Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Experiential Blink: mapping the cost of working memory encoding onto conscious perception in the attentional blink.Hannah Pincham, Howard Bowman & Szucs Denes - unknown
    The attentional blink (AB) represents a cognitive deficit in reporting the second of two targets (T2), when that second target appears 200-600 msec after the first (T1). However, it is unclear how this paradigm impacts the subjective visibility (that is, the conscious perception) of T2, and whether the temporal profile of T2 report accuracy matches the temporal profile of subjective visibility. In order to compare report accuracy and subjective visibility, we asked participants to identify T1 and T2, and to rate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Are subliminal mere exposure effects a form of implicit learning?Robert F. Bornstein - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Awareness and abstraction are graded dimensions.Axel Cleeremans - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):402-403.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Measuring consciousness: Task accuracy and awareness as sigmoid functions of stimulus duration.Kristian Sandberg, Bo Martin Bibby, Bert Timmermans, Axel Cleeremans & Morten Overgaard - 2011 - Consciousness and Cognition 20 (4):1659-1675.
    When consciousness is examined using subjective ratings, the extent to which processing is conscious or unconscious is often estimated by calculating task performance at the subjective threshold or by calculating the correlation between accuracy and awareness. However, both these methods have certain limitations. In the present article, we propose describing task accuracy and awareness as functions of stimulus intensity as suggested by Koch and Preuschoff . The estimated lag between the curves describes how much stimulus intensity must increase for awareness (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • How should implicit learning be characterized?David R. Shanks & Mark F. St John - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):427-447.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness: Limited but consequential.Timothy D. Wilson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):701-701.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is consciousness information processing?Raymond Klein - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):683-683.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Developing concepts of consciousness.Aaron Sloman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):694-695.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Limits of preconscious processing.Albrecht Werner Inhoff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):680-681.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Velmans's overfocused perspective on consciousness.Marcel Kinsbourne - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):682-683.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What do you mean by conscious?John Morton - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):43-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against semantic preprocessing in parafoveal vision.Keith Rayner - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):46-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The psychophysics of subliminal perception.Neil A. Macmillan - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Priming without awareness: What was all the fuss about?Keith E. Stanovich & Dean G. Purcell - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):47-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Subjective discriminability of invisibility: A framework for distinguishing perceptual and attentional failures of awareness.Ryota Kanai, Vincent Walsh & Chia-Huei Tseng - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (4):1045-1057.
    Conscious visual perception can fail in many circumstances. However, little is known about the causes and processes leading to failures of visual awareness. In this study, we introduce a new signal detection measure termed subjective discriminability of invisibility that allows one to distinguish between subjective blindness due to reduction of sensory signals or to lack of attentional access to sensory signals. The SDI is computed based upon subjective confidence in reporting the absence of a target . Using this new measure, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Very brief exposure: The effects of unreportable stimuli on fearful behavior.Paul Siegel & Joel Weinberger - 2009 - Consciousness and Cognition 18 (4):939-951.
    A series of experiments tested the hypothesis that very brief exposure to feared stimuli can have positive effects on avoidance of the corresponding feared object. Participants identified themselves as fearful of spiders through a widely used questionnaire. A preliminary experiment showed that they were unable to identify the stimuli used in the main experiments. Experiment 2 compared the effects of exposure to masked feared stimuli at short and long stimulus onset asynchronies . Participants were individually administered one of three continuous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Apperception revisited: ?Subliminal? monocular perception during the apperception of fused random-dot stereograms.R. KunzendoRf - 1992 - Consciousness and Cognition 1 (1):63-76.
    “Source monitoring” theory is applied to the turn-of-the-century argument that, whenever binocularly fused patterns are self-consciously apperceived, both eyes' monocular sensations are consciously perceived. According to monitoring theory's refinement of the argument, binocularly apperceived patterns are accompanied by selfconsciousness that one is perceiving patterns , whereas monocular sensations are accompanied by no self-consciousness of their source. In the current test of this refined argument, 32 subjects were monocularly presented with 6 letters of the alphabet, while binocularly fusing 6 different letters, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Subjective measures of unconscious knowledge of concepts.Eleni Ziori & Zoltán Dienes - 2006 - Mind and Society 5 (1):105-122.
    This paper considers different subjective measures of conscious and unconscious knowledge in a concept formation paradigm. In particular, free verbal reports are compared with two subjective measures, the zero-correlation and the guessing criteria, based on trial-by-trial confidence ratings (a type of on-line verbal report). Despite the fact that free verbal reports are frequently dismissed as being insensitive measures of conscious knowledge, a considerable bulk of research on implicit learning has traditionally relied on this measure of consciousness, because it is widely (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Can false memory for critical lures occur without conscious awareness of list words?Daniel D. Sadler, Sharon M. Sodmont & Lucas A. Keefer - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 58:136-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Visibility Is Not Equivalent to Confidence in a Low Contrast Orientation Discrimination Task.Manuel Rausch & Michael Zehetleitner - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Reversed Priming Effects May Be Driven by Misperception Rather than Subliminal Processing.Anders Sand - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Interocular suppression prevents interference in a flanker task.Qiong Wu, Jonathan T. H. Lo Voi, Thomas Y. Lee, Melissa-Ann Mackie, Yanhong Wu & Jin Fan - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:152768.
    Executive control of attention refers to processes that detect and resolve conflict among competing thoughts and actions. Despite the high-level nature of this faculty, the role of awareness in executive control of attention is not well understood. In this study, we used interocular suppression to mask the flankers in an arrow flanker task, in which the flankers and the target arrow were presented simultaneously in order to elicit executive control of attention. Participants were unable to detect the flanker arrows or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Visual statistical learning in children and young adults: how implicit?Julie Bertels, Emeline Boursain, Arnaud Destrebecqz & Vinciane Gaillard - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A review of the literature with and without awareness. [REVIEW]George Wolford - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • No conscious or co-conscious?Graham F. Wagstaff - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):700-700.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Facilitation or inhibition from parafoveal words?Geoffrey Underwood - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):48-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Note.Joseph Tzelgov - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 6 (2-3):441-451.
    The relations between automatic processing and consciousness are discussed in this paper. It is argued that automatic processing should not be identified with the absence of consciousness. The organism has access to representations resulting from automatic processing, but these representations, in contrast to the representations resulting from nonautomatic processing, are not propositional. Therefore monitoring of the process, the defining feature of nonautomatic processing, is not possible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Dissociating consciousness from cognition.David Spiegel - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):695-696.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasons for doubting the existence of even epiphenomenal consciousness.Georges Rey - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):691-692.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Isn't the first-person perspective a bad third-person perspective?W. Schaeken & G. D'Ydewalle - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):692-693.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hydrocephalus and “misapplied competence”: Awkward evidence for or against?N. F. Dixon - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):675-676.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Has consciousness a sharp edge?Robert A. M. Gregson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):679-680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A curious coincidence? Consciousness as an object of scientific scrutiny fits our personal experience remarkably well.Bernard J. Baars - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):669-670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Consciousness and content in learning: Missing or misconceived?Richard A. Carlson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):673-674.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of awareness in affective information processing: An exploration of the Zajonc hypothesis.Louis G. Tassinary, Scott P. Orr, George Wolford, Shirley E. Napps & John T. Lanzetta - 1984 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 22 (6):489-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The perception of visual emotion: Comparing different measures of awareness.Remigiusz Szczepanowski, Jakub Traczyk, Michał Wierzchoń & Axel Cleeremans - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (1):212-220.
    Here, we explore the sensitivity of different awareness scales in revealing conscious reports on visual emotion perception. Participants were exposed to a backward masking task involving fearful faces and asked to rate their conscious awareness in perceiving emotion in facial expression using three different subjective measures: confidence ratings , with the conventional taxonomy of certainty, the perceptual awareness scale , through which participants categorize “raw” visual experience, and post-decision wagering , which involves economic categorization. Our results show that the CR (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Implicit learning of mappings between forms and metaphorical meanings.Fengying Li, Xiuyan Guo, Lei Zhu, Zhiliang Yang & Zoltan Dienes - 2013 - Consciousness and Cognition 22 (1):174-183.
    Previous research has shown that people can implicitly acquire mappings between word forms and literal meanings . We argue, from the metaphor-representation and embodiment perspectives, that people can unconsciously establish mappings between word forms and not only literal but also metaphorical meanings. Using Williams’ paradigm, we found that transfer of form-meaning connections from a concrete domain to an abstract domain was achieved in a metaphor-consistent way without awareness. Our results support the view that unconscious knowledge can be flexibly deployed in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The dissociation paradigm and its discontents: How can unconscious perception or memory be inferred?Michael Snodgrass - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (1):107-116.
    Erdelyi does us all a great service by his customarily incisive discussion of the various ways in which our field tends to neglect, confuse, and misunderstand numerous critical issues in attempting to differentiate conscious from unconscious perception and memory. Although no single commentary could hope to comprehensively assess these issues, I will address Erdelyi’s three main points: How the dissociation paradigm can be used to validly infer unconscious perception; The implications of below-chance effects; and The role of time. I suggest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • A lawful first-person psychology involving a causal consciousness: A psychoanalytic solution.Howard Shevrin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):693-694.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Learning strategies and situated knowledge.Antonio Rizzo & Oronzo Parlangeli - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):420-421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Marginally perceptible outcome feedback, motor learning and implicit processes.Rich S. W. Masters, Jon P. Maxwell & Frank F. Eves - 2009 - Consciousness and Cognition 18 (3):639-645.
    Participants struck 500 golf balls to a concealed target. Outcome feedback was presented at the subjective or objective threshold of awareness of each participant or at a supraliminal threshold. Participants who received fully perceptible feedback learned to strike the ball onto the target, as did participants who received feedback that was only marginally perceptible . Participants who received feedback that was not perceptible showed no learning. Upon transfer to a condition in which the target was unconcealed, performance increased in both (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A limitation of the reflex-arc approach to consciousness.J. Steven Reznick & Philip David Zelazo - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):692-692.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unconscious perception: Assumptions and interpretive difficulties.Eyal M. Reingold - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (1):117-122.
    Reingold and MerikleÕs (1988, 1990) critique of the classic dissociation paradigm identified several issues as inherent problems that severely undermine the utility of this paradigm. Erdelyi (2004) extending his prior analysis (Erdelyi, 1985, 1986) points out several additional factors that may complicate the interpretation of empirically obtained dissociations. The goal of the present manuscript is to further discuss some of these commonly neglected interpretive difficulties. Ó 2003 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Integrating unseen events over time.Thomas P. Reber & Katharina Henke - 2012 - Consciousness and Cognition 21 (2):953-960.
    Events often share elements that guide us to integrate knowledge from these events. Integration allows us to make inferences that affect reactions to new events. Integrating events and making inferences are thought to depend on consciousness. We show that even unconsciously experienced events, that share elements, are integrated and influence reactions to new events. An unconscious event consisted of the subliminal presentation of two unrelated words. Half of subliminal word pairs shared one word . Overlapping word pairs were presented between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Evaluative Learning with “Subliminally” Presented Stimuli.Jan de Houwer, Hilde Hendrickx & Frank Baeyens - 1997 - Consciousness and Cognition 6 (1):87-107.
    Evaluative learning refers to the change in the affective evaluation of a previously neutral stimulus that occurs after the stimulus has been associated with a second, positive or negative, affective stimulus . Four experiments are reported in which the AS was presented very briefly. Significant evaluative learning was observed in participants who did not notice the presentation of the affective stimuli or could not discriminate between the briefly presented positive and negative ASi when asked to do so . In two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The pilfering of awareness and guilt by association.Kenneth R. Paap - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):45-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Fringe consciousness in sequence learning: The influence of individual differences.Elisabeth Norman, Mark C. Price & Simon C. Duff - 2006 - Consciousness and Cognition 15 (4):723-760.
    We first describe how the concept of “fringe consciousness” can characterise gradations of consciousness between the extremes of implicit and explicit learning. We then show that the NEO-PI-R personality measure of openness to feelings, chosen to reflect the ability to introspect on fringe feelings, influences both learning and awareness in the serial reaction time task under conditions that have previously been associated with implicit learning . This provides empirical evidence for the proposed phenomenology and functional role of fringe consciousness in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Visual motion disambiguation by a subliminal sound.Andre Dufour, Pascale Touzalin, Michèle Moessinger, Renaud Brochard & Olivier Després - 2008 - Consciousness and Cognition 17 (3):790-797.
    There is growing interest in the effect of sound on visual motion perception. One model involves the illusion created when two identical objects moving towards each other on a two-dimensional visual display can be seen to either bounce off or stream through each other. Previous studies show that the large bias normally seen toward the streaming percept can be modulated by the presentation of an auditory event at the moment of coincidence. However, no reports to date provide sufficient evidence to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Consciousness is a “subjective” state.Philip M. Merikle & Jim Cheesman - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):42-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations