Switch to: References

Citations of:

Brainstorms: Philosophical Essays on Mind and Psychology

Cambridge, Massachusetts: Bradford Books (1978)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Verbal hallucinations also occur in normals.Thomas B. Posey - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):530-530.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The importance of connective tissue within and between muscles.Caroline M. Pond - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):562-562.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Structured Thoughts: The Spatial-Motor View.Benoit Hardy-Vallée & Pierre Poirier - 2005 - In Gerhard Schurz, Edouard Machery & Markus Werning (eds.), Applications to Linguistics, Psychology and Neuroscience. De Gruyter. pp. 229-250.
    Is thinking necessarily linguistic? Do we think with words, to use Bermudez’s (2003) phrase? Or does thinking occur in some other, yet to be determined, representational format? Or again do we think in various formats, switching from one to the other as tasks demand? In virtue perhaps of the ambiguous na- ture of first-person introspective data on the matter, philosophers have tradition- ally disagreed on this question, some thinking that thought had to be pictorial, other insisting that it could not (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unified cognition misses language.Csaba Pléh - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):451-453.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The behavior of self-control.Joseph J. Plaud - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):139-140.
    Rachlin's view of self-control as a sequence or chain of behaviors is contrasted with traditional behavioral analyses of self-control which emphasize a simplistic interpretation of the hyperbolic function relating small-sooner (SS) and larger-later (LL) reinforcers to specific behaviors. The validity of Rachlin's teleological analysis is examined in relation to the acquisition and steady-state performance of self-control behaviors. Central to an analysis of self-control is the functional difference between behavior under the control of SS and LL reinforcers, because SS-reinforced behavior is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuroethological analysis of central pattern generators.Harold M. Pinsker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):559-560.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thoughts and Belief Ascriptions.Pierre Jacob - 1987 - Mind and Language 2 (4):301-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Computationalism, The Church–Turing Thesis, and the Church–Turing Fallacy.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2007 - Synthese 154 (1):97-120.
    The Church–Turing Thesis (CTT) is often employed in arguments for computationalism. I scrutinize the most prominent of such arguments in light of recent work on CTT and argue that they are unsound. Although CTT does nothing to support computationalism, it is not irrelevant to it. By eliminating misunderstandings about the relationship between CTT and computationalism, we deepen our appreciation of computationalism as an empirical hypothesis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Alan Turing and the mathematical objection.Gualtiero Piccinini - 2003 - Minds and Machines 13 (1):23-48.
    This paper concerns Alan Turing’s ideas about machines, mathematical methods of proof, and intelligence. By the late 1930s, Kurt Gödel and other logicians, including Turing himself, had shown that no finite set of rules could be used to generate all true mathematical statements. Yet according to Turing, there was no upper bound to the number of mathematical truths provable by intelligent human beings, for they could invent new rules and methods of proof. So, the output of a human mathematician, for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Social and psychological influences on hypnotic behavior.Campbell Perry & Jean-Roch Laurence - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):478-479.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Exploring the “boundary” between the minds of monkeys and humans.Sidney I. Perloe - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):163-164.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Critical Study Velleman: Self to Self.John Perry - 2010 - Noûs 44 (4):740-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • At what level will pattern generators be understood?V. W. Pentreath - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (4):559-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Explanation in Computational Psychology: Language, Perception and Level 1.5.Christopher Peacocke - 1986 - Mind and Language 1 (2):101-123.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • Content, computation, and externalism.Christopher Peacocke - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):227-264.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • How was movement controlled before Newton?Lloyd D. Partridge - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):561-561.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Collectivism on the horizon: A challenge to Pettit's critique of collectivism.Katarzyna Paprzycka - 1998 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (2):165 – 181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Don't just sit there, optimise something.J. H. P. Paelinck - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):230-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Calls as labels: An intriguing theme, but one with limitations.Donald H. Owings - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):162-163.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking is a difficult habit to break.Geir Overskeid - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):138-139.
    Self-control is in the eye of the beholder. However, we speak of if a person has come to think conscious thoughts that change the motivational value of stimuli in the outside world. It is claimed that conscious thinking, and not habits bordering on compulsion, is behind self-control.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hypnotic experience: A cognitive social-psychological reality.Martin T. Orne, David F. Dinges & Emily Carota Orne - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):477-478.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Pettit's thought ascription to groups.Kanit Sirichan - 2024 - Asian Journal of Philosophy 3 (1):1-18.
    A thought, taken as a propositional attitude or the content of psychological predicates such as believe, wish, desire, hope, is ascribed to an entity with mental states. A thought is not only allegedly ascribed to particular non-mental things like computer, book, it is also ascribed to non-material things, linguistically in plural terms, e.g. plural pronouns (e.g. we, they), collective names or singular proper names (e.g. the United States), proper names in plural form or general terms (e.g. the Microsoft, feminists). Plural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Brain physiology and the unconscious initiation of movements.R. Näätänen - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):549-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • From Representation to Thirdness and Representamen to Medium: Evolution of Peircean Key Terms and Topics.Winfried Nöth - 2011 - Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 47 (4):445-481.
    The nature of representation has been a central but controversial issue of cognitive philosophy. After 2,500 years of reflection (cf. Rolf 2006), opinions are still divided. On the one hand, there are those who are convinced that we have reached a crisis of representation in the arts, the media, and cultural theory; on the other hand, representation has remained right at the top of the agenda of cognitive science and Artificial Intelligence research (cf. Nöth & Ljungberg, eds. 2003; Nöth 1997). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Heartbreak of Semantics.Norbert Hornstein - 1988 - Mind and Language 3 (1):9-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What are mental states?William Noble & Iain Davidson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):162-162.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflex action in the context of motor control.T. Richard Nichols - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):559-560.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • The intentional stance and the knowledge level.Allen Newell - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):520.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • SOAR as a unified theory of cognition: Issues and explanations.Allen Newell - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):464-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Précis of Unified theories of cognition.Allen Newell - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):425-437.
    The book presents the case that cognitive science should turn its attention to developing theories of human cognition that cover the full range of human perceptual, cognitive, and action phenomena. Cognitive science has now produced a massive number of high-quality regularities with many microtheories that reveal important mechanisms. The need for integration is pressing and will continue to increase. Equally important, cognitive science now has the theoretical concepts and tools to support serious attempts at unified theories. The argument is made (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Machine understanding and the chinese room.Natika Newton - 1989 - Philosophical Psychology 2 (2):207-15.
    John Searle has argued that one can imagine embodying a machine running any computer program without understanding the symbols, and hence that purely computational processes do not yield understanding. The disagreement this argument has generated stems, I hold, from ambiguity in talk of 'understanding'. The concept is analysed as a relation between subjects and symbols having two components: a formal and an intentional. The central question, then becomes whether a machine could possess the intentional component with or without the formal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Reconsidering pain.Norton Nelkin - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (3):325-43.
    In 1986, I argued that pains are essentially not phenomenal states. Using a Wittgen-steinian son of argument, I showed that the same sort of phenomena can be had on different occasions, and on one occasion persons be in pain, while on another occasion persons not be in pain. I also showed that very different phenomena could be experienced and, yet, organisms have the same sort of pain. I supported my arguments with empirical data from both laboratory and clinical studies. There (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • On the content of representations.R. J. Nelson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Patterns.Norton Nelkin - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):56-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Naturalizing intentions.R. J. Nelson - 1984 - Synthese 61 (2):173 - 203.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Libet's dualism.R. J. Nelson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):550-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Illusions about Persons.James Lindemann Nelson - 2007 - American Journal of Bioethics 7 (1):65-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Tonic stretch reflex during voluntary activity.Peter D. Neilson - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):559-559.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Machine intelligence (MI), competence and creativity.Rajakishore Nath - 2009 - AI and Society 23 (3):441-458.
    In mid-twentieth century, the hypothesis, ‘a machine can think’ became very popular after, Alan Turing’s article on ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence’. This hypothesis, ‘a machine can think’ established the foundations of machine intelligence (MI), and claimed that machines have consciousness and creativity, with the power to compete with human beings. In the first section, I shall show how consciousness and creativity is conceptualized in the domain of MI. The main aim of MI is not only to construct difficult programs to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Can naturalism explain consciousness? A critique.Rajakishore Nath - 2017 - AI and Society 32 (4):563-571.
    The problem of consciousness is one of the most important problems both in cognitive science and in philosophy. There are different philosophers and different scientists who define consciousness and explain it differently. In philosophy, ‘consciousness’ does not have a definition in terms of genus and differentia or necessary and sufficient conditions. In this paper, I shall explore the very idea of machine consciousness. The machine consciousness has offered causal explanation to the ‘how’ and ‘what’ of consciousness, but they fail to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Against phenomenal objects.Thomas Natsoulas - 1980 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 10 (2):97–114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Alan Turing’s Concept of Mind.Rajakishore Nath - 2020 - Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research 37 (1):31-50.
    In the mid of nineteenth century, the hypothesis, “machine can think,” became very popular after Alan Turing’s article on “Computing Machinery and Intelligence.” This hypothesis, “machine can think,” established the foundations of machine intelligence and claimed that machines have a mind. It has the power to compete with human beings. In the first section, I shall explore the importance of Turing thesis, which has been conceptualized in the domain of machine intelligence. Turing presented a completely different view of the machine (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hypnosis: Towards a rational explanation of irrational behaviour.Peter L. N. Naish - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):476-477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some thoughts on the proper foundations for the study of cognition in animals.Lynn Nadel - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):383-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Overcoming addiction through abstract patterns.Jesus Mosterin - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (1):137-138.
    You cannot overcome addiction or impulsiveness through abstract patterns alone. They show you the way to go, but do not fuel the effort. Some further variable is needed in the equation, some internal force or motivational mechanism, whatever its nature. Overlooking this leads to a neo-Socratic exaggeration of the role of cognition in selfcontrol.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representations gone mental.Alex Morgan - 2014 - Synthese 191 (2):213-244.
    Many philosophers and psychologists have attempted to elucidate the nature of mental representation by appealing to notions like isomorphism or abstract structural resemblance. The ‘structural representations’ that these theorists champion are said to count as representations by virtue of functioning as internal models of distal systems. In his 2007 book, Representation Reconsidered, William Ramsey endorses the structural conception of mental representation, but uses it to develop a novel argument against representationalism, the widespread view that cognition essentially involves the manipulation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • Intentionality: Some Lessons from the History of the Problem from Brentano to the Present.Dermot Moran - 2013 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 21 (3):317-358.
    Intentionality (‘directedness’, ‘aboutness’) is both a central topic in contemporary philosophy of mind, phenomenology and the cognitive sciences, and one of the themes with which both analytic and Continental philosophers have separately engaged starting from Brentano and Edmund Husserl’s ground-breaking Logical Investigations (1901) through Roderick M. Chisholm, Daniel C. Dennett’s The Intentional Stance, John Searle’s Intentionality, to the recent work of Tim Crane, Robert Brandom, Shaun Gallagher and Dan Zahavi, among many others. In this paper, I shall review recent discussions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • How modest is the gain of the stretch reflex?James A. Mortimer & Peter Eisenberg - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):557-558.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious decisions.Chris Mortensen - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):548-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The infinite regress of optimization.Philippe Mongin - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (2):229-230.
    A comment on Paul Schoemaker's target article in Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 14 (1991), p. 205-215, "The Quest for Optimality: A Positive Heuristic of Science?" (https://doi.org/10.1017/S0140525X00066140). This comment argues that the optimizing model of decision leads to an infinite regress, once internal costs of decision (i.e., information and computation costs) are duly taken into account.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark