Switch to: References

Citations of:

An introduction to logic and scientific method

[Madison, Wis.]: Pub. for the United States Armed Forces Institute by Harcourt, Brace and company. Edited by Ernest Nagel (1944)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Quantity and number.James Franklin - 2013 - In Daniel Novotný & Lukáš Novák (eds.), Neo-Aristotelian Perspectives in Metaphysics. London: Routledge. pp. 221-244.
    Quantity is the first category that Aristotle lists after substance. It has extraordinary epistemological clarity: "2+2=4" is the model of a self-evident and universally known truth. Continuous quantities such as the ratio of circumference to diameter of a circle are as clearly known as discrete ones. The theory that mathematics was "the science of quantity" was once the leading philosophy of mathematics. The article looks at puzzles in the classification and epistemology of quantity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Towards an understanding of science.Cemal Yildirim - 1970 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 1 (1):104-118.
    Summary In the attempt to understand science, definition is not much of a help. Due to the ever growing complexity of science, no unique and universally valid set of defining criteria is available. Hence, certain distinctions are resorted to: science is both a body of tested knowledge and a method of inquiry. The latter, in turn, consists of two phases: discovery and confirmation. The writer argues that it is mainly in respect of its method that science can best be characterized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The circle in the ontological argument.Douglas Walton - 1978 - International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9 (4):193 - 218.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Introduction.Gabriele Usberti - 1994 - Topoi 13 (2):67-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Prerequisites for quantification in the empirical sciences.Ladislav Tondl - 1972 - Theory and Decision 2 (3):238-261.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Paradigms of measurement.Piotr Swistak - 1990 - Theory and Decision 29 (1):1-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Possible science, impossible discipline.Howard Schuman - 1994 - Social Epistemology 8 (1):27 – 33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Axioms in Mathematical Practice.Dirk Schlimm - 2013 - Philosophia Mathematica 21 (1):37-92.
    On the basis of a wide range of historical examples various features of axioms are discussed in relation to their use in mathematical practice. A very general framework for this discussion is provided, and it is argued that axioms can play many roles in mathematics and that viewing them as self-evident truths does not do justice to the ways in which mathematicians employ axioms. Possible origins of axioms and criteria for choosing axioms are also examined. The distinctions introduced aim at (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Aristotle's perfect syllogisms, predication, and thedictum de omni.Richard Patterson - 1993 - Synthese 96 (3):359 - 378.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The real objective of Mendel's paper.Floyd V. Monaghan & Alain F. Corcos - 1990 - Biology and Philosophy 5 (3):267-292.
    According to the traditional account Mendel's paper on pea hybrids reported a study of inheritance and its laws. Hence, Mendel came to be known as The Father of Genetics. This paper demonstrates that, in fact, Mendel's objective in his research was finding the empirical laws which describe the formation of hybrids and the development of their offspring over several generations. Having found these laws (and not the laws of inheritance that he is generally credited with) he proposed a theoretical scheme (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Systems of ordering data.Ernst Mayr - 1995 - Biology and Philosophy 10 (4):419-434.
    Four ordering systems have been used most frequently in taxonomy: (1) special purpose classifications, (2) downward classifications (identification schemes), (3) upward or grouping classifications (traditional), and (4) Hennigian phylogenetic systems. The special properties of these four systems are critically evaluated. Grouping classifications and phylogenetic systems have very different objectives: the former the documentation of similarity and closeness of relationship, the latter of phylogeny. Both are legitimate ordering systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Simpson's paradox and the wayward researcher.Gary Malinas - 1997 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (3):343 – 359.
    Simpson's Paradox is introduced and analysed via the mishaps of a researcher who at first falls afoul of the traps Simpson-reversals can set, and then he learns to exploit those traps to advantage. (Note: An error in the treatment of the Sure Thing Principle is corrected in "Simpson's Paradox: A Logically Benign, Empirically Treacherous Hydra").
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What's in a Name?Don S. Levi - 2008 - Philosophical Investigations 31 (4):340-358.
    This paper is about the mode of being of names. The paper begins by explaining why the joke is on commentators who see Lewis Carroll's White Knight as applying the use/mention distinction. Then it argues that the real problem with the distinction is that the idea that names are used to mention what they name depends on mistakenly conceiving of language as existing autonomously; and that philosophers have this conception because they fail to appreciate what they are doing when they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Maximum likelihood estimation on generalized sample spaces: An alternative resolution of Simpson's paradox. [REVIEW]Matthias P. Kläy & David J. Foulis - 1990 - Foundations of Physics 20 (7):777-799.
    We propose an alternative resolution of Simpson's paradox in multiple classification experiments, using a different maximum likelihood estimator. In the center of our analysis is a formal representation of free choice and randomization that is based on the notion of incompatible measurements.We first introduce a representation of incompatible measurements as a collection of sets of outcomes. This leads to a natural generalization of Kolmogoroff's axioms of probability. We then discuss the existence and uniqueness of the maximum likelihood estimator for a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mental Models in Cognitive Science.P. N. Johnson-Laird - 1980 - Cognitive Science 4 (1):71-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Boole and mill: differing perspectives on logical psychologism.John Richards - 1980 - History and Philosophy of Logic 1 (1-2):19-36.
    Logical psychologism is the position that logic is a special branch of psychology, that logical laws are descriptíons of experience to be arrived at through observation, and are a posteriori.The accepted arguments against logical psychologism are effective only when directed against this extreme version. However, the clauses in the above characterization are independent and ambiguous, and may be considered separately. This separation permits a reconsideration of less extreme attempts to tie logic to psychology, such as those defended by Mill and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The Development of Logic as Reflected in the Fate of the Syllogism 1600–1900.James Van Evra - 2000 - History and Philosophy of Logic 21 (2):115-134.
    One way to determine the quality and pace of change in a science as it undergoes a major transition is to follow some feature of it which remains relatively stable throughout the process. Following the chosen item as it goes through reinterpretation permits conclusions to be drawn about the nature and scope of the broader change in question. In what follows, this device is applied to the change which took place in logic in the mid-nineteenth century. The feature chosen as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A Model for the Division of Semiotic Labor in Scientific Argument: The Interaction of Words and Images.Alan G. Gross - 2011 - Science in Context 24 (4):517-544.
    ArgumentA growing cross-disciplinary literature has acknowledged the importance of verbal-visual interaction in the creation and communication of scientific texts. I contend that the proper understanding of these texts must flow from a hermeneutic model that takes verbal-visual interaction seriously, one that is firmly grounded in cognitive constraints and affordances. The model I propose has two modules, one for perception, derived from Gestalt psychology, the other for cognition, derived from Peirce's semiotics. I apply this model to an important but largely neglected (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descriptive vs Revisionary Social Epistemology: The Former as Seen by the Latter.Steve Fuller - 2004 - Episteme 1 (1):23-34.
    When Peter Strawson subtitled the most celebrated book in ordinary language philosophy, Individuals, ‘An essay in descriptive metaphysics’, he shocked mainly for having reintroduced ‘metaphysics’ into intellectually respectable English a quarter-century after A.J. Ayer had consigned it to the logical positivists' index of forbidden philosophical words . Few at the time appreciated the import of the modifiers ‘descriptive’ and its opposite, ‘revisionary’. Now, another half century on, philosophers have come around to Bertrand Russell's original view that both the ordinary language (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Negative, infinite, and hotter than infinite temperatures.Philip Ehrlich - 1982 - Synthese 50 (2):233 - 277.
    We examine the notions of negative, infinite and hotter than infinite temperatures and show how these unusual concepts gain legitimacy in quantum statistical mechanics. We ask if the existence of an infinite temperature implies the existence of an actual infinity and argue that it does not. Since one can sensibly talk about hotter than infinite temperatures, we ask if one could legitimately speak of other physical quantities, such as length and duration, in analogous terms. That is, could there be longer (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The existential assumptions of traditional logic.Dwayne Hudson Mulder - 1996 - History and Philosophy of Logic 17 (1-2):141-154.
    There have been and continue to be disagreements about how to consider the traditional square of opposition and the traditional inferences of obversion, conversion, contraposition and inversion from the perspective of contemporary quantificational logic. Philosophers have made many different attempts to save traditional inferences that are invalid when they involve empty classes. I survey some of these attempts and argue that the only satisfactory way of saving all the traditional inferences is to make the existential assumption that both the subject (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Paradox of Inference and the Non-Triviality of Analytic Information.Marie Duží - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (5):473 - 510.
    The classical theory of semantic information (ESI), as formulated by Bar-Hillel and Carnap in 1952, does not give a satisfactory account of the problem of what information, if any, analytically and/or logically true sentences have to offer. According to ESI, analytically true sentences lack informational content, and any two analytically equivalent sentences convey the same piece of information. This problem is connected with Cohen and Nagel's paradox of inference: Since the conclusion of a valid argument is contained in the premises, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Education and some aspects of meaning: A background study.R. D. Bramwell - 1972 - British Journal of Educational Studies 20 (1):12-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Education and Some Aspects of Meaning: A Background Study.R. D. Bramwell - 1972 - British Journal of Educational Studies 20 (1):12 - 26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fallacies and alternative interpretations.Jonathan E. Adler - 1994 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (3):271 – 282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations