Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell

Northwestern University Press (1944)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Causal Slingshots.Michael Baumgartner - 2010 - Erkenntnis 72 (1):111-133.
    Causal slingshots are formal arguments advanced by proponents of an event ontology of token-level causation which, in the end, are intended to show two things: (i) The logical form of statements expressing causal dependencies on token level features a binary predicate ‘‘... causes ...’’ and (ii) that predicate takes events as arguments. Even though formalisms are only revealing with respect to the logical form of natural language statements, if the latter are shown to be adequately captured within a corresponding formalism, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Une grammaire de l'incomplétude référentielle: la logique intensionnelle des Principia Mathematica.Jocelyne Couture - 1983 - Dialogue 22 (1):69-90.
    Cet article s'ajoute à la liste déjà longue de ceux qui traitent des rapports entre la théorie russellienne des descriptions définies et la théorie ramifiée des types. Seule la prétention d'aborder cette question dans une perspective nouvelle justifie ici sa présence: d'une part, la théorie des descriptions définies sera resituée dans le contexte initial et souvent méconnu de la théorie des expressions dénotantes et d'autre part, c'est à la logique intensionnelle de Russell, objet d'une méconnaissance au moins égale, que nous (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The machine as data: a computational view of emergence and definability.S. Barry Cooper - 2015 - Synthese 192 (7):1955-1988.
    Turing’s paper on computable numbers has played its role in underpinning different perspectives on the world of information. On the one hand, it encourages a digital ontology, with a perceived flatness of computational structure comprehensively hosting causality at the physical level and beyond. On the other, it can give an insight into the way in which higher order information arises and leads to loss of computational control—while demonstrating how the control can be re-established, in special circumstances, via suitable type reductions. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A logic of abstraction related to finite constructive number classes.Andrea Cantini - 1991 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 31 (1):69-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Grelling's paradox.Noel Burton-Roberts - 2001 - In Robert M. Harrish & Istvan Kenesei (eds.), Philosophical Studies. John Benjamins. pp. 90--187.
    Grelling's Paradox is the paradox which results from considering whether heterologicality, the word-property which a designator has when and only when the designator does not bear the word-property it designates, is had by 'heterologicality'. Although there has been some philosophical debate over its solution, Grelling's Paradox is nearly uniformly treated as a variant of either the Liar Paradox or Russell's Paradox, a paradox which does not present any philosophical challenges not already presented by the two better known paradoxes. The aims (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Denoting, corresponding and facts.Donald Brownstein - 1976 - Theoria 42 (1-3):115-138.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Transcendance, an essential concept for system and complexity sciences to spread out.Elie Bernard-Weil - 2000 - Complexity 6 (2):23-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Shallow Analysis and the Slingshot Argument.Michael Baumgartner - 2010 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 39 (5):531-556.
    According to the standard opinions in the literature, blocking the unacceptable consequences of the notorious slingshot argument requires imposing constraints on the metaphysics of facts or on theories of definite descriptions (or class abstracts). This paper argues that both of these well-known strategies to rebut the slingshot overshoot the mark. The slingshot, first and foremost, raises the question as to the adequate logical formalization of statements about facts, i.e. of factual contexts. It will be shown that a rigorous application of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Note on Leibniz’s Argument Against Infinite Wholes.Mark van Atten & Mark Atten - 2015 - In Robert Tragesser, Mark van Atten & Mark Atten (eds.), Essays on Gödel’s Reception of Leibniz, Husserl, and Brouwer. Cham: Springer Verlag. pp. 121-129.
    Leibniz had a well-known argument against the existence of infinite wholes that is based on the part-whole axiom: the whole is greater than the part. The refutation of this argument by Russell and others is equally well known. In this note, I argue (against positions recently defended by Arthur, Breger, and Brown) for the following three claims: (1) Leibniz himself had all the means to devise and accept this refutation; (2) This refutation does not presuppose the consistency of Cantorian set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Term limits revisited.Stephen Neale - 2008 - Philosophical Perspectives 22 (1):375-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • A Note on Leibniz's Argument Against Infinite Wholes.Mark van Atten - 2011 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (1):121-129.
    Leibniz had a well-known argument against the existence of infinite wholes that is based on the part-whole axiom: the whole is greater than the part. The refutation of this argument by Russell and others is equally well known. In this note, I argue (against positions recently defended by Arthur, Breger, and Brown) for the following three claims: (1) Leibniz himself had all the means to devise and accept this refutation; (2) This refutation does not presuppose the consistency of Cantorian set (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Mathematics, science and ontology.Thomas Tymoczko - 1991 - Synthese 88 (2):201 - 228.
    According to quasi-empiricism, mathematics is very like a branch of natural science. But if mathematics is like a branch of science, and science studies real objects, then mathematics should study real objects. Thus a quasi-empirical account of mathematics must answer the old epistemological question: How is knowledge of abstract objects possible? This paper attempts to show how it is possible.The second section examines the problem as it was posed by Benacerraf in Mathematical Truth and the next section presents a way (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Editorial Introduction. Truth Values: Part I. [REVIEW]Yaroslav Shramko & Heinrich Wansing - 2009 - Studia Logica 91 (3):295-304.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Carnap: Reflections of a metaphysical student. [REVIEW]Abner Shimony - 1992 - Synthese 93 (1-2):261 - 274.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Universals: Ways or Things?Scott Berman - 2008 - Metaphysica 9 (2):219-234.
    What all contemporary so-called aristotelian realists have in common has been identified by David Armstrong as the principle of instantiation. This principle has been put forward in different versions, but all of them have the following simple consequence in common: uninstantiated universals do not exist. Such entities are for the lotus-eating Platonist to countenance, but not for any sort of moderate realist. I shall argue that this principle, in any guise, is not the best way to differentiate aristotelianism from Platonism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • On the syntax of logic and set theory.Lucius T. Schoenbaum - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):568-599.
    We introduce an extension of the propositional calculus to include abstracts of predicates and quantifiers, employing a single rule along with a novel comprehension schema and a principle of extensionality, which are substituted for the Bernays postulates for quantifiers and the comprehension schemata of ZF and other set theories. We prove that it is consistent in any finite Boolean subset lattice. We investigate the antinomies of Russell, Cantor, Burali-Forti, and others, and discuss the relationship of the system to other set-theoretic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Husserl's conception of formal ontology.Roberto Poli - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (1):1-14.
    The concept of formal ontology was first developed by Husserl. It concerns problems relating to the notions of object, substance, property, part, whole, predication, nominalization, etc. The idea of formal ontology is present in many of Husserl?s works, with minor changes. This paper provides a reconstruction of such an idea. Husserl?s proposal is faced with contemporary logical orthodoxy and it is presented also an interpretative hypothesis, namely that the original difference between the general perspective of usual model theory and formal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Some remarks on extending and interpreting theories with a partial predicate for truth.William N. Reinhardt - 1986 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 15 (2):219 - 251.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Grelling’s Paradox.Jay Newhard - 2005 - Philosophical Studies 126 (1):1 - 27.
    Grelling’s Paradox is the paradox which results from considering whether heterologicality, the word-property which a designator has when and only when the designator does not bear the word-property it designates, is had by ‘ ȁ8heterologicality’. Although there has been some philosophical debate over its solution, Grelling’s Paradox is nearly uniformly treated as a variant of either the Liar Paradox or Russell’s Paradox, a paradox which does not present any philosophical challenges not already presented by the two better known paradoxes. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A plea for logical objects.Matthew William McKeon - 2009 - Synthese 167 (1):163-182.
    An account of validity that makes what is invalid conditional on how many individuals there are is what I call a conditional account of validity. Here I defend conditional accounts against a criticism derived from Etchemendy’s well-known criticism of the model-theoretic analysis of validity. The criticism is essentially that knowledge of the size of the universe is non-logical and so by making knowledge of the extension of validity depend on knowledge of how many individuals there are, conditional accounts fail to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analysis, abstraction principles, and slingshot arguments.James Levine - 2006 - Ratio 19 (1):43–63.
    Frege's views regarding analysis and synomymy have long been the subject of critical discussion. Some commentators, led by Dummett, have argued that Frege was committed to the view that each thought admits of a unique ultimate analysis. However, this interpretation is in apparent conflict with Frege's criterion of synonymy, according to which two sentence express the same thought if one cannot understand them without regarding them as having the same truth–value. In a recent article in this journal, Drai attempts to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Typos of Principia Mathematica.Gregory Landini - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (4):306 - 334.
    Principia Mathematic goes to great lengths to hide its order/type indices and to make it appear as if its incomplete symbols behave as if they are singular terms. But well-hidden as they are, we cannot understand the proofs in Principia unless we bring them into focus. When we do, some rather surprising results emerge ? which is the subject of this paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Evolution of Principia Mathematica; Bertrand Russell's Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition.Gregory Landini - 2013 - History and Philosophy of Logic 34 (1):79-97.
    Bernard Linsky, The Evolution of Principia Mathematica; Bertrand Russell's Manuscripts and Notes for the Second Edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 2011. 407 pp. + two plates. $150.00/£...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Russellian Facts About the Slingshot.Gregory Landini - 2014 - Axiomathes 24 (4):533-547.
    The so-called “Slingshot” argument purports to show that an ontology of facts is untenable. In this paper, we address a minimal slingshot restricted to an ontology of physical facts as truth-makers for empirical physical statements. Accepting that logical matters have no bearing on the physical facts that are truth-makers for empirical physical statements and that objects are themselves constituents of such facts, our minimal slingshot argument purportedly shows that any two physical statements with empirical content are made true by one (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do We Need Mathematical Facts?Wojciech Krysztofiak - 2014 - History and Philosophy of Logic 35 (1):1-32.
    The main purpose of the paper concerns the question of the existence of hard mathematical facts as truth-makers of mathematical sentences. The paper defends the standpoint according to which hard mathematical facts do not exist in semantic models of mathematical theories. The argumentative line in favour of the defended thesis proceeds as follows: slingshot arguments supply us with some reasons to reject various ontological theories of mathematical facts; there are two ways of blocking these arguments: through the rejection of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hyper-Slingshot. Is Fact-Arithmetic Possible?Wojciech Krysztofiak - 2015 - Foundations of Science 20 (1):59-76.
    The paper presents a new argument supporting the ontological standpoint according to which there are no mathematical facts in any set theoretic model of arithmetical theories. It may be interpreted as showing that it is impossible to construct fact-arithmetic. The importance of this conclusion arises in the context of cognitive science. In the paper, a new type of slingshot argument is presented, which is called hyper-slingshot. The difference between meta-theoretical hyper-slingshots and conventional slingshots consists in the fact that the former (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The functions of Russell’s no class theory.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):633-664.
    Certain commentators on Russell's “no class” theory, in which apparent reference to classes or sets is eliminated using higher-order quantification, including W. V. Quine and (recently) Scott Soames, have doubted its success, noting the obscurity of Russell’s understanding of so-called “propositional functions”. These critics allege that realist readings of propositional functions fail to avoid commitment to classes or sets (or something equally problematic), and that nominalist readings fail to meet the demands placed on classes by mathematics. I show that Russell (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Epistemic logicism & Russell's regressive method.A. D. Irvine - 1989 - Philosophical Studies 55 (3):303 - 327.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • The Graph Conception of Set.Luca Incurvati - 2014 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (1):181-208.
    The non-well-founded set theories described by Aczel (1988) have received attention from category theorists and computer scientists, but have been largely ignored by philosophers. At the root of this neglect might lie the impression that these theories do not embody a conception of set, but are rather of mere technical interest. This paper attempts to dispel this impression. I present a conception of set which may be taken as lying behind a non-well-founded set theory. I argue that the axiom AFA (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Gottlob Frege, one more time.Claude Imbert & tr Bontea, Adriana - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):156-173.
    : Frege's philosophical writings, including the "logistic project," acquire a new insight by being confronted with Kant's criticism and Wittgenstein's logical and grammatical investigations. Between these two points a non-formalist history of logic is just taking shape, a history emphasizing the Greek and Kantian inheritance and its aftermath. It allows us to understand the radical change in rationality introduced by Gottlob Frege's syntax. This syntax put an end to Greek categorization and opened the way to the multiplicity of expressions producing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gottlob Frege, One More Time.Claude Imbert - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (4):156-173.
    Frege's philosophical writings, including the “logistic project,” acquire a new insight by being confronted with Kant's criticism and Wittgenstein's logical and grammatical investigations. Between these two points a non-formalist history of logic is just taking shape, a history emphasizing the Greek and Kantian inheritance and its aftermath. It allows us to understand the radical change in rationality introduced by Gottlob Frege's syntax. This syntax put an end to Greek categorization and opened the way to the multiplicity of expressions producing their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Russell's 1925 logic.A. P. Hazen & J. M. Davoren - 2000 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4):534 – 556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Against pluralism.A. P. Hazen - 1993 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (2):132 – 144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • On the termination of russell’s description elimination algorithm.Clemens Grabmayer, Joop Leo, Vincent van Oostrom & Albert Visser - 2011 - Review of Symbolic Logic 4 (3):367-393.
    In this paper we study the termination behavior of Russell’s description elimination rewrite system. We discuss certain claims made by Kripke (2005) in his paper concerning the possible nontermination of elimination of descriptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • An Argument for the Ontological Innocence of Mereology.Rohan French - 2016 - Erkenntnis 81 (4):683-704.
    In Parts of Classes David Lewis argued that mereology is ‘ontologically innocent’, mereological notions not incurring additional ontological commitments. Unfortunately, though, Lewis’s argument for this is not fully spelled out. Here we use some formal results concerning translations between formal languages to argue for the ontological innocence of mereology directly.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Alonzo Church.Oliver Marshall & Harry Deutsch - 2021 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Alonzo Church (1903–1995) was a renowned mathematical logician, philosophical logician, philosopher, teacher and editor. He was one of the founders of the discipline of mathematical logic as it developed after Cantor, Frege and Russell. He was also one of the principal founders of the Association for Symbolic Logic and the Journal of Symbolic Logic. The list of his students, mathematical and philosophical, is striking as it contains the names of renowned logicians and philosophers. In this article, we focus primarily on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Principia mathematica.A. D. Irvine - 2008 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations