Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. "On Denoting" and the Principle of Acquaintance.Russell Wahl - 2007 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 27 (1):7-23.
    While Russell’s concerns in developing the theory of descriptions were primarily with his foundation of logic, he was aware of the epistemological uses of both the theory of denoting concepts and the 1905 theory of deWnite descriptions. At the end of “On Denoting” he suggests that the principle of acquaintance is a “result” of the new theory of denoting. In this paper I examine the relation between the theory of descriptions and the principle of acquaintance, and I reject two suggestions, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why Frege cases do involve cognitive phenomenology but only indirectly.Alberto Voltolini - 2016 - Philosophical Explorations 19 (2):205-221.
    In this paper, I want to hold, first, that a treatment of Frege cases in terms of a difference in cognitive phenomenology of the involved experiential mental states is not viable. Second, I will put forward another treatment of such cases that appeals to a difference in intentional objects metaphysically conceived not as exotica, but as schematic objects, that is, as objects that have no metaphysical nature qua objects of thought. This allows their nature to be settled independently of their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Strange Case of Dr. Moloch and Mr. Snazzo (or the Parmenides’ Riddle Once Again).Alberto Voltolini - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (4):54.
    Once one draws a distinction between loyal non-existent items, which do not exist in a non-universal sense of the first-order existence predicate, and non-items, which fail to exist in a universal sense of that predicate, one may allow for the former but not for the latter in the overall ontological domain, so as to adopt a form of soft Parmenideanism. There are both theoretical and empirical reasons for this distinction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Singularity of Experiences and Thoughts.Alberto Voltolini - 2020 - Topoi 39 (2):459-473.
    Recently, various people have maintained that one must revise either the externalistically-based notion of singular thought or the naïve realism-inspired notion of relational particularity, as respectively applied to some thoughts and to some perceptual experiences. In order to do so, one must either provide a broader notion of singular thought or flank the notion of relational particularity with a broader notion of phenomenal particularity. I want to hold that there is no need of that revision. For the original notions can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There Are Intentionalia of Which It Is True That Such Objects Do Not Exist.Alberto Voltolini - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21 (3):394-414.
    According to Crane’s schematicity thesis (ST) about intentional objects, intentionalia have no particular metaphysical nature qua thought-of entities; moreover, the real metaphysical nature of intentionalia is various, insofar as it is settled independently of the fact that intentionalia are targets of one’s thought. As I will point out, ST has the ontological consequence that the intentionalia that really belong to the general inventory of what there is, the overall domain, are those that fall under a good metaphysical kind, i.e., a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Russell e l'abbandono del suo meinonghianesimo nascosto.Alberto Voltolini - 2006 - Rivista di Estetica 32 (32):93-107.
    In questo paper cercherò di mostrare che la visione tradizionale del mutamento da parte di Russell della sua teoria delle descrizioni definite negli anni che vanno dai Principles of Mathematics del 1903 a «On Denoting» del 1905, visione secondo cui Russell produce una nuova teoria delle descrizioni (anche) per liberarsi dagli impegni ontologici manifesti di stampo meinonghiano ad entità inesistenti connessi alla sua precedente teoria delle descrizioni, non è convincente, perché le due teorie...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is It Merely Loose Talk?⋆.Alberto Voltolini - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (1):51-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • To think is to have something in one’s thought.Alberto Voltolini & Elisabetta Sacchi - 2012 - Quaestio 12:395-422.
    Along with a well-honoured tradition, we will accept that intentionality is at least a property a thought holds necessarily, i.e., in all possible worlds that contain it; more specifically, a necessary relation, namely the relation of existential dependence of the thought on its intentional object. Yet we will first of all try to show that intentionality is more than that. For we will claim that intentionality is an essential property of the thought, namely a property whose predication to the thought (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • If intentional objects are objects for a subject, how are they related?Alberto Voltolini - 2022 - Philosophical Psychology 35 (8):1136-1151.
    Tim Crane has put forward a theory of intentional objects (intentionalia), which has taken up again and expanded by Casey Woodling. Crane’s theory is articulated in three main theses: a) every intentional state, or thought, is about an intentional object; b) taken as such, whether or not it exists, an intentional object is a schematic object; c) taken as such, whether or not it exists, an intentional object is a phenomenological object. In this paper, I will try to show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hic sunt impossibilia. Odradek e altri oggetti non convenzionali.Stefano Vaselli - 2006 - Rivista di Estetica 33 (33):237-266.
    The topic of this article is to develop an alternative, ontologically settled, problematic intuition about how to establish theoretical criteria of (non) conceptuality of an intentional content which kind of properties must an object possess to be able to furnish a full formal satisfaction to a conceptualization process? Are there any objects upon which our concepts can only go in vain in a sort of non conceptual short circuit’s breakdown in the very same act, in order to be caught in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meinongian extensions of predicates.Anna Sierszulska - 2005 - Logic and Logical Philosophy 14 (2):145-163.
    The paper analyses the contemporary notion of an extension of apredicate from the perspective of semantics typical for Meinongian logics, andin opposition to the traditional notion of extension. This leads to a discussionof the types of properties that can be predicated about objects as belonging tothe sets of properties ascribed to them, and such that can be predicated aboutthem only ‘externally’. It is also problematic in which sense nonexistentobjects possess the properties ascribed to them. The concluding remarksconcern some issues related (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Of Course there are Fictional Characters.R. M. Sainsbury - 2012 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 262 (4):615-630.
    I argue that there is no straightforward inference from there being fictional characters to any interesting form of realism. One reason is that “fictional” may be an intensional operator with wide scope, depriving the quantifier of its usual force. Another is that not all uses of “there are” are ontologically committing. A realist needs to show that neither of these phenomena are present in “There are fictional characters”. Other roads to realism run into difficulties when negotiating the role that presupposition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The property-theoretical, performative-nominalistic theory of proper names.Francesco Orilia - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (3):155–176.
    This paper embeds a theory of proper names in a general approach to singular reference based on type‐free property theory. It is proposed that a proper name “N” is a sortal common noun whose meaning is essentially tied to the linguistic type “N”. Moreover, “N” can be singularly referring insofar as it is elliptical for a definite description of the form the “N” Following Montague, the meaning of a definite description is taken to be a property of properties. The proposed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Property‐theoretical, Performative‐nominalistic Theory of Proper Names.Francesco Orilia - 2000 - Dialectica 54 (3):155-176.
    This paper embeds a theory of proper names in a general approach to singular reference based on type‐free property theory. It is proposed that a proper name “N” is a sortal common noun whose meaning is essentially tied to the linguistic type “N”. Moreover, “N” can be singularly referring insofar as it is elliptical for a definite description of the form the “N” Following Montague, the meaning of a definite description is taken to be a property of properties. The proposed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Property theory and the revision theory of definitions.Francesco Orilia - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (1):212-246.
    Russell’s type theory has been the standard property theory for years, relying on rigid type distinctions at the grammatical level to circumvent the paradoxes of predication. In recent years it has been convincingly argued by Bealer, Cochiarella, Turner and others that many linguistic and ontological data are best accounted for by using a type-free property theory. In the spirit of exploring alternatives and “to have as many opportunities as possible for theory comparison”, this paper presents another type-free property theory, to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A theory of fictional entities based on denoting concepts.Francesco Orilia - 2012 - Revue Internationale de Philosophie 262 (4):577-592.
    There are many data suggesting that we should acknowledge fictional entities in our ontological inventory, in spite of the paraphrasing strategies that Russell’s theory of descriptions can offer. Thus the realist attitude toward fictional entities of Meinongian and artifactualist accounts may seem well-motivated. Yet, these approaches infringe the Russellian “robust sense of reality.” A different realist account is proposed here, one that is compatible with the Russellian “robust sense of reality” in that it identifies fictional entities with denoting concepts, understood (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Belief representation in a deductivist type-free doxastic logic.Francesco Orilia - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (2):163-203.
    Konolige''s technical notion of belief based on deduction structures is briefly reviewed and its usefulness for the design of artificial agents with limited representational and deductive capacities is pointed out. The design of artificial agents with more sophisticated representational and deductive capacities is then taken into account. Extended representational capacities require in the first place a solution to the intensional context problems. As an alternative to Konolige''s modal first-order language, an approach based on type-free property theory is proposed. It considers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Russell and the Ontological Argument.Gregory Landini - 2009 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 29 (2):101-128.
    Abstract:It is well known that in Principia Mathematica Russell offers a theory of definite descriptions and holds that ‘existence’ is not a property. It is less well known that in “On Denoting” he discusses the version of Anselm’s ontological argument for God formulated by Descartes, accepting the premiss “Existence is a perfection” and assessing the argument as valid but question-begging. This is different from his later comments in A History of Western Philosophy which find the argument invalid. Indeed, given the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Axiomatizing Belnap's conditional assertion.J. Michael Dunn - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (4):383 - 397.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • “The story says that” operator in story semantics.Charles B. Daniels - 1987 - Studia Logica 46 (1):73-86.
    In [2] a semantics for implication is offered that makes use of stories — sets of sentences assembled under various constraints. Sentences are evaluated at an actual world and in each member of a set of stories. A sentence B is true in a story s just when B s. A implies B iff for all stories and the actual world, whenever A is true, B is true. In this article the first-order language of [2] is extended by the addition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Reply to Andriy Vasylchenko’s Review of Formal Ontology and Conceptual Realism.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 2009 - Axiomathes 19 (2):167-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conceptualism, Realism, and Intensional Logic.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 1989 - Topoi 8 (1):15-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Conceptualism, ramified logic, and nominalized predicates.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 1986 - Topoi 5 (1):75-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • (Mock-)Thinking about the Same.Alberto Voltolini - 2017 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 24:282-307.
    In this paper, I want to address once more the venerable problem of intentional identity, the problem of how different thoughts can be about the same thing even if this thing does not exist. First, I will try to show that antirealist approaches to this problem are doomed to fail. For they ultimately share a problematic assumption, namely that thinking about something involves identifying it. Second, I will claim that once one rejects this assumption and holds instead that thoughts are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Heidegger's Logico-Semantic Strikeback.Alberto Voltolini - 2015 - Organon F: Medzinárodný Časopis Pre Analytickú Filozofiu 22:19-38.
    In (1959), Carnap famously attacked Heidegger for having constructed an insane metaphysics based on a misconception of both the logical form and the semantics of ordinary language. In what follows, it will be argued that, once one appropriately (i.e., in a Russellian fashion) reads Heidegger’s famous sentence that should paradigmatically exemplify such a misconception, i.e., “the nothing nothings”, there is nothing either logically or semantically wrong with it. The real controversy as to how that sentence has to be evaluated—not as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Representing Intentional Objects in Conceptual Realism.Nino B. Cocchiarella - 2013 - Humana Mente 6 (25).
    In this paper we explain how the intentional objects of our mental states can be represented by the intensional objects of conceptual realism. We first briefly examine and show how Brentano’s actualist theory of judgment and his notion of an immanent object have a clear and natural representation in our conceptualist logic of names. We then briefly critically examine Meinong’s theory of objects before turning finally to our own representation of intentional objects in terms of the intensional objects of conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Guise Theory Revisited.Francesco Orilia - 2013 - Humana Mente 6 (25).
    Castañeda’s guise theory is a peculiarly interesting Neo-Meinongian approach, in virtue of its bundle-theoretic and anti-representationalist features. But it also has some problematic aspects. It crucially relies on a series of sameness relations, such as consubstantiation or consociation, but this list is incomplete. Moreover, guise theory is hindered by its view of the sameness relations as forms of predication alternative to what may be called, following Plantinga, standard predication. This paper thus proposes a revised version of guise theory that acknowledges (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark