Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Fate of William Whewell’s Four Palætiological Domains: A Comparative Study.Koen B. Tanghe - 2019 - Perspectives on Science 27 (6):810-838.
    In 1847, the British polymath William Whewell pointed out that the sciences for which he, in 1837, had coined the term “palætiological” have much in common and that they may reflect light upon each other by being treated together. This recommendation is here put into practice in a specific way, to wit, not by comparing the palaetiological sciences that Whewell distinguished himself but by comparing the general historical development of the scientific study of the four broad palætiological domains that he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Between the Local and the Global: History of Science in the European Periphery Meets Post-Colonial Studies.Manolis Patiniotis - 2013 - Centaurus 55 (4):361-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Lakatosian Rational Reconstruction Updated.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2017 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 31 (1):83-102.
    I argue in this article that an aspect of Imre Lakatos’s philosophy has been largely ignored in previous literature. The key feature of Lakatos’s philosophy of the historiography of science is its non-representationalism, which enables comparisons of alternative ‘historiographic research programmes’ without implying that the interpretations of history re-present or mirror the past. I discuss some problems of this interpretation and show specifically that Lakatos’s philosophy does not distort the history of science despite its normative ambitions. The last section is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Epistemic Significance of Valid Inference – A Model-Theoretic Approach.Constantin C. Brîncuș - 2015 - In Sorin Costreie & Mircea Dumitru (eds.), Meaning and Truth. Pro Universitaria. pp. 11-36.
    The problem analysed in this paper is whether we can gain knowledge by using valid inferences, and how we can explain this process from a model-theoretic perspective. According to the paradox of inference (Cohen & Nagel 1936/1998, 173), it is logically impossible for an inference to be both valid and its conclusion to possess novelty with respect to the premises. I argue in this paper that valid inference has an epistemic significance, i.e., it can be used by an agent to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • I Am Knowledge. Get Me Out Of Here! On Localism And The Universality Of Science.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2011 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 42 (4):590-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Consideration Of Babylonian Astronomy Within The Historiography Of Science.Francesca Rochberg - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 33 (4):661-684.
    This paper traces the reception of Babylonian astronomy into the history of science, beginning in early to mid twentieth century when cuneiform astronomical sources became available to the scholarly public. The dominant positivism in philosophy of science of this time influenced criteria employed in defining and demarcating science by historians, resulting in a persistently negative assessment of the nature of knowledge evidenced in cuneiform sources. Ancient Near Eastern astronomy was deemed pre- or non-scientific, and even taken to reflect a stage (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La voz de los artesanos en el Renacimiento científico: cosmógrafos y cartógrafos en el preludio de la “nueva filosofía natural”.Antonio Sánchez - 2010 - Arbor 186 (743):449-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What’s Wrong with Talking About the Scientific Revolution? Applying Lessons from History of Science to Applied Fields of Science Studies.Lindy A. Orthia - 2016 - Minerva 54 (3):353-373.
    Since the mid-twentieth century, the ‘Scientific Revolution’ has arguably occupied centre stage in most Westerners’, and many non-Westerners’, conceptions of science history. Yet among history of science specialists that position has been profoundly contested. Most radically, historians Andrew Cunningham and Perry Williams in 1993 proposed to demolish the prevailing ‘big picture’ which posited that the Scientific Revolution marked the origin of modern science. They proposed a new big picture in which science is seen as a distinctly modern, western phenomenon rather (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The pen and the sword: recovering the disciplinary identity of physiology and anatomy before 1800.Andrew Cunningham - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):631-665.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • A History of Universalism: Conceptions of the Internationality of Science from the Enlightenment to the Cold War. [REVIEW]Geert J. Somsen - 2008 - Minerva 46 (3):361-379.
    That science is fundamentally universal has been proclaimed innumerable times. But the precise geographical meaning of this universality has changed historically. This article examines conceptions of scientific internationalism from the Enlightenment to the Cold War, and their varying relations to cosmopolitanism, nationalism, socialism, and ‘the West’. These views are confronted with recent tendencies to cast science as a uniquely European product.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Athanasius Kircher’s magical instruments: an essay on ‘science’, ‘religion’ and applied metaphysics.Koen Vermeir - 2007 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 38 (2):363-400.
    In this paper I endeavour to bridge the gap between the history of material culture and the history of ideas. I do this by focussing on the intersection between metaphysics and technology—what I call ‘applied metaphysics’—in the oeuvre of the Jesuit scholar Athanasius Kircher. By scrutinising the interplay between texts, objects and images in Kircher’s work, it becomes possible to describe the multiplicity of meanings related to his artefacts. I unearth as yet overlooked metaphysical and religious meanings of the camera (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Setting Up A Discipline, Ii: British history of science and “the end of ideology”, 1931–1948.Anna-K. Mayer - 2004 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (1):41-72.
    For the history of science the 1940s were a transformative decade, when salient scholars like Herbert Butterfield or Alexandre Koyré set out to shape postwar culture by promoting new standards for understanding science. Some years ago I placed these developments in a tradition of enduring arts–science tensions and the contemporary notion that previous, “scientistic”, historical practices needed to be confronted with disinterested codes of historical craft. Here, I want to further explore the ideological dimensions of the processes through which the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The Romantic Machine: Utopian Science and Technology after Napoleon. [REVIEW]Guillaume Carnino - 2013 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 44 (4):608-612.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The pen and the Sword: Recovering the disciplinary identity of physiology and anatomy before 1800 - I: Old physiology-the pen.Andrew Cunningham - 2002 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33 (4):631-665.
    It is argued that the disciplinary identity of anatomy and physiology before 1800 are unknown to us due to the subsequent creation, success and historiographical dominance of a different discipline-experimental physiology. The first of these two papers deals with the identity of physiology from its revival in the 1530s, and demonstrates that it was a theoretical, not an experimental, discipline, achieved with the mind and the pen, not the hand and the knife. The physiological work of Jean Fernel, Albrecht von (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Inventing the Scientific Revolution.James A. Secord - 2023 - Isis 114 (1):50-76.
    As a master narrative for understanding the emergence of the modern world, the concept of a seventeenth-century scientific revolution has been central to the history of science. It is generally believed that this key analytical framework was created in Europe and became widely used for the first time during the Cold War through the writings of Herbert Butterfield and Alexander Koyré. This view, however, is mistaken. The scientific revolution is largely a product of debates about social reconstruction in the United (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Introduction: Rethinking History of Science in the Anthropocene.Lukas M. Verburgt & Elske de Waal - 2022 - Isis 113 (2):366-376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hacking’s historical epistemology: a critique of styles of reasoning.Martin Kusch - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (2):158-173.
    The paper begins with a detailed reconstruction of the development of Ian Hacking’s theory of scientific ‘styles of reasoning’, paying particular attention to Alistair Crombie’s influence, and suggesting that Hacking’s theory deserves to come under the title ‘historical epistemology’. Subsequently, the paper seeks to establish three critical theses. First, Hacking’s reliance on Crombie leads him to adopt an outdated historiographical position; second, Hacking is unsuccessful in his attempt to distance historical epistemology from epistemic relativism; and third, Hacking has not offered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Microstudies versus big picture accounts?Soraya de Chadarevian - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 40 (1):13-19.
    Microstudies and big picture accounts are often counterposed. This paper investigates the supposed dichotomy between the two historiographical approaches. In particular it investigates how the discussions are reflected in the historiography of molecular biology and the special questions posed by the disciplinary context. Taking inspiration from the microhistory tradition as exemplified by the works of Carlo Ginzburg, Jacques Revel, and David Sabean among others, the paper highlights the heuristic value of microstudies to reconstruct the multiple contexts that link apparently small (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Selection, presentism, and pluralist history.Hakob Barseghyan - 2022 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 92 (C):60-70.
    Despite a growing body of literature that attempts to draw a line between legitimate and illegitimate forms of presentism in academic history, ‘avoid presentism’ is still often preached as the first rule of historiography. Distinct from other forms of presentism is selective presentism – the practice of taking some present-day activity, event, idea, or problem as a starting point in our selection of historical facts. Throughout the paper I examine the relation of some of the most popular selection criteria – (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Découvertes Médicales et Philosophie de la Nature Humaine.Stefanie Buchenau, Claire Crignon, Marie Gaille, Delphine Kolesnik-Antoine & Anne-Lise Rey - 2013 - Revue de Synthèse 134 (4):537-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rethinking ‘style’ for historians and philosophers of science: converging lessons from sexuality, translation, and East Asian studies.Howard H. Chiang - 2009 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 40 (2):109-118.
    Historians and philosophers of science have furnished a wide array of theoretical-historiographical terms to emphasize the discontinuities among different systems of knowledge. Some of the most famous include Thomas Kuhn’s “paradigm”, Michel Foucault’s “episteme”, and the notion of “styles of reasoning” more recently developed by Ian Hacking and Arnold Davidson. This paper takes up this theoretical-historiographical thread by assessing the values and limitations of the notion of “style” for the historical and philosophical study of science. Specifically, reflecting on various methodological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Book review. [REVIEW]Jennifer Croissant, John Angus Campbell, Richard C. Jennings, Robert G. Hudson, Paul Rosen, Linda L. Layne, Roland Bal & Dhruv Raina - 1998 - Social Epistemology 12 (2):153-213.
    Invention by Design: How Engineers Get from Thought to Thing by Henry PetroskiBut Is It Science? The Philosophical Question in the Creation/Evolution Controversy by Michael RuseImpure Science: Aids, Activism and the Politics of Knowledge by Steven EpsteinA purposeless history and a ‘ Brave New World’ for animalsCity of Bits: Space, Place and the Infobahn by William J. Mitchell and Telecommunications and the City: Electronic Spaces, Urban Places by Stephen Graham and Simon MarvinExpecting Trouble: Surrogacy, Fetal Abuse & New Reproductive Technologies (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Autonomy and Objectivity of Science.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2012 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 26 (3):309-334.
    This article deals with the problematic concepts of the rational and the social, which have been typically seen as dichotomous in the history and philosophy of science literature. I argue that this view is mistaken and that the social can be seen as something that enables rationality in science, and further, that a scientific community as well as an individual can be taken as an epistemic subject. Furthermore, I consider how scientific communities could be seen as freely acting and choosing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Life and Thought of Herbert Butterfield: History, Science and God.Herman Paul - 2012 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 26 (2):232-235.
    (2012). The Life and Thought of Herbert Butterfield: History, Science and God. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science: Vol. 26, No. 2, pp. 232-235. doi: 10.1080/02698595.2012.703485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflexivity, Relativism, Microhistory: Three Desiderata for Historical Epistemologies. [REVIEW]Martin Kusch - 2011 - Erkenntnis 75 (3):483-494.
    This paper tries to motivate three desiderata for historical epistemologies: (a) that they should be reflective about the pedigree of their conceptual apparatus; (b) that they must face up to the potentially relativistic consequences of their historicism; and (c) that they must not forget the hard-won lessons of microhistory (i.e. historical events must be explained causally; historical events must not be artificially divided into internal/intellectual and external/social “factors” or “levels”; and constructed series of homogenous events must not be treated as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Magnets, Magic, and Other Anomalies: In Defense of Methodological Naturalism.John Perry & Sarah Lane Ritchie - 2018 - Zygon 53 (4):1064-1093.
    Recent critiques of methodological naturalism (MN) claim that it fails by conflicting with Christian belief and being insufficiently humble. We defend MN by tracing the real history of the debate, contending that the story as it is usually told is mythic. We show how MN works in practice, including among real scientists. The debate is a red herring. It only appears problematic because of confusion among its opponents about how scientists respond to experimental anomalies. We conclude by introducing our preferred (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Working Knowledges Before and After circa 1800.John V. Pickstone - 2007 - Isis 98 (3):489-516.
    ABSTRACT Historians of science, inasmuch as they are concerned with knowledges and practices rather than institutions, have tended of late to focus on case studies of common processes such as experiment and publication. In so doing, they tend to treat science as a single category, with various local instantiations. Or, alternatively, they relate cases to their specific local contexts. In neither approach do the cases or their contexts build easily into broader histories, reconstructing changing knowledge practices across time and space. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • What needs to be explained about modern science? [REVIEW]Diederick Raven - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Science 44 (3):449-454.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Civil Scientists: Dutch Scientists between 1750 and 1875.Ad Maas - 2010 - History of Science 48 (1):75-103.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inventing scientific method: The privilege system as a model for scientific knowledge-production.Marius Buning - 2014 - Intellectual History Review 24 (1):59-70.
    This paper argues that the development of early-modern science was strongly influenced by prevailing legal practices.1 This argument goes back to the work of Barbara Shapiro, who explored in a numb...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shapin's the scientific revolution: What will philosophers find? [REVIEW]K. Brad Wray - 1999 - Social Epistemology 13 (3 & 4):331 – 335.
    This is a book review of Steven Shapin's The Scientific Revolution.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Layered history: Styles of reasoning as stratified conditions of possibility.James Elwick - 2012 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 43 (4):619-627.
    This paper depicts Ian Hacking’s ‘styles of reasoning’ as conditions of possibility. After distinguishing between possibilities and causes, it articulates the implicit stratigraphical metaphor used to describe the relationship between different conditions of possibility, with ‘lower’ layers being necessary for ‘higher’ ones. It notes the use of this stratigraphical metaphor in the work of multiple scholars in history and in science studies. The paper suggests three ways in which this model can be useful: clarifying the definition and use of ‘context’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Book review. [REVIEW]Luc Foisneau, John Hedley Brooke, Katherine J. Morris, Desmond M. Clarke, John Stephens, Bruce Haddock, Robert Stern, José A. Robles & Philip Stratton‐Lake - 1995 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 3 (2):441-472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Poetics of Physics.Chris Jeynes, Michael C. Parker & Margaret Barker - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (1):3.
    Physics has been thought to truly represent reality since at least Galileo, and the foundations of physics are always established using philosophical ideas. In particular, the elegant naming of physical entities is usually very influential in the acceptance of physical theories. We here demonstrate (using current developments in thermodynamics as an example) that both the epistemology and the ontology of physics ultimately rest on poetic language. What we understand depends essentially on the language we use. We wish to establish our (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Historiogaphy of Not-so-recent Science.Peter Dear - 2012 - History of Science 50 (2):197-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The History of Science and the History of Microscopy.Ann La Berge - 1999 - Perspectives on Science 7 (1):111-142.
    These three books illustrate some key themes in the history of science and the history of microscopy. First is a new enthusiasm among some historians and philosophers of science to embrace the history of microscopy as an area worthy of study, a recognized area of investigation for the historian and philosopher of science. In so doing these historians have redefined the subject area from the more traditional and much researched history of microscopes, with its emphasis on the technical, to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Will the real scientists please stand up? dead ends and live issues in the explanation of scientific knowledge.Paul A. Roth - 1996 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 27 (1):43-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The modern invention of “science‐and‐religion”: What follows?Peter Harrison - 2016 - Zygon 51 (3):742-757.
    I am grateful to the four reviewers of The Territories of Science and Religion for their careful and insightful readings of the book, and their kind words about it. They all got the central arguments pretty much right, and thus any critical comments are not the result of fundamental misunderstandings. While there are some common themes in the assessments, each reviewer, happily, has offered a distinct perspective on the book. For this reason I will deal with their comments in turn, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • De Volder’s Cartesian Physics and Experimental Pedagogy.Tammy Nyden - 2013 - In Mihnea Dobre Tammy Nyden (ed.), Cartesian Empiricisms. Dordrecht: Springer.
    In 1675, Burchard de Volder (1643–1709) was the first professor to introduce the demonstration of experiment into a university physics course and built the Leiden Physics Theatre to accommodate this new pedagogy. When he requested the funds from the university to build the facility, he claimed that the performance of experiments would demonstrate the “truth and certainty” of the postulates of theoretical physics. Such a claim is interesting given de Volder’s lifelong commitment to Cartesian scientia. This chapter will examine de (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ideology of modern science. [REVIEW]Peter Dear - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (4):821-828.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Religion, science and natural philosophy: thoughts on Cunningham's thesis.Peter Dear - 2001 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 32 (2):377-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Anachronism and retrospective explanation: in defence of a present-centred history of science.Nick Tosh - 2003 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 34 (3):647-659.
    This paper defends the right of historians to make use of their knowledge of the remote consequences of past actions. In particular, it is argued that the disciplinary cohesion of the history of science relies crucially upon our ability to target, for further investigation, those past activities ancestral to modern science. The history of science is not limited to the study of those activities but it is structured around them. In this sense, the discipline is inherently ‘present-centred’: its boundaries are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Lab History: Reflections.Robert Kohler - 2008 - Isis 99 (4):761-768.
    ABSTRACT After a productive start in the 1980s, laboratory history is now surprisingly neglected—not lab science, but the lab as social institution. To restart interest, I suggest that we see labs as period specific (early modern, modern, postmodern) and of a piece with each era's dominant social institutions and practices. In the modern era, for example, labs have become powerful and ubiquitous because their operating principles are those of the nation-state and its consumerist political economy. Their educational function is crucial: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Naturecultures? Science, Affect and the Non-human.Joanna Latimer & Mara Miele - 2013 - Theory, Culture and Society 30 (7-8):5-31.
    Rather than focus on effects, the isolatable and measureable outcomes of events and interventions, the papers assembled here offer different perspectives on the affective dimension of the meaning and politics of human/non-human relations. The authors begin by drawing attention to the constructed discontinuity between humans and non-humans, and to the kinds of knowledge and socialities that this discontinuity sustains, including those underpinned by nature-culture, subject-object, body-mind, individual-society polarities. The articles presented track human/non-human relations through different domains, including: humans/non-humans in history (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Conceptual Frameworks on the Relationship Between Physics–Mathematics in the Newton Principia Geneva Edition (1822).Raffaele Pisano & Paolo Bussotti - 2022 - Foundations of Science 27 (3).
    The aim of this paper is twofold: (1) to show the principal aspects of the way in which Newton conceived his mathematical concepts and methods and applied them to rational mechanics in his Principia; (2) to explain how the editors of the Geneva Edition interpreted, clarified, and made accessible to a broader public Newton’s perfect but often elliptic proofs. Following this line of inquiry, we will explain the successes of Newton’s mechanics, but also the problematic aspects of his perfect geometrical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • De-anthropomorphizing energy and energy conservation: The case of Max Planck and Ernst Mach.Daan Wegener - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 41 (2):146-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • “Writing in Letters of Blood”: Manners in Scientific Dispute in Nineteenth-Century Britain and the German Lands.Raf de Bont - 2013 - History of Science 51 (3):309-335.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Senses of Localism.Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen - 2012 - History of Science 50 (4):477-500.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Charlatan epistemology: As illustrated by a study of wonder-working in the late seventeenth-century Dutch Republic.Koen Vermeir - 2020 - Science in Context 33 (4):363-384.
    ArgumentThis article highlights the epistemic concerns that have permeated the historical discourse around charlatanism. In it, I study the term “charlatan” as a multivalent actor’s category without a stable referent. Instead of defining or identifying “the charlatan,” I analyze how the concept of the charlatan was used to make epistemic interventions about what constituted credible knowledge in two interconnected controversies. Focusing on these controversies allows me to thematize how the concept of “the charlatan” expanded beyond medical contexts and to bring (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations