Switch to: References

Citations of:

Brainstorms

MIT Press (1978)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The egg revealed.William S. Verplanck - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):605-606.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is human information processing conscious?Max Velmans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):651-69.
    Investigations of the function of consciousness in human information processing have focused mainly on two questions: (1) where does consciousness enter into the information processing sequence and (2) how does conscious processing differ from preconscious and unconscious processing. Input analysis is thought to be initially "preconscious," "pre-attentive," fast, involuntary, and automatic. This is followed by "conscious," "focal-attentive" analysis which is relatively slow, voluntary, and flexible. It is thought that simple, familiar stimuli can be identified preconsciously, but conscious processing is needed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   348 citations  
  • Is the mind conscious, functional, or both?Max Velmans - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):629-630.
    What, in essence, characterizes the mind? According to Searle, the potential to be conscious provides the only definitive criterion. Thus, conscious states are unquestionably "mental"; "shallow unconscious" states are also "mental" by virtue of their capacity to be conscious (at least in principle); but there are no "deep unconscious mental states" - i.e. those rules and procedures without access to consciousness, inferred by cognitive science to characterize the operations of the unconscious mind are not mental at all. Indeed, according to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Common sense, functional theories and knowledge of the mind.Max Velmans - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):85-86.
    A commentary on a target article by Alison Gopnik (1993) How we know our minds: the illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality. Focusing on evidence of how children acquire a theory of mind, this commentary argues that there are internal inconsistencies in theories that both argue for the functional role of conscious experiences and the irreducibility of those experiences to third-person viewable information processing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness from a first-person perspective.Max Velmans - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):702-726.
    This paper replies to the first 36 commentaries on my target article on “Is human information processing conscious?” (Behavioral and Brain Sciences,1991, pp.651-669). The target article focused largely on experimental studies of how consciousness relates to human information processing, tracing their relation from input through to output, while discussion of the implications of the findings both for cognitive psychology and philosophy of mind was relatively brief. The commentaries reversed this emphasis, and so, correspondingly, did the reply. The sequence of topics (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   132 citations  
  • Infant intentionality as object directedness: An alternative to representationalism.Dankert Vedeler - 1991 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 21 (4):431–448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Giving up the ghost.William Vaughan - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):501-501.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionality, Normativity and Naturalism.Somogy Varga - 2015 - Philosophia 43 (3):611-624.
    Hutto and Satne review current attempts to provide a naturalized content and underline some of the most convincing reasons why they remain inadequate. The authors reframe and update Haugeland’s assessment of this research program, but besides describing the particular challenges facing the different candidate accounts, they also propose what seems to be a promising way to further a debate that has not advanced in recent years. In this paper I argue that a more detailed exploration of some aspects of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The intentionality of formal systems.Ard Van Moer - 2006 - Foundations of Science 11 (1-2):81-119.
    One of the most interesting and entertaining philosophical discussions of the last few decades is the discussion between Daniel Dennett and John Searle on the existence of intrinsic intentionality. Dennett denies the existence of phenomena with intrinsic intentionality. Searle, however, is convinced that some mental phenomena exhibit intrinsic intentionality. According to me, this discussion has been obscured by some serious misunderstandings with regard to the concept ‘intrinsic intentionality’. For instance, most philosophers fail to realize that it is possible that the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Schemata and representational constraints.Cees van Leeuwen - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):448-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness is not a natural kind.J. van Brakel - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):269-270.
    Blocks distinction between “phenomenal feel” consciousness and “thought/cognition” consciousness is a cultural construction. Consciousness (and its “subspecies”) is not a natural kind. Some crosscultural data are presented to support this.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teleological explanations and their relation to causal explanation in psychology.Elizabeth R. Valentine - 1988 - Philosophical Psychology 1 (1):61-68.
    The relation of teleological to causal explanations in psychology is examined. Nagel's claim that they are logically equivalent is rejected. Two arguments for their non-equivalence are considered: (i) the impossibility of specifying initial conditions in the case of teleological explanations and (ii) the claim that different kinds of logic are involved. The view that causal explanations provide only necessary conditions whereas teleological explanations provide sufficient conditions is rejected: causal explanations can provide sufficient conditions, typically being unable to provide necessary ones, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Content externalism and the epistemic conception of the self.Brie Gertler - 2007 - Philosophical Issues 17 (1):37-56.
    Our fundamental conception of the self seems to be, broadly speaking, epistemic: selves are things that have thoughts, undergo experiences, and possess reasons for action and belief. In this paper, I evaluate the consequences of this epistemic conception for the widespread view that properties like thinking that arthritis is painful are relational features of the self.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Verbal reports and visual awareness.Geoffrey Underwood - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attention is necessary for word integration.Geoffrey Underwood - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):698-698.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conscious and unconscious representation of aspectual shape in cognitive science.Geoffrey Underwood - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):628-629.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Perception, information, and computation.S. Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):408-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Unintended thought and nonconscious inferences exist.James S. Uleman & Jennifer K. Uleman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):627-628.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Blindsight, orgasm, and representational overlap.Michael Tye - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):268-269.
    It is argued that there is no fallacy in the reasoning in the example of the thirsty blindsight subject, on one reconstruction of that reasoning. Neither the case of orgasm nor the case of a visual versus an auditory experience as of something overheard shows that phenomenal content is not representational.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • L. J. Cohen, again: On the evaluation of inductive intuitions.Amos Tversky - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (3):354-356.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The reign of pain fails mainly in the brain.Dennis C. Turk & Peter Salovey - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intentionally: A problem of multiple reference frames, specificational information, and extraordinary boundary conditions on natural law.M. T. Turvey - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (1):153-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Schemas: Not yet an interlingua for the brain sciences.John K. Tsotsos - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):447-448.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Belief attribution in science: Folk psychology under theoretical stress.J. D. Trout - 1991 - Synthese 87 (June):379-400.
    Some eliminativists have predicted that a developed neuroscience will eradicate the principles and theoretical kinds (belief, desire, etc.) implicit in our ordinary practices of mental state attribution. Prevailing defenses of common-sense psychology infer its basic integrity from its familiarity and instrumental success in everyday social commerce. Such common-sense defenses charge that eliminativist arguments are self-defeating in their folk psychological appeal to the belief that eliminativism is true. I argue that eliminativism is untouched by this simple charge of inconsistency, and introduce (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The secret operations of the mind.Saul Traiger - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (3):303-315.
    For my part, my only hope is, that I may contribute a little to the advancement of knowledge, by giving in some particulars a different turn to the speculations of philosophers, and pointing out to them more distinctly those subjects, where alone they can expect assurance and conviction.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semantic responsibility.Josefa Toribio - 2002 - Philosophical Explorations 5 (1):39-58.
    In this paper I attempt to develop a notion of responsibility (semantic responsibility) that is to the notion of belief what epistemic responsibility is to the notion of justification. 'Being semantically responsible' is shown to involve the fulfilment of cognitive duties which allow the agent to engage in the kind of reason-laden discourses which render her beliefs appropriately sensitive to correction. The concept of semantic responsibility suggests that the notion of belief found in contemporary philosophical debates about content implicitly encompasses (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mindful belief: Accountability, expertise, and cognitive kinds.Josefa Toribio - 2002 - Theoria 68 (3):224-49.
    It is sometimes said that humans are unlike other animals in at least one crucial respect. We do not simply form beliefs, desires and other mental states, but are capable of caring about our mental states in a distinctive way. We can care about the justification of our beliefs, and about the desirability of our desires. This kind of observation is usually made in discussions of free will and moral responsibility. But it has profound consequences, or so I shall argue, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Blindsight: Not all unexpected findings are experimental artifacts.Tore Torjussen & Svein Magnussen - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Where's the person?Michael Tomasello - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):84-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Rejecting induction: Using occam's razor too soon.J. T. Tolliver - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):669-670.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models, yes; homunculus, no.Frederick M. Toates - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):650.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Selection by consequences: A universal causal mode?William Timberlake - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):499-501.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why Alison Gopnik should be a behaviorist.Nicholas S. Thompson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):83-84.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Vehicles all the way down?Nicholas S. Thompson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):638-638.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Freedom of Judgment.Mark Thomas Walker - 2003 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 11 (1):63-92.
    This is the sequel to my paper 'Against One Form of Judgment-Determinism' ( IJPS , May 2001), wherein I argued that theoretical rationalization, that is, the forming of judgments by way of inference from other judgments, cannot simply be identified with any kind of predetermination of conclusion-judgments by premise-judgments. Taking 'free' to mean 'neither mechanistically explicable nor random' (where something is mechanistically explicable if and only if it is either predetermined or probabilified in a certain way, and is random if (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are theories of imagery theories of imagination? An active perception approach to conscious mental content.Nigel J. T. Thomas - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (2):207-245.
    Can theories of mental imagery, conscious mental contents, developed within cognitive science throw light on the obscure (but culturally very significant) concept of imagination? Three extant views of mental imagery are considered: quasi‐pictorial, description, and perceptual activity theories. The first two face serious theoretical and empirical difficulties. The third is (for historically contingent reasons) little known, theoretically underdeveloped, and empirically untried, but has real explanatory potential. It rejects the “traditional” symbolic computational view of mental contents, but is compatible with recentsituated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Are radical and cognitive behaviorism incompatible?Roger K. Thomas - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):650.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The pragmatics of induction.Paul Thagard - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):668-669.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Parallel computation and the mind-body problem.Paul Thagard - 1986 - Cognitive Science 10 (3):301-18.
    states are to be understood in terms of their functional relationships to other mental states, not in terms of their material instantiation in any particular kind of hardware. But the argument that material instantiation is irrelevant to functional..
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • Nonhuman intentional systems.H. S. Terrace - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):378-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Mental way stations” in contemporary theories of animal learning.William S. Terry - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):649.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Clinical artificial intelligence.Virginia Teller & Hartvig Dahl - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):549-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The possibility of irreducible intentionality.Charles Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):626-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is Having Contradictory Beliefs Possible? Discussion and Critique of Arguments for the Psychological Principle of Non-Contradiction.Maciej Tarnowski - 2020 - Studia Semiotyczne—English Supplement 31:91-126.
    The aim of this paper is to present and analyze arguments provided for the Psychological Principle of Non-Contradiction which states that one cannot have, or cannot be described as having, contradictory beliefs. By differentiating two possible interpretations of PNC, descriptive and normative, and examining arguments provided for each of them separately I point out the flaws in reasoning in these arguments and difficulties with aligning PNC with the empirical data provided by research done in cognitive and clinical psychology. I claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The computing frog.G. Székely - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):446-446.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is PARRY paranoid?David W. Swanson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):548-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representing practice in cognitive science.LucyA Suchman - 1988 - Human Studies 11 (2-3):305 - 325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How to think about rules and rule following.Karsten R. Stueber - 2005 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (3):307-323.
    This article will discuss the difficulties of providing a plausible account of rule following in the social realm. It will show that the cognitive model of rule following is not suited for this task. Nevertheless, revealing the inadequacy of the cognitive model does not justify the wholesale dismissal of understanding human practices as rule-following practices, as social theorists like Bourdieu or Dreyfus have argued. Instead it will be shown that rule-following behavior is best understood as being based on a set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • The essential moral self.Nina Strohminger & Shaun Nichols - 2014 - Cognition 131 (1):159-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   151 citations