Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Learning is critical, not implementation versus algorithm.James T. Townsend - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):497-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the proper treatment of thermostats.David S. Touretzky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):55-56.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionist models are also algorithmic.David S. Touretzky - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):496-497.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Massive redeployment or distributed modularity?Alexia Toskos Dils & Stephen J. Flusberg - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4):292-293.
    In distinguishing itself from other distributed approaches to cognition, Anderson's theory of neural reuse is susceptible to some of the same criticisms that have been leveled at modular approaches. Specifically, neural reuse theories state that: (1) the of a given brain circuit is fixed, rather than shaped by its input, and (2) that high-level cognitive behaviors can be cleanly mapped onto a specific set of brain circuits in a non-contextualized manner.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are visuomotor representations cognitively penetrable? Biasing action-guiding vision.Josefa Toribio - 2018 - Synthese (Suppl 17):1-19.
    Is action-guiding vision cognitively penetrable? More specifically, is the visual processing that guides our goal-directed actions sensitive to semantic information from cognitive states? This paper critically examines a recent family of arguments whose aim is to challenge a widespread and influential view in philosophy and cognitive science: the view that action-guiding vision is cognitively impenetrable. I argue, in response, that while there may very well be top–down causal influences on action-guiding vision, they should not be taken to be an instance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Where's the person?Michael Tomasello - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):84-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • It's imitation, not mimesis.Michael Tomasello - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):771-772.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Cognitive ethology comes of age.Michael Tomasello - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):168-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognition as cause.Michael Tomasello - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):607-608.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rejecting induction: Using occam's razor too soon.J. T. Tolliver - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):669-670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ecological rationality and its contents.M. Todd, Laurence Fiddick & Stefan Krauss - 2000 - Thinking and Reasoning 6 (4):375 – 384.
    (2000). Ecological rationality and its contents. Thinking & Reasoning: Vol. 6, No. 4, pp. 375-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Why Alison Gopnik should be a behaviorist.Nicholas S. Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):83-84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The cerebellum and memory.Richard F. Thompson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):801-802.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Oh no! Not social Darwinism again!.Nicholas S. Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):309-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Overcoming contextual variables, negative results, and Macphail's null hypothesis.Roger K. Thomas - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (4):680.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Language, thought and consciousness in the modern mind.Evan Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):770-771.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does language arise from a calculus of dominance?Nicholas S. Thompson - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):387-387.
    Robin Dunbar's hypothesis that language capacity in response to the demands of maintaining large groups suggests a more specific hypothesis that language arose from a cognitive calculus by which animals could predict their status in complex dominance situations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaos can be overplayed.René Thom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):182-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Buddhist Philosophy and Scientific Naturalism.Evan Thompson - 2023 - Sophia 62 (1):71-86.
    This paper is a response to Christian Coseru, ‘The Middle Way to Reality: On Why I Am Not a Buddhist and Other Philosophical Curiosities.’ I address Coseru’s critical comments about naturalism, evolutionary psychology, scientific realism, and Madhyamaka philosophy. I argue that scientific naturalism is not the right framework for relating Buddhism to science; rather, the proper framework is the ethics of knowledge. I argue that Coseru’s defence of evolutionary psychology is unconvincing and rests on a misunderstanding of the issues concerning (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Are theories of imagery theories of imagination? An active perception approach to conscious mental content.Nigel J. T. Thomas - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (2):207-245.
    Can theories of mental imagery, conscious mental contents, developed within cognitive science throw light on the obscure (but culturally very significant) concept of imagination? Three extant views of mental imagery are considered: quasi‐pictorial, description, and perceptual activity theories. The first two face serious theoretical and empirical difficulties. The third is (for historically contingent reasons) little known, theoretically underdeveloped, and empirically untried, but has real explanatory potential. It rejects the “traditional” symbolic computational view of mental contents, but is compatible with recentsituated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Are developmental disorders like cases of adult brain damage? Implications from connectionist modelling.Michael Thomas & Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 2002 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (6):727-750.
    It is often assumed that similar domain-specific behavioural impairments found in cases of adult brain damage and developmental disorders correspond to similar underlying causes, and can serve as convergent evidence for the modular structure of the normal adult cognitive system. We argue that this correspondence is contingent on an unsupported assumption that atypical development can produce selective deficits while the rest of the system develops normally (Residual Normality), and that this assumption tends to bias data collection in the field. Based (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Sexual momentum may be independent of social status.Del Thiessen - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):308-309.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The pragmatics of induction.Paul Thagard - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):668-669.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extending explanatory coherence.Paul Thagard - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):490-502.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Explanatory coherence (plus commentary).Paul Thagard - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):435-467.
    This target article presents a new computational theory of explanatory coherence that applies to the acceptance and rejection of scientific hypotheses as well as to reasoning in everyday life, The theory consists of seven principles that establish relations of local coherence between a hypothesis and other propositions. A hypothesis coheres with propositions that it explains, or that explain it, or that participate with it in explaining other propositions, or that offer analogous explanations. Propositions are incoherent with each other if they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   226 citations  
  • The spiritual limits of neuropsychological life.John A. Teske - 1996 - Zygon 31 (2):209-234.
    How neuropsychology is necessary but insufficient for understanding spirituality is explored. Multileveled spiritual requisites are systematically examined in terms of their neuropsychological constituents and limitations. The central “problem of integrity” is articulated via the “modularity” of our neuropsychology, and evidence is presented for disunities of self and consciousness. It is argued that the integrity of self or spirit is a contingent achievement rather than a necessary given. Integrating possibilities include belief, emotion, and relationships. Understanding integrity, and the transformations of self-surrender (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • From embodied to extended cognition.John A. Teske - 2013 - Zygon 48 (3):759-787.
    Embodied cognitive science holds that cognitive processes are deeply and inescapably rooted in our bodily interactions with the world. Our finite, contingent, and mortal embodiment may be not only supportive, but in some cases even constitutive of emotions, thoughts, and experiences. My discussion here will work outward from the neuroanatomy and neurophysiology of the brain to a nervous system which extends to the boundaries of the body. It will extend to nonneural aspects of embodiment and even beyond the boundaries of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Situation theory and mental models.Alice G. B. ter Meulen - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (2):358-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What is the algorithmic level?M. M. Taylor & R. A. Pigeau - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):495-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What really matters.Charles Taylor - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The thinker dreams of being an emperor.M. M. Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):685-686.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Epistemic justification and psychological realism.James E. Taylor - 1990 - Synthese 85 (2):199 - 230.
    The main thesis of this paper is that it is not possible to determine the nature of epistemic justification apart from scientific psychological investigation. I call this view the strong thesis of methodological psychologism. Two sub-theses provide the primary support for this claim. The first sub-thesis is that no account of epistemic justification is correct which requires for the possession of at least one justified belief a psychological capacity which humans do not have. That is, the correct account of epistemic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Mara Beller, _Quantum Dialogue: The Making Of A Revolution_ . Chicago: The University of Chicago Press (1999), xvi + 366 pp., $35.00 (cloth), $20.00 (paper). [REVIEW]Scott Tanona - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):395-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mara Beller, Quantum Dialogue: The Making Of A Revolution. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press , xvi + 366 pp., $35.00 , $20.00. [REVIEW]Scott Tanona - 2002 - Philosophy of Science 69 (2):395-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The computing frog.G. Székely - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):446-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder as a Disturbance of Security Motivation.Henry Szechtman & Erik Woody - 2004 - Psychological Review 111 (1):111-127.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Knowledge as a Non‐Normative Relation.Kurt Sylvan - 2018 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (1):190-222.
    According to a view I’ll call Epistemic Normativism, knowledge is normative in the same sense in which paradigmatically normative properties like justification are normative. This paper argues against EN in two stages and defends a positive non-normativist alternative. After clarifying the target in §1, I consider in §2 some arguments for EN from the premise that knowledge entails justification. I first raise some worries about inferring constitution from entailment. I then rehearse the reasons why some epistemologists reject the Entailment Thesis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Some ethical implications of neurosciences.Charles Susanne & M. Szente - 1997 - Global Bioethics 10 (1-4):111-121.
    The new methods of modern sciences can contribute to understand the genesis of mental illness, the disturbances in brain chemistry, physiology, anatomy or genetical information underlying different diseases of the nervous system. Understanding mental illness is not only challenging to science, but is also of great social importance. Moreover, the new developments of neurosciences put new lights on discussions such as brain-mind concepts, unity of mind, definition of consciousness and even definition of the person.For the majority of the scientists, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Problem spaces, language and connectionism: Issues for cognition.Patrick Suppes - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):457-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reproducing American Sign Language sentences: cognitive scaffolding in working memory.Ted Supalla, Peter C. Hauser & Daphne Bavelier - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5:82875.
    The American Sign Language Sentence Reproduction Test (ASL-SRT) requires the precise reproduction of a series of ASL sentences increasing in complexity and length. Error analyses of such tasks provides insight into working memory and scaffolding processes. Data was collected from three groups expected to differ in fluency: deaf children, deaf adults and hearing adults, all users of ASL. Quantitative (correct/incorrect recall) and qualitative error analyses were performed. Percent correct on the reproduction task supports its sensitivity to fluency as test performance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Interaction of the Explicit and the Implicit in Skill Learning: A Dual-Process Approach.Ron Sun - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (1):159-192.
    This article explicates the interaction between implicit and explicit processes in skill learning, in contrast to the tendency of researchers to study each type in isolation. It highlights various effects of the interaction on learning (including synergy effects). The authors argue for an integrated model of skill learning that takes into account both implicit and explicit processes. Moreover, they argue for a bottom-up approach (first learning implicit knowledge and then explicit knowledge) in the integrated model. A variety of qualitative data (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   55 citations  
  • On levels of cognitive modeling.Ron Sun, Andrew Coward & Michael J. Zenzen - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (5):613-637.
    The article first addresses the importance of cognitive modeling, in terms of its value to cognitive science (as well as other social and behavioral sciences). In particular, it emphasizes the use of cognitive architectures in this undertaking. Based on this approach, the article addresses, in detail, the idea of a multi-level approach that ranges from social to neural levels. In physical sciences, a rigorous set of theories is a hierarchy of descriptions/explanations, in which causal relationships among entities at a high (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Desiderata for cognitive architectures.Ron Sun - 2004 - Philosophical Psychology 17 (3):341-373.
    This article addresses issues in developing cognitive architectures--generic computational models of cognition. Cognitive architectures are believed to be essential in advancing understanding of the mind, and therefore, developing cognitive architectures is an extremely important enterprise in cognitive science. The article proposes a set of essential desiderata for developing cognitive architectures. It then moves on to discuss in detail some of these desiderata and their associated concepts and ideas relevant to developing better cognitive architectures. It argues for the importance of taking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Theoretical terms without analytic truths.Michael Strevens - 2012 - Philosophical Studies 160 (1):167-190.
    When new theoretical terms are introduced into scientific discourse, prevailing accounts imply, analytic or semantic truths come along with them, by way of either definitions or reference-fixing descriptions. But there appear to be few or no analytic truths in scientific theory, which suggests that the prevailing accounts are mistaken. This paper looks to research on the psychology of natural kind concepts to suggest a new account of the introduction of theoretical terms that avoids both definition and reference-fixing description. At the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Introduction: a cartography of contemporary cognitive social theory.Piet Strydom - 2007 - European Journal of Social Theory 10 (3):339-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Genes, specificity, and the lexical/functional distinction in language acquisition.Karin Stromswold - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):648-649.
    Contrary to Müller's claims, and in support of modular theories, genetic factors play a substantial and significant role in language. The finding that some children with specific language impairment (SLI) have nonlinguistic impairments may reflect improper diagnosis of SLI or impairments that are secondary to linguistic impairments. Thus, such findings do not argue against the modularity thesis. The lexical/functional distinction appears to be innate and specifically linguistic and could be instantiated in either symbolic or connectionist systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wavelength processing and colour experience.Petra Stoerig & Alan Cowey - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):53-53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On perceptual expertise.Dustin Stokes - 2021 - Mind and Language 36 (2):241-263.
    Expertise is a cognitive achievement that clearly involves experience and learning, and often requires explicit, time-consuming training specific to the relevant domain. It is also intuitive that this kind of achievement is, in a rich sense, genuinely perceptual. Many experts—be they radiologists, bird watchers, or fingerprint examiners—are better perceivers in the domain(s) of their expertise. The goal of this paper is to motivate three related claims, by substantial appeal to recent empirical research on perceptual expertise: Perceptual expertise is genuinely perceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Meaning and Demonstration.Matthew Stone & Una Stojnic - 2015 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 6 (1):69-97.
    In demonstration, speakers use real-world activity both for its practical effects and to help make their points. The demonstrations of origami mathematics, for example, reconfigure pieces of paper by folding, while simultaneously allowing their author to signal geometric inferences. Demonstration challenges us to explain how practical actions can get such precise significance and how this meaning compares with that of other representations. In this paper, we propose an explanation inspired by David Lewis’s characterizations of coordination and scorekeeping in conversation. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • From data to dynamics: The use of multiple levels of analysis.Gregory O. Stone - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):54-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations