Switch to: References

Citations of:

Logics and languages

London,: Methuen [Distributed in the U.S.A. by Harper & Row (1973)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Linguistic or pragmatic description in the context of the performadox.Alice Davison - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (4):499 - 526.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Quotational theories of propositional attitudes.M. J. Cresswell - 1980 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 9 (1):17 - 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • De re belief generalized.Maxwell J. Cresswell & Arnim Stechow - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (4):503 - 535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • Nominalization and Montague grammar: A semantics without types for natural languages.Gennaro Chierchia - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3):303 - 354.
    We started from the fact that type theory, in the way it was implemented in IL, makes it costly to deal with nominalization processes. We have also argued that the type hierarchy as such doesn't play any real role in a grammar; the classification it provides for different semantic objects is already contained, in some sense, in the categorial structure of the grammar itself. So, on the basis of a theory of properties (Cocchiarella's HST*) we have tried to build a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • A performadox in truth-conditional semantics.Steven E. Boër & William G. Lycan - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (1):71 - 100.
    An argument is developed at some length to show that any semantical theory which treats superficially nonperformative sentences as being governed by performative prefaces at some level of underlying structure must either leave those sentences semantically uninterpreted or assign them the wrong truth-conditions. Several possible escapes from this dilemma are examined; it is tentatively concluded that such hypotheses as the Ross-Lakoff-Sadock Performative Analysis should be rejected despite their attractions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • The algebra of events.Emmon Bach - 1986 - Linguistics and Philosophy 9 (1):5--16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   140 citations  
  • Jackson on perception.M. J. Cresswell - 1980 - Theoria 46 (2-3):123-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • El dogma extensionalista de las aproximaciones veritativo-condicionales del significado.Leticia Santos Varona - 2017 - Contrastes: Revista Internacional de Filosofía 22 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Language Adequacy.Urszula Wybraniec-Skardowska - 2015 - Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 40 (1):257-292.
    The paper concentrates on the problem of adequate reflection of fragments of reality via expressions of language and inter-subjective knowledge about these fragments, called here, in brief, language adequacy. This problem is formulated in several aspects, the most being: the compatibility of language syntax with its bi-level semantics: intensional and extensional. In this paper, various aspects of language adequacy find their logical explication on the ground of the formal-logical theory T of any categorial language L generated by the so-called classical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Note on Structural Logics.Zbigniew Stachniak - 1985 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 31 (19‐20):317-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Possibility Semantics for Intuitionistic Logic.M. J. Cresswell - 2004 - Australasian Journal of Logic 2:11-29.
    The paper investigates interpretations of propositional and firstorder logic in which validity is defined in terms of partial indices; sometimes called possibilities but here understood as non-empty subsets of a set W of possible worlds. Truth at a set of worlds is understood to be truth at every world in the set. If all subsets of W are permitted the logic so determined is classical first-order predicate logic. Restricting allowable subsets and then imposing certain closure conditions provides a modelling for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Sulla relatività logica.Achille C. Varzi - 2004 - In Massimiliano Carrara & Pierdaniele Giaretta (eds.), Filosofia e logica. Rubbettino Editore. pp. 135–173.
    Italian translation of "On Logical Relativity" (2002), by Luca Morena.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What model theoretic semantics cannot do?Ernest Lepore - 1983 - Synthese 54 (2):167 - 187.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Ambiguity, generality, and indeterminacy: Tests and definitions. [REVIEW]Brendan S. Gillon - 1990 - Synthese 85 (3):391 - 416.
    The problem addressed is that of finding a sound characterization of ambiguity. Two kinds of characterizations are distinguished: tests and definitions. Various definitions of ambiguity are critically examined and contrasted with definitions of generality and indeterminacy, concepts with which ambiguity is sometimes confused. One definition of ambiguity is defended as being more theoretically adequate than others which have been suggested by both philosophers and linguists. It is also shown how this definition of ambiguity obviates a problem thought to be posed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • The interpretation of frequency adjectives.Gregory T. Stump - 1980 - Linguistics and Philosophy 4 (2):221 - 257.
    What I have attempted to show in the foregoing is that: (1) For any frequency adjective f, there is an element of meaning common to both the adverbial and the generic usage of f; this is a function f′ from propositions to truth-values such that f′(Φ)′ is true at an interval i iff Φ′ is true at subintervals of i distributed through i in a certain way. (2) In an adverbial use of f, f′ functions like the corresponding frequency adverb. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Biscuit conditionals: Quantification over potential literal acts. [REVIEW]Muffy E. A. Siegel - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (2):167 - 203.
    In biscuit conditionals (BCs) such as If you’re hungry, there’s pizza in the fridge, the if clause appears to apply to the illocutionary act performed in uttering the main clause, rather than to its propositional content. Accordingly, previous analyses of BCs have focused on illocutionary acts, and, this, I argue, leads them to yield incorrect paraphrases. I propose, instead, that BCs involve existential quantification over potential literal acts such as assertions, questions, commands, and exclamations, the semantic objects associated with declarative, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Semantic nominalism.John Bigelow - 1981 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 59 (4):403 – 421.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Intertheoretic Reduction, Confirmation, and Montague’s Syntax-Semantics Relation.Kristina Liefke & Stephan Hartmann - 2018 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 27 (4):313-341.
    Intertheoretic relations are an important topic in the philosophy of science. However, since their classical discussion by Ernest Nagel, such relations have mostly been restricted to relations between pairs of theories in the natural sciences. This paper presents a case study of a new type of intertheoretic relation that is inspired by Montague’s analysis of the linguistic syntax-semantics relation. The paper develops a simple model of this relation. To motivate the adoption of our new model, we show that this model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From Epistemic Contextualism to Epistemic Expressivism.Matthew Chrisman - 2007 - Philosophical Studies 135 (2):225-254.
    In this paper, I exploit the parallel between epistemic contextualism and metaethical speaker-relativism to argue that a promising way out of two of the primary problems facing contextualism is one already explored in some detail in the ethical case – viz. expressivism. The upshot is an argument for a form of epistemic expressivism modeled on a familiar form of ethical expressivism. This provides a new nondescriptivist option for understanding the meaning of knowledge attributions, which arguably better captures the normative nature (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   83 citations  
  • Paradox, Closure and Indirect Speech Reports.Stephen Read - 2015 - Logica Universalis 9 (2):237-251.
    Bradwardine’s solution to the the logical paradoxes depends on the idea that every sentence signifies many things, and its truth depends on things’ being wholly as it signifies. This idea is underpinned by his claim that a sentence signifies everything that follows from what it signifies. But the idea that signification is closed under entailment appears too strong, just as logical omniscience is unacceptable in the logic of knowledge. What is needed is a more restricted closure principle. A clue can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Free Choice Disjunction and Epistemic Possibility.Thomas Ede Zimmermann - 2000 - Natural Language Semantics 8 (4):255-290.
    This paper offers an explanation of the fact that sentences of the form (1) ‘X may A or B’ may be construed as implying (2) ‘X may A and X may B’, especially if they are used to grant permission. It is suggested that the effect arises because disjunctions are conjunctive lists of epistemic possibilities. Consequently, if the modal may is itself epistemic, (1) comes out as equivalent to (2), due to general laws of epistemic logic. On the other hand, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   110 citations  
  • Temporal adverbials, tenses and the perfect.Frank Vlach - 1993 - Linguistics and Philosophy 16 (3):231 - 283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Problems in the construction of a theory of natural language.F. J. Vandamme - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (4):541-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Montague semantics, nominalization and Scott's domains.Raymond Turner - 1983 - Linguistics and Philosophy 6 (2):259 - 288.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Note on Structural Logics.Zbigniew Stachniak - 1985 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 31 (19-20):317-320.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Yehoshua bar-Hillel (1915–1975).Helmut Schnelle - 1978 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 9 (1):i-12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Universal semantics?Richard Routley - 1975 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 4 (3):327 - 356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • And the Visibility Parameter for D-Adverbs.Arnim von Stechow - unknown
    The proponents of strong lexicalism hold the view that “words” are formed in the lexicon and are opaque for the syntax ((Dowty 1979), (DiSciullo and Williams 1987), (Jackendoff 1990) and many others). Modular morphology, on the other hand, offers the possibility that at least some words are partially formed in the syntax ((Baker 1988), (Borer 1988), (Hale and Keyser 1994), (Chomsky 1995) and many others). In (Stechow 1995) and (Stechow 1996) it has been argued that facts observed with German wieder (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Complex Predication and the Metaphysics of Properties.Bryan Pickel - 2014 - Dialectica 68 (2):209-230.
    The existence of complex predicates seems to support an abundant conception of properties. Specifically, the application conditions for complex predicates seem to be explained by the distribution of a sparser base of predicates. This explanatory link might suggest that the existence and distribution of properties expressed by complex predicates are explained by the existence and distribution of a sparser base of properties. Thus, complex predicates seem to legitimize the assumption of a wide array of properties. The additional properties are no (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interpreting formal logic.Jaroslav Peregrin - 1994 - Erkenntnis 40 (1):5 - 20.
    The concept ofsemantic interpretation is a source of chronic confusion: the introduction of a notion ofinterpretation can be the result of several quite different kinds of considerations.Interpretation can be understood in at least three ways: as a process of dis-abstraction of formulas, as technical tool for the sake of characterizing truth, or as a reconstruction of meaning-assignment. However essentially different these motifs are and however properly they must be kept apart, these can all be brought to one and the same (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Situations, worlds and contexts.Barbara H. Partee - 1985 - Linguistics and Philosophy 8 (1):53--58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On categorial grammar and logical form.Witold Marciszewski - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (1):1-5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Structured meanings and reflexive domains.Serge Lapierre - 1992 - Studia Logica 51 (2):215 - 239.
    This paper is about the most important technical problem faced by Structured Meanings Semantics: the reiteration of hyperintensional functors (i.e., functors of -categorial languages of the sort defined by Max Cresswell in [6]). A way to solve this problem in a general and natural way by using Scott's Domains is both suggested and shown. The result is a semantics which unrestrictedly allows reiterations of hyperintensional functors. The semantics is also extended to accommodate -categorial languages with variables.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reply to Baker.William G. Lycan - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (1):95 – 100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Believing in semantics.John C. Bigelow - 1978 - Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (1):101--144.
    This paper concerns the semantics of belief-sentences. I pass over ontologically lavish theories which appeal to impossible worlds, or other points of reference which contain more than possible worlds. I then refute ontologically stingy, quotational theories. My own theory employs the techniques of possible worlds semantics to elaborate a Fregean analysis of belief-sentences. In a belief-sentence, the embedded clause does not have its usual reference, but refers rather to its own semantic structure. I show how this theory can accommodate quantification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Cross-categorial semantics for conjoined common nouns.Merrie Bergmann - 1982 - Linguistics and Philosophy 5 (3):399 - 401.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Die zurückführung Des möglichen auf Das wirkliche.Peter Kügler - 1994 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 25 (2):223 - 240.
    The Reduction of the Possible to the Real. Modern philosophy cannot avoid dealing with possible worlds - neither in the field of intensional logic nor in other fields not directly connected with logical investigations. This paper attempts to develop a method to substitute possible worlds by the real world, referring to the works of Stig Kanger and Nino B. Cocchiarella. This is done by investigating the metaphorical and dynamical functions of natural languages. It is proved that this new technique is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On rewriting sentences into formulas.Pavel Křížek - 1978 - Studia Logica 37 (1):115 - 128.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On degrees of adequacy for formal semantics of natural languages.Asa Kasher - 1976 - Philosophica 18 (2):139-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The semantics of Frege's Grundgesetze.John N. Martin - 1984 - History and Philosophy of Logic 5 (2):143-176.
    Quantifiers in Frege's Grundgesetze like are not well-defined because the part Fx & Gx stands for a concept but the yoking conjunction is horizontalised and must stand for a truth-value. This standard interpretation is rejected in favor of a substitutional reading that, it is argued, both conforms better to the text and is well-defined. The theory of the horizontal is investigated in detail and the composite reading of Frege's connectives as made up of horizontals is rejected. The sense in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Can every modifier be treated as a sentence modifier?Lloyd Humberstone - 2008 - Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1):241-275.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Semantics of propositional attitudes: A critical study of Cresswell's. [REVIEW]Anil Gupta & Leah Savion - 1987 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 16 (4):395-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Model Theory and the Pragmatics of Indexicals.Paul Gochet - 1977 - Dialectica 31 (3‐4):389-408.
    SummaryThe paper is a critical survey of the semantics and pragmatics of Indexicals. Both the coordinate‐approach due to Lewis and the semantization of pragmatics attempted by Lakoff are shown to be inadequate. Cresswell's more dynamic approach is shown to withstand the objections raised against it. Sophisticated accounts such as a two dimensional tense logic, or a semantics involving pragmatic models and multiple reference models are shown to be necessary to cope with the intricacies of the use of tense in natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantics and truth relative to a world.Michael Glanzberg - 2009 - Synthese 166 (2):281-307.
    This paper argues that relativity of truth to a world plays no significant role in empirical semantic theory, even as it is done in the model-theoretic tradition relying on intensional type theory. Some philosophical views of content provide an important notion of truth at a world, but they do not constrain the empirical domain of semantic theory in a way that makes this notion empirically significant. As an application of this conclusion, this paper shows that a potential motivation for relativism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • On the semantics/pragmatics distinction.Brendan S. Gillon - 2008 - Synthese 165 (3):373-384.
    This paper addresses two questions: what is the distinction between semantics and pragmatics? And why is this distinction important? These questions are discussed in light of the central explanatory goal of linguistics and in relation to the phenomenon of context sensitivity, as illustrated by relational words with implicit arguments and by so-called quantifier domain restriction. It is concluded that context sensitivity is, in the former case, grammatical or lexical and, in the latter case, neither.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Implicit complements: a dilemma for model theoretic semantics. [REVIEW]Brendan S. Gillon - 2012 - Linguistics and Philosophy 35 (4):313-359.
    I show that words with indefinite implicit complements occasion a dilemma for their model theory. There has been only two previous attempts to address this problem, one by Fodor and Fodor (1980) and one by Dowty (1981). Each requires that any word tolerating an implicit complement be treated as ambiguous between two different lexical entries and that a meaning postulate or lexical rule be given to constrain suitably the meanings of the various entries for the word. I show that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Towards a referential analysis of temporal expressions.Mürvet Enç - 1986 - Linguistics and Philosophy 9 (4):405 - 426.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Prepositions and points of view.M. J. Cresswell - 1978 - Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (1):1 - 41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Identity and intensional objects.M. J. Cresswell - 1975 - Philosophia 5 (1-2):47-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Intensionality and context change.Gennaro Chierchia - 1994 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 3 (2):141-168.
    It is arguably desirable to have a theory of meaning that (i) does not identify propositions with sets of worlds, (ii) enables to capture the dynamic character of semantic interpretation and (iii) provides the basis for a semantic program that incorporates and extends the achievements of Montague semantics. A theory of properties and propositions that meets these desiderata is developed and several applications to the semantic analysis of natural languages are explored.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations