Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Informed Consent: What Must Be Disclosed and What Must Be Understood?Joseph Millum & Danielle Bromwich - 2021 - American Journal of Bioethics 21 (5):46-58.
    Over the last few decades, multiple studies have examined the understanding of participants in clinical research. They show variable and often poor understanding of key elements of disclosure, such as expected risks and the experimental nature of treatments. Did the participants in these studies give valid consent? According to the standard view of informed consent they did not. The standard view holds that the recipient of consent has a duty to disclose certain information to the profferer of consent because valid (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Paternalistic persuasion: are doctors paternalistic when persuading patients, and how does persuasion differ from convincing and recommending?Anniken Fleisje - 2023 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 26 (2):257-269.
    In contemporary paternalism literature, persuasion is commonly not considered paternalistic. Moreover, paternalism is typically understood to be problematic either because it is seen as coercive, or because of the insult of the paternalist considering herself superior. In this paper, I argue that doctors who persuade patients act paternalistically. Specifically, I argue that trying to persuade a patient (here understood as aiming for the patient to consent to a certain treatment, although he prefers not to) should be differentiated from trying to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Informed Consent Under Ignorance.Daniel Villiger - forthcoming - American Journal of Bioethics:1-13.
    In recent years, an old challenge to informed consent has been rediscovered: the challenge of ignorance. Several authors argue that due to the presence of irreducible ignorance in certain treatments, giving informed consent to these treatments is not possible. The present paper examines in what ways ignorance is believed to prevent informed consent and which treatments are affected by that. At this, it becomes clear that if the challenge of ignorance truly holds, it poses a major problem to informed consent. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge about and attitudes toward medical informed consent: a Lebanese population survey.Mary Deeb, Dana Alameddine, Rasha Abi Radi Abou Jaoudeh, Widian Laoun, Julian Maamari, Rawan Honeini, Alain Khouri, Fadi Abou-Mrad, Nassib Elia & Aniella Abi-Gerges - 2024 - Ethics and Behavior 34 (2):89-103.
    As Medicine shifts from a paternalistic practice to a patient-centered approach, the concept of medical informed consent (IC) has evolved to safeguard patient autonomy. However, its current implementation still presents many challenges in clinical practice. We assessed the knowledge and attitudes of the general Lebanese population regarding the IC process as well as their sociodemographic and medical correlates. An anonymous online survey was distributed to the Lebanese population using social media channels. A sample of 500 adults with an average age (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Education and the Prevention of AIDS.Paul D. Cleary - 1988 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 16 (3-4):267-273.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Unbearable Requirement of Informed Consent.Ellen Wright Clayton - 2019 - American Journal of Bioethics 19 (5):19-20.
    In the spirit of full disclosure, I have been a member of the Delphi panels discussed in this article (Beskow and Weinfurt 2019) since their inception and was one of the people who was recently int...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Complex Relationship of Genetics, Groups, and Health: What It Means for Public Health.Ellen Wright Clayton - 2002 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 30 (2):290-297.
    Genetics offers real opportunities for public health actors. Increased understanding of genetics will illuminate some of the factors that affect disease and, in many cases, will lead to more effective treatments. The recognition that phenylketonuria was caused by a metabolic defect that led to the accumulation of toxic levels of phenylalanine, an elevation that could largely be averted by adopting a low-phenylalanine diet, is an early example. Some cases of what was thought to be Sudden Infant Death Syndrome, a diagnosis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Complex Relationship of Genetics, Groups, and Health: What it Means for Public Health.Ellen Wright Clayton - 2002 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 30 (2):290-297.
    Genetics offers real opportunities for public health actors. Increased understanding of genetics will illuminate some of the factors that affect disease and, in many cases, will lead to more effective treatments. The recognition that phenylketonuria was caused by a metabolic defect that led to the accumulation of toxic levels of phenylalanine, an elevation that could largely be averted by adopting a low-phenylalanine diet, is an early example. Some cases of what was thought to be Sudden Infant Death Syndrome, a diagnosis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Genetic Research as Therapy: Implications of “Gene Therapy” for Informed Consent.Larry R. Churchill, Myra L. Collins, Nancy M. P. King, Stephen G. Pemberton & Keith A. Wailoo - 1998 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 26 (1):38-47.
    In March 1996, the General Accounting Office issued the report Scientific Research: Continued Vigilance Critical to Protecting Human Subjects. It stated that “an inherent conflict of interest exists when physician-researchers include their patients in research protocols. If the physicians do not clearly distinguish between research and treatment in their attempt to inform subjects, the possible benefits of a study can be overemphasized and the risks minimized.” The report also acknowledged that “the line between research and treatment is not always clear (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Genetic Research as Therapy: Implications of "Gene Therapy" for Informed Consent.Larry R. Churchill, Myra L. Collins, Nancy M. R. King, Stephen G. Pemberton & Keith A. Wailoo - 1998 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 26 (1):38-47.
    In March 1996, the General Accounting Office (GAO) issued the reportScientific Research: Continued Vigilance Critical to Protecting Human Subjects.It stated that “an inherent conflict of interest exists when physician-researchers include their patients in research protocols. If the physicians do not clearly distinguish between research and treatment in their attempt to inform subjects, the possible benefits of a study can be overemphasized and the risks minimized.” The report also acknowledged that “the line between research and treatment is not always cleartoclinicians. Controversy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Common Morality Principles in Biomedical Ethics: Responses to Critics.James F. Childress & Tom L. Beauchamp - 2022 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 31 (2):164-176.
    After briefly sketching common-morality principlism, as presented in Principles of Biomedical Ethics, this paper responds to two recent sets of challenges to this framework. The first challenge claims that medical ethics is autonomous and unique and thus not a form of, or justified or guided by, a common morality or by any external morality or moral theory. The second challenge denies that there is a common morality and insists that futile efforts to develop common-morality approaches to bioethics limit diversity and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Respect for personhood: Concrete implications of a philosophical misunderstanding.Karel-Bart Celie & John J. Paris - 2019 - Clinical Ethics 14 (3):146-150.
    Intentionally or not, our clinical practice is informed by our philosophical premises. A subtle misunderstanding can have frequent, though insidious, implications in day-to-day clinical encounters....
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Where Did Informed Consent for Research Come From?Alexander Morgan Capron - 2018 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 46 (1):12-29.
    To understand the future of informed consent, we should pay attention to two ethical-legal sources in addition to the revised Common Rule. Physicians acting as investigators and patients serving as research subjects bring to that relationship a long history regarding consent to treatment, and everyone dealing with research ethics needs to be aware of the Nuremberg Code and other human-rights documents. These three streams make separate and distinctly different contributions to informed consent doctrine.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Teaching the virtues: justifications and recommendations.Candace C. Gauthier - 1997 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 6 (3):339-.
    The current interest in and discussion of virtue ethics suggests that this approach to moral decisionmaking has several distinct advantages as applied to ethical issues in healthcare delivery. For the most part, calls to incorporate the virtues of the healthcare provider in discussions of these issues have sought to supplement rather than totally replace traditional ethical theories, such as the utilitarian focus on maximizing the best overall consequences and the Kantian concern to act on the duty of respect for persons. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mandatory Disclosure and Medical Paternalism.Emma C. Bullock - 2016 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 19 (2):409-424.
    Medical practitioners are duty-bound to tell their patients the truth about their medical conditions, along with the risks and benefits of proposed treatments. Some patients, however, would rather not receive medical information. A recent response to this tension has been to argue that that the disclosure of medical information is not optional. As such, patients do not have permission to refuse medical information. In this paper I argue that, depending on the context, the disclosure of medical information can undermine the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Silent Decisions: Limits of Consent and the Terminally III Patient.Troyen A. Brennan - 1988 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 16 (3-4):204-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Paths to Reducing Medical Injury: Professional Liability and Discipline vs. Patient Safety ? and the Need for a Third Way.Randall R. Bovbjerg, Robert H. Miller & David W. Shapiro - 2001 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 29 (3-4):369-380.
    Too many patients are injured in the course of care. Clinicians may mistakenly cause new harm to a patient or fail to take established steps to improve the presenting condition. Medical institutions within which they work may lack mechanisms to reduce errors or prevent them from harming patients. Many, perhaps even most, injuries are preventable, probably numbering in the hundreds of thousands a year for hospital care alone. Long ignored by medical practitioners and health-care payers and little appreciated by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Paths to Reducing Medical Injury: Professional Liability and Discipline vs. Patient Safety — And the Need for a Third Way.Randall R. Bovbjerg, Robert H. Miller & David W. Shapiro - 2001 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 29 (3-4):369-380.
    Too many patients are injured in the course of care. Clinicians may mistakenly cause new harm to a patient or fail to take established steps to improve the presenting condition. Medical institutions within which they work may lack mechanisms to reduce errors or prevent them from harming patients. Many, perhaps even most, injuries are preventable, probably numbering in the hundreds of thousands a year for hospital care alone. Long ignored by medical practitioners and health-care payers and little appreciated by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Liability Reform Should Make Patients Safer: “Avoidable Classes of Events” are a Key Improvement.Randall R. Bovbjerg & Laurence R. Tancredi - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):478-500.
    Too many patients are injured in the course of medical care. This truth is as distressing now as it was four years ago when it began an article in this journal’s last similar symposium. Many or most injuries seem preventable. Yet today’s systems of care and of oversight of care too often fail to prevent them, despite generations of increasing legal intervention. Few injuries are litigated, even fewer addressed through medical peer review or state disciplinary authorities. The Institute of Medicine’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Liability Reform Should Make Patients Safer: "Avoidable Classes of Events" are a Key Improvement.Randall R. Bovbjerg & Laurence R. Tancredi - 2005 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 33 (3):478-500.
    Too many patients are injured in the course of medical care. This truth is as distressing now as it was four years ago when it began an article in this journal’s last similar symposium. Many or most injuries seem preventable. Yet today’s systems of care and of oversight of care too often fail to prevent them, despite generations of increasing legal intervention. Few injuries are litigated, even fewer addressed through medical peer review or state disciplinary authorities. The Institute of Medicine’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • When slippery slope arguments miss the mark: a lesson from one against physician-assisted death.Eric Blackstone & Stuart J. Youngner - 2018 - Journal of Medical Ethics 44 (10):657-660.
    In 1989, Susan Wolf convincingly warned of a troublesome consequence that should discourage any movement in American society towards physician-assisted death—a legal backlash against the gains made for limiting life-sustaining treatment. The authors demonstrate that this dire consequence did not come to pass. As physician-assisted suicide gains a foothold in USA and elsewhere, many other slippery slope arguments are being put forward. Although many of these speculations should be taken seriously, they do not justify halting the new practice. Instead, our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Three stages in the lifecycle of bioethics: Observations on "bioethics as Co-PI".Roberta M. Berry - 2005 - American Journal of Bioethics 5 (6):30 – 32.
    S. Matthew Liao's paper (2005) exemplifies what I characterize as the third stage in the lifecycle of bioethics, “bioethics as co-PI,” in which bioethics asserts a role in directing the biomedical...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Response to Commentaries.Tom L. Beauchamp & James F. Childress - 2020 - Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 45 (4-5):560-579.
    After expressing our gratitude to the commentators for their valuable analyses and assessments of Principles of Biomedical Ethics, we respond to several particular critiques raised by the commentators under the following rubrics: the compatibility of different sets of principles and rules; challenges to the principle of respect for autonomy; connecting principles to cases and resolving their conflicts; the value of and compatibility of virtues and principles; common morality theory; and moral status. We point to areas where we see common agreement (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Informed Consent: Its History, Meaning, and Present Challenges.Tom L. Beauchamp - 2011 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 20 (4):515-523.
    The practice of obtaining informed consent has its history in, and gains its meaning from, medicine and biomedical research. Discussions of disclosure and justified nondisclosure have played a significant role throughout the history of medical ethics, but the term “informed consent” emerged only in the 1950s. Serious discussion of the meaning and ethics of informed consent began in medicine, research, law, and philosophy only around 1972.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Vulnerability and Trustworthiness.David Barnard - 2016 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 25 (2):288-300.
    :Although recent literature on professionalism in healthcare abounds in recommended character traits, attitudes, or behaviors, with a few exceptions, the recommendations are untethered to any serious consideration of the contours and ethical demands of the healing relationship. This article offers an approach based on the professional’s commitment to trustworthiness in response to the vulnerability of those seeking professional help. Because our willingness and ability to trust health professionals or healthcare institutions are affected by our personality, culture, race, age, prior experiences (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The story of the body and the story of the person: Towards an ethics of representing human bodies and body-parts.Y. Michael Barilan - 2004 - Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 8 (2):193-205.
    Western culture has a few traditions of representing the human body – among them mortuary art (gisants), the freak show, the culture of the relics, renaissance art and pre-modern and modern anatomy. A historical analysis in the spirit of Norbert Elias is offered with regard to body – person relationship in anatomy. Modern anatomy is characterized by separating the story of the person from the story of the body, a strategy that is incompatible with the bio-psycho-social paradigm of clinical medicine. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Clinical Use of Placebos: Still the Physician's Prerogative?Anne Barnhill - 2012 - Hastings Center Report 42 (3):29-37.
    The American Medical Association's Code of Ethics prohibits physicians from giving substances they believe are placebos to their patients unless the patient is informed of and agrees to use of the substance. Various questions surround the AMA policy, however. One of these has to do with what should be disclosed. The AMA holds that any treatment that the physician believes is a placebo should be identified as such to the patient. But consider a more restrictive policy that requires physicians to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophers' Invasion of Clinical Ethics: Historical and Personal Reflections.Robert Baker - 2018 - American Journal of Bioethics 18 (6):51-54.
    When laypeople learned what decisions physicians were making about laypeople's health they were often appalled. … They discovered that physicians … were making controversial moral moves, choices th...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Ethics and Governance of Medical Research: What does regulation have to do with morality?Richard Ashcroft - 2003 - New Review of Bioethics 1 (1):41-58.
    (2003). The Ethics and Governance of Medical Research: What does regulation have to do with morality? New Review of Bioethics: Vol. 1, No. 1, pp. 41-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Made in the U.S.A.: Legal and Ethical Issues in Artificial Heart Experimentation.George J. Annas - 1986 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 14 (3-4):164-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Informed Consent: Charade or Choice?George J. Annas - 2017 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 45 (1):10-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Relationship Between Uncertainty and Affect.Eric C. Anderson, R. Nicholas Carleton, Michael Diefenbach & Paul K. J. Han - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 10:469966.
    Uncertainty and affect are fundamental and interrelated aspects of the human condition. Uncertainty is often associated with negative affect, but in some circumstances it is associated with positive affect. In this paper, we review different explanations for the varying relationship between uncertainty and affect. We identify “mental simulation” as a key process that links uncertainty to affective states. We suggest that people have a propensity to simulate negative outcomes, which results in a propensity towards negative affective responses to uncertainty. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A feminist model for women's health care.Linda Andrist - 1997 - Nursing Inquiry 4 (4):268-274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Past, Present, and Future of Informed Consent in Research and Translational Medicine.Susan M. Wolf, Ellen Wright Clayton & Frances Lawrenz - 2018 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 46 (1):7-11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Surgeons, Intensivists, and Discretion to Refuse Requested Treatments.Mark R. Wicclair & Douglas B. White - 2014 - Hastings Center Report 44 (5):33-42.
    Physicians are expected to engage patients as partners in identifying the possible benefits and harms associated with treatment options and selecting from among medically appropriate treatment options, rather than simply dictating what treatments patients will and will not receive. This collaborative model reflects the recognition that citizens in multicultural societies have diverse values and are likely to have different views about whether the possible benefits of a medical intervention outweigh the possible harms. However, there are circumstances in which the collaborative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Responses to Open Peer Commentaries on "Physicians' Silent Decisions: Because Patient Autonomy Doesn't Always Come First".Simon N. Whitney & Laurence B. McCullough - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (7):1-3.
    Physicians make some medical decisions without disclosure to their patients. Nondisclosure is possible because these are silent decisions to refrain from screening, diagnostic or therapeutic interventions. Nondisclosure is ethically permissible when the usual presumption that the patient should be involved in decisions is defeated by considerations of clinical utility or patient emotional and physical well-being. Some silent decisions—not all—are ethically justified by this standard. Justified silent decisions are typically dependent on the physician's professional judgment, experience and knowledge, and are not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Placebos in Clinical Practice and the Power of Suggestion.Anthony Vernillo - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):32-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Medical Record Confidentiality Law, Scientific Research, and Data Collection in the Information Age.Richard C. Turkington - 1997 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 25 (2-3):113-129.
    A powerful movement is afoot to create a national computerized system of health records. Advocates claim it could save the health delivery system billions of dollars and improve the quality of health services. According to Lawrence Gostin, a leading commentator on privacy and health records, this new infrastructure is “already under way and [has] an aura of inevitability.” When it is in place, almost any information that is viewed as relevant to a decision in the health care delivery system would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Medical Record Confidentiality Law, Scientific Research, and Data Collection in the Information Age.Richard C. Turkington - 1997 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 25 (2-3):113-129.
    A powerful movement is afoot to create a national computerized system of health records. Advocates claim it could save the health delivery system billions of dollars and improve the quality of health services. According to Lawrence Gostin, a leading commentator on privacy and health records, this new infrastructure is “already under way and [has] an aura of inevitability.” When it is in place, almost any information that is viewed as relevant to a decision in the health care delivery system would (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The First Amendment and Physician Speech in Reproductive Decision Making.Sonia M. Suter - 2015 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 43 (1):22-34.
    Courts are divided as to whether abortion informed consent mandates violate the First Amendment. This article argues that given the doctor's and patient's unique expertise, the patient's strong interests in autonomous decision making, and the fact that these laws regulate speech, rather than conduct, heighted or strict scrutiny should apply to such mandates.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Trust, Risk, and Race in American Medicine.Laura Specker Sullivan - 2020 - Hastings Center Report 50 (1):18-26.
    Trust is a core feature of the physician-patient relationship, and risk is central to trust. Patients take risks when they trust their providers to care for them effectively and appropriately. Not all patients take these risks: some medical relationships are marked by mistrust and suspicion. Empirical evidence suggests that some patients and families of color in the United States may be more likely to mistrust their providers and to be suspicious of specific medical practices and institutions. Given both historical and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Relational Autonomy, Paternalism, and Maternalism.Laura Specker Sullivan & Fay Niker - 2018 - Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21 (3):649-667.
    The concept of paternalism is intricately tied to the concept of autonomy. It is commonly assumed that when paternalistic interventions are wrong, they are wrong because they impede individuals’ autonomy. Our aim in this paper is to show that the recent shift towards conceiving of autonomy relationally highlights a separate conceptual space for a nonpaternalistic kind of interpersonal intervention termed maternalism. We argue that maternalism makes a twofold contribution to the debate over the ethics of interpersonal action and decision-making. Descriptively, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Views of clinical trial participants on the readability and their understanding of informed consent documents.Rita Sommers, Cornelius Van Staden & Francois Steffens - 2017 - AJOB Empirical Bioethics 8 (4):277-284.
    Background: One of the ethical imperatives for a valid consent process in clinical medication trials is that the process be guided by and recorded in an informed consent document (ICD). Concerns have been expressed, however, about readability and participant understanding of ICDs, which are often 10–20 pages long. Objective measures of readability and understanding have been used to support these concerns in several articles, but surprisingly the voice of trial participants on ICDs has not been heard in previous studies. Hence, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • "Should the Grandparents Die?": Allocation of Medical Resources with an Aging Population.Margaret A. Somerville - 1986 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 14 (3-4):158-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Autonomy and Paternalism in Health Policy: Currents in Contemporary Bioethics.Mark A. Rothstein - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (4):590-594.
    In the United States the delivery of health care traditionally has been hierarchical and strictly controlled by physicians. Physicians typically provided patients with little information about their diagnosis, prognosis, and treatment plan; patients were expected to follow their physicians’ orders and ask no questions. Beginning in the 1970s, with the widespread adoption of the doctrine of informed consent to treatment, the physician-patient relationship began to be more collaborative, although the extent of the change has been subject to debate. At a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Autonomy and Paternalism in Health Policy: Currents in Contemporary Bioethics.Mark A. Rothstein - 2014 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 42 (4):590-594.
    In the United States the delivery of health care traditionally has been hierarchical and strictly controlled by physicians. Physicians typically provided patients with little information about their diagnosis, prognosis, and treatment plan; patients were expected to follow their physicians’ orders and ask no questions. Beginning in the 1970s, with the widespread adoption of the doctrine of informed consent to treatment, the physician-patient relationship began to be more collaborative, although the extent of the change has been subject to debate. At a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Genetic Exceptionalism vs. Paradigm Shift: Lessons from HIV.Lainie Friedman Ross - 2001 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 29 (2):141-148.
    The term “exceptionalism” was introduced into health care in 1991 when Bayer described “HIV exceptionalism” as the policy of treating the human immunodeficiency virus different from other infectious diseases, particularly other sexually transmitted diseases. It was reflected in the following practices: pre- and post-HIV test counseling, the development of specific separate consent forms for HIV testing, and stringent requirements for confidentiality of HIV test results. The justification for these practices was the belief that testing was essential for prevention and that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Genetic Exceptionalism vs. Paradigm Shift: Lessons from HIV.Lainie Friedman Ross - 2001 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 29 (2):141-148.
    The term “exceptionalism” was introduced into health care in 1991 when Bayer described “HIV exceptionalism” as the policy of treating the human immunodeficiency virus different from other infectious diseases, particularly other sexually transmitted diseases. It was reflected in the following practices: pre- and post-HIV test counseling, the development of specific separate consent forms for HIV testing, and stringent requirements for confidentiality of HIV test results. The justification for these practices was the belief that testing was essential for prevention and that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Fragility, uncertainty, and healthcare.Wendy A. Rogers & Mary J. Walker - 2016 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 37 (1):71-83.
    Medicine seeks to overcome one of the most fundamental fragilities of being human, the fragility of good health. No matter how robust our current state of health, we are inevitably susceptible to future illness and disease, while current disease serves to remind us of various frailties inherent in the human condition. This article examines the relationship between fragility and uncertainty with regard to health, and argues that there are reasons to accept rather than deny at least some forms of uncertainty. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Metamorphosis of Managed Care: Implications for Health Reform Internationally.Marc A. Rodwin - 2010 - Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 38 (2):352-364.
    Many writers suggest that managed care had a brief life and that we are now in a post-managed care era. Yet managed care has had a long history and continues to thrive. Writers also often assume that managed care is a fixed entity, or focus on its tools, rather than the context in which it operates and the functions it performs. They overlook that managed care has evolved and neglect to examine the role that it plays in the health system.This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark