Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Origin of Moral Norms: A Moderate Nativist Account.Jessy Giroux - 2011 - Dialogue 50 (2):281-306.
    RÉSUMÉ: Dans cet article, je distingue deux familles théoriques qui conçoivent les normes morales comme des «intrants» (inputs) ou des «extrants» (outputs). Je soutiens que l’on peut ultimement unifier la meilleure version de ces deux modèles en un seul modèle théorique que je nomme l’Innéisme Modéré. La différence entre ces deux modèles apparemment antagonistes en est une de perspective plutôt que de contenu : alors que le modèle des intrants analyse l’impact de dispositions émotionnelles sur l’évolution historique des normes morales, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Necessity of Mathematics.Juhani Yli‐Vakkuri & John Hawthorne - 2018 - Noûs 52 (3):549-577.
    Some have argued for a division of epistemic labor in which mathematicians supply truths and philosophers supply their necessity. We argue that this is wrong: mathematics is committed to its own necessity. Counterfactuals play a starring role.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A Virtue Semantics.Cheng-Hung Tsai - 2008 - South African Journal of Philosophy 27 (1):27-39.
    In this paper, I propose a virtue-theoretic approach to semantics, according to which the study of linguistic competence in particular, and the study of meaning and language in general, should focus on a speaker's interpretative virtues, such as charity and interpretability, rather than the speaker's knowledge of rules. The first part of the paper proffers an argument for shifting to virtue semantics, and the second part outlines the nature of such virtue semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Languages and idiolects: their language and ours.James Higginbotham - 2006 - In Barry C. Smith (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language. Oxford University Press. pp. 140--50.
    An idiolectal conception of language is compatible with a substantive role for external things — objects, including other people — in the characterization of idiolects. Illustrations of this role are not hard to come by. The point of looking outward from the individual is pretty evident for the case of reference to perceptually encountered objects: had the world been significantly different, a person with the same molecular history would have acquired, and called by the same familiar names, different physical and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Can Internalism and Externalism be Reconciled in a Biological Epistemology of Language?Prakash Mondal - 2012 - Biosemiotics 5 (1):61 - 82.
    This paper is an attempt at exploring the possibility of reconciling the two interpretations of biolinguistics which have been recently projected by Koster(Biolinguistics 3(1):61–92, 2009). The two interpretations—trivial and nontrivial—can be roughly construed as non-internalist and internalist conceptions of biolinguistics respectively. The internalist approach boils down to a conception of language where language as a mental grammar in the form of I-language grows and functions like a biological organ. On the other hand, under such a construal consistent with Koster’s (Biolinguistics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Phrase structure parameters.Janet Dean Fodor & Stephen Crain - 1990 - Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (6):619-659.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anatomy of hierarchical information processing.Terrence W. Deacon - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What exactly is Universal Grammar, and has anyone seen it?Ewa Dąbrowska - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Innate knowledge and linguistic principles.Peter W. Culiover - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):615-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nature, nurture, and universal grammar.Stephen Crain & Paul M. Pietroski - 2001 - Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (2):139-186.
    In just a few years, children achieve a stable state of linguistic competence, making them effectively adults with respect to: understanding novel sentences, discerning relations of paraphrase and entailment, acceptability judgments, etc. One familiar account of the language acquisition process treats it as an induction problem of the sort that arises in any domain where the knowledge achieved is logically underdetermined by experience. This view highlights the cues that are available in the input to children, as well as childrens skills (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   45 citations  
  • Language acquisition in the absence of experience.Stephen Crain - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):597-612.
    A fundamental goal of linguistic theory is to explain how natural languages are acquired. This paper describes some recent findings on how learners acquire syntactic knowledge for which there is little, if any, decisive evidence from the environment. The first section presents several general observations about language acquisition that linguistic theory has tried to explain and discusses the thesis that certain linguistic properties are innate because they appear universally and in the absence of corresponding experience. A third diagnostic for innateness, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   113 citations  
  • Charting the course of language development.Stephen Crain - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):639-650.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lending a hand.Michael C. Corballis - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):185-186.
    The precise manner in which language serves its communicative function suggests that natural selection, rather than exaptation or reappropriation, played the major role in its evolution. Natural selection is more readily invoked, I suggest, if it is assumed that language originated as a system of manual gestures, and later switched to an oral mode.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hierarchies and tool-using strategies.Kevin J. Connolly & Edison de J. Manoel - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):554-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Syntax, More or Less.John Collins - 2007 - Mind 116 (464):805-850.
    Much of the best contemporary work in the philosophy of language and content makes appeal to the theories developed in generative syntax. In particular, there is a presumption that—at some level and in some way—the structures provided by syntactic theory mesh with or support our conception of content/linguistic meaning as grounded in our first-person understanding of our communicative speech acts. This paper will suggest that there is no such tight fit. Its claim will be that, if recent generative theories are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Methodology, not metaphysics: Against semantic externalism.John Collins - 2009 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 83 (1):53-69.
    Borg (2009) surveys and rejects a number of arguments in favour of semantic internalism. This paper, in turn, surveys and rejects all of Borg's anti-internalist arguments. My chief moral is that, properly conceived, semantic internalism is a methodological doctrine that takes its lead from current practice in linguistics. The unifying theme of internalist arguments, therefore, is that linguistics neither targets nor presupposes externalia. To the extent that this claim is correct, we should be internalists about linguistic phenomena, including semantics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Reflexive anaphor resolution in spoken language comprehension: structural constraints and beyond.Kaili Clackson & Vera Heyer - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Causality and parameter setting.Robin Clark - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):337-338.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parameter setting in “instantaneous” and real-time acquisition.Guglielmo Cinque - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):336-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pitch Perception in the First Year of Life, a Comparison of Lexical Tones and Musical Pitch.Ao Chen, Catherine J. Stevens & René Kager - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Single words, multiple words, and the functions of language.A. Charles Catania - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):184-185.
    Wilkins & Wakefield assign importance to motor systems but skip from anatomy to cognitive structure with little attention to behavior. Organisms, no matter how sophisticated, that do not behave in accord with what they know will fall by the evolutionary wayside. Facts about behavior can supplement the authors' theory, whose hierarchical structures can accommodate an evolutionary scenario in which a million years or more of functionally varied utterances mainly limited to single words is followed by an explosion of linguistic diversity (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and the Animal Origins of Linguistic Communication.Luke Cash - 2017 - Philosophical Investigations 40 (4):303-328.
    Wittgenstein's notorious sample of a ‘complete primitive language’ is often thought to be closer in kind to animal forms of communication than human language. Indeed, it has been criticised on precisely these grounds. But such debates make little sense if we take seriously Wittgenstein's idea that language is a family resemblance concept. So, rather than argue that the builders’ game ‘really is a language’, I propose to turn the debate on its head and welcome the comparison. By changing our perspective (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thoughts and oughts.Mason Cash - 2008 - Philosophical Explorations 11 (2):93 – 119.
    Many now accept the thesis that norms are somehow constitutively involved in people's contentful intentional states. I distinguish three versions of this normative thesis that disagree about the type of norms constitutively involved. Are they objective norms of correctness, subjective norms of rationality, or intersubjective norms of social practices? I show the advantages of the third version, arguing that it improves upon the other two versions, as well as incorporating their principal insights. I then defend it against two serious challenges: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Subject relative clauses are not universally easier to process: Evidence from Basque.Manuel Carreiras, Jon Andoni Duñabeitia, Marta Vergara, Irene de la Cruz-Pavía & Itziar Laka - 2010 - Cognition 115 (1):79-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What Do Words Do for Us?Ronnie Cann & Ruth Kempson - 2017 - Dialectica 71 (3):425-460.
    In this paper we adopt the hypothesis that languages are mechanisms for interaction, and that grammars encode the means by which such interaction may take place, by use of procedures that construct representations of meaning from strings of words uttered in context, and conversely strings of words are built up from representations of content in interaction with context. In a review of the systemic use of ellipsis in dialogue and associated split-utterance phenomena, we show how, in Dynamic Syntax, words give (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Not in the absence of experience.Helen Smith Caims - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):614-615.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasoning in moral conflicts.Monica Bucciarelli & Margherita Daniele - 2015 - Thinking and Reasoning 21 (3):265-294.
    Following the assumptions of the mental model theory and its account of moral judgements, we argue for a main role of reasoning in moral judgements, especially in dealing with moral conflicts. In four experiments, we invited adult participants to evaluate scenarios describing moral or immoral actions. Our results confirm the predictions deriving from our assumptions: Given a moral or immoral scenario, the manipulation of the propositions which refer to norms and values results in a scenario eliciting a moral conflict ; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On triggers.Hugh W. Buckingham - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):335-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral dilemmas in females: children are more utilitarian than adults.Monica Bucciarelli - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6:149174.
    Influential theories on moral judgments propose that they rely either on emotions or on innate moral principles. In contrast, the mental model theory postulates that moral judgments rely on reasoning, either intuition or deliberation. The theory allows for the possibility that intuitions lead to utilitarian judgments. This paper reports two experiments involving fifth-grade children, adolescents, and adults; the results revealed that children reason intuitively to resolve moral dilemmas in which action and inaction lead to different outcomes. In particular, the results (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Is preadaptation for language a necessary assumption?David J. Bryant - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):183-184.
    Preadaptation for language is an unnecessary assumption because intermediate stages of linguistic ability are possible and adaptive. Language could have evolved through gradual selection from structures exhibiting few features associated with modern structures. Without physical evidence pertaining to language ability in prehabilis hominids, it remains possible that selective pressures for language use preceded and necessitated modern neurolinguistic structures.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Formalization and the objects of logic.Georg Brun - 2008 - Erkenntnis 69 (1):1 - 30.
    There is a long-standing debate whether propositions, sentences, statements or utterances provide an answer to the question of what objects logical formulas stand for. Based on the traditional understanding of logic as a science of valid arguments, this question is firstly framed more exactly, making explicit that it calls not only for identifying some class of objects, but also for explaining their relationship to ordinary language utterances. It is then argued that there are strong arguments against the proposals commonly put (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Simians, space, and syntax: Parallels between human language and primate social cognition.Leslie Brothers & Michael J. Raleigh - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):613-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge and Lotteries. [REVIEW]Steffen Borge - 2006 - Disputatio 1 (20):361-368.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Recursive Subsystems in Aphasia and Alzheimer's Disease: Case Studies in Syntax and Theory of Mind.Zoltán Bánréti, Ildikó Hoffmann & Veronika Vincze - 2016 - Frontiers in Psychology 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What does language acquisition tell us about language evolution?Paul Bloom - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):553-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Syntax is not as simple as it seems.Derek Bickerton - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):552-553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Finding the true place of Homo habilis in language evolution.Derek Bickerton - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):182-183.
    Despite some sound basic assumptions, Wilkins & Wakefield portray a Homo habilis too linguistically sophisticated to fit in with the subsequent fossil record and thereby lose a reasoned explanation for human innovativeness. They err, too, in accepting a single-level model of conceptual structure and in deriving initial linguistic units from calls, a process far more dubious than the derivation of home-sign from naive gesture.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The domain of classical conditioning: Extensions to Pavlovian-operant interactions.Philip J. Bersh & Wayne G. Whitehouse - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):137-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of development.Ruth A. Berman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):612-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Folk experiments.Jeffery W. Bentley - 2006 - Agriculture and Human Values 23 (4):451-462.
    Folk experiments in agriculture are often inspired by new ideas blended with old ones, motivated by economic and environmental change. They tend to save labor or capital. These notions are illustrated with nine short case studies from Nicaragua and El Salvador. The new ideas that catalyze folk experiments may be provided by development agencies, but paradoxically, the folk experiments are so common that the agencies that inspire them usually pay little attention to them. Some folk experiments are original, but others (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Some observations on degree of learnability.C. L. Baker - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):334-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mood as verbal definiteness in a" tenseless" language.Mark Baker & Lisa Travis - 1997 - Natural Language Semantics 5 (3):213-269.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Trouble with Memes: Inference versus Imitation in Cultural Creation.Scott Atran - 2001 - Human Nature 12 (4):351-381.
    Memes are hypothetical cultural units passed on by imitation; although nonbiological, they undergo Darwinian selection like genes. Cognitive study of multimodular human minds undermines memetics: unlike in genetic replication, high-fidelity transmission of cultural information is the exception, not the rule. Constant, rapid 'mutation' of information during communication generates endlessly varied creations that nevertheless adhere to modular input conditions. The sort of cultural information most susceptible to modular processing is that most readily acquired by children, most easily transmitted across individuals, most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • Making the best use of primate tool use?James R. Anderson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Integrating experiential and distributional data to learn semantic representations.Mark Andrews, Gabriella Vigliocco & David Vinson - 2009 - Psychological Review 116 (3):463-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   51 citations  
  • Brain mechanisms in classical conditioning.A. Alexieva & N. A. Nicolov - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):137-137.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What Machine Learning Can Tell Us About the Role of Language Dominance in the Diagnostic Accuracy of German LITMUS Non-word and Sentence Repetition Tasks.Lina Abed Ibrahim & István Fekete - 2019 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    This study investigates the performance of 21 monolingual and 56 bilingual children aged 5;6-9;0 on German-LITMUS-sentence-repetition (SRT; Hamann et al., 2013) and nonword-repetition-tasks (NWRT; Grimm et al., 2014), which were constructed according to the LITMUS-principles (Language Impairment Testing in Multilingual Settings; Armon-Lotem et al., 2015). Both tasks incorporate complex structures shown to be cross-linguistically challenging for children with Specific Language Impairment (SLI) and aim at minimizing bias against bilingual children while still being indicative of the presence of language impairment across (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognitive Primitives of Collective Intentions: Linguistic Evidence of Our Mental Ontology.Natalie Gold & Daniel Harbour - 2012 - Mind and Language 27 (2):109-134.
    Theories of collective intentions must distinguish genuinely collective intentions from coincidentally harmonized ones. Two apparently equally apt ways of doing so are the ‘neo-reductionism’ of Bacharach (2006) and Gold and Sugden (2007a) and the ‘non-reductionism’ of Searle (1990, 1995). Here, we present findings from theoretical linguistics that show that we is not a cognitive primitive, but is composed of notions of I and grouphood. The ramifications of this finding on the structure both of grammatical and lexical systems suggests that an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pre-Hunt Communication Provides Context for the Evolution of Early Human Language.Szabolcs Számadó - 2010 - Biological Theory 5 (4):366-382.
    The origin of human language is one of the most fascinating and most difficult problems of evolution. Here I argue that pre-hunt communication was the starting context of the evolution of human language. Hunting of big game created a shared interest; animals and hunting actions are easy to imitate; the need to plan created a pressure for increasing complexity; and finally, cultural inheritance of hunting tools and know-how made the transition unique. I further argue that this “first step” was actually (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On one as an anaphor.Stephen Neale - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (2):353-354.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation