David Thomas - 1978 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 21 (1-4):1 – 32.
    After a definition of ?common sense? it is argued that sociology and common sense both do and ought to interact with one another. Four positions on the sociology?common sense relation in the light of the interaction thesis are then critically discussed: sociology must break with common sense; sociology must be based on common sense; sociology and common sense are incomparable; and sociology and common sense are identical. The first two of these positions are further sub?divided in terms of whether the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quark quantum numbers and the problem of microphysical observation.K. S. Shrader-Frechette - 1982 - Synthese 50 (1):125 - 145.
    The main question addressed in this essay is whether quarks have been observed in any sense and, if so, what might be meant by this use of the term, observation. In the first (or introductory) section of the paper, I explain that well-known researchers are divided on the answers to these important questions. In the second section, I investigate microphysical observation in general. Here I argue that Wilson's analogy between observation by means of high-energy accelerators and observation by means of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why not science for anarchists too? A reply to Feyerabend.Arne Naess - 1975 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 18 (2):183 – 194.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • An Approach to the History of Early Astronomy.Robert Palter - 1970 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 1 (2):93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Essay Review: The Chemistry of History: The Development of Modern Chemistry: A History of ChemistryThe Development of Modern Chemistry. IhdeAaron J. . Pp. xii + 851. £4. A History of Chemistry. Volume iv.PartingtonJ. R. . Pp. xxxii + 1007. £10 10s.A. W. Thackray - 1966 - History of Science 5 (1):124-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Newtonian in mind but Aristotelian at heart.Maurice G. Ebison - 1993 - Science & Education 2 (4):345-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Descartes, the Sceptics, and the Rejection of Vitalism in Seventeenth-Century Physiology.Phillip R. Sloan - 1977 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 8 (1):1.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Old McDonald’s Had a Farm: The Metaphysics of Factory Farming.Drew Leder - 2012 - Journal of Animal Ethics 2 (1):73-86.
    This article explores the cultural and philosophical foundations of factory farming. Modes of capitalist production play a role: Marx’s analysis of the fourfold alienation of labor can be applied to animal-laborers. However, the harshness with which animals are treated exceeds the harshness directed toward human workers. At root is a cultural anthropocentrism that prohibits viewing animals as moral subjects, removing ethical restraints. Ultimately, the modernist ways in which animals are treated as both like and unlike human workers are related to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The methods of natural inquiry during the sixteenth-century: Bartolomeo Maranta and Ferrante Imperato.José Ricardo Sánchez Baudoin - unknown
    The present dissertation focuses on the examination of the methods of natural inquiry during the sixteenth-century. The historico-epistemological analysis of the different methodologies, which naturalists used to read the book of nature, shows that natural history, medicine, and alchemy were closely interconnected during the sixteenth-century. How did the naturalist thinkers justify and validate their knowledge? The present dissertation answers this question by means of two relevant historical examples of the pharmaceutical domain: Maranta’s theriac and Imperato’s philosophical medicine. They both show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A History of Universalism: Conceptions of the Internationality of Science from the Enlightenment to the Cold War. [REVIEW]Geert J. Somsen - 2008 - Minerva 46 (3):361-379.
    That science is fundamentally universal has been proclaimed innumerable times. But the precise geographical meaning of this universality has changed historically. This article examines conceptions of scientific internationalism from the Enlightenment to the Cold War, and their varying relations to cosmopolitanism, nationalism, socialism, and ‘the West’. These views are confronted with recent tendencies to cast science as a uniquely European product.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • (2 other versions)Essay Review: What is the History of Science Really Like?, Science: A Four Thousand Year HistoryScience: A Four Thousand Year History. FaraPatricia . Pp. xii + 408. £20. ISBN 978-0-19-922689-4.Iwan Rhys Morus - 2009 - History of Science 47 (3):359-366.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Confirmation of Black's Theory of Lime.Patrick Maher - 1999 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (2):335-353.
    In 1756 Joseph Black published a new theory of the nature of lime, one that is now viewed as essentially correct. Black's theory was not immediately accepted, and a competing theory, published in 1764 by Johann Meyer, was widely preferred to Black's for some years. In this paper, probability theory is used to show that, and why, some of Black's evidence made his theory more probable than Meyer's.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Essay review-science: A four thousand year history, by Patricia Fara.Iwan Rhys Morus - 2009 - History of Science 47 (3):359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Duhem and the origins of statics: Ramifications of the crisis of 1903–04.R. N. D. Martin - 1990 - Synthese 83 (3):337 - 355.
    Much speculation on the sources of Duhem's historical interests fails to account for the major shifts in these interests: neither his belief in the continuous development of physics nor his Catholicism, when his Church was encouraging the study of generally Aristotelian scholastic thought, led to any interest in mediaeval science before 1904. Equally, his own claim that he was merely testing his views on the nature of physical theory is easily squared only with earlier work with no trace of mediaeval (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Status of Brain in the Concept of Mind.Henry Cohen - 1952 - Philosophy 27 (102):195 - 210.
    It is with no feigned modesty that I acknowledge, as a limited and superficial student of philosophy, the honour you have done me by your invitation to deliver the Manson Lecture. But if the honour is undeserved, it is by fortuitous circumstance the more appreciated. Dr. Manson was a family doctor in Warrington, Lancs., with whom I was privileged to have close professional associations. He was a man of many parts who regarded the isolation of medicine from philosophy as an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation