Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On being systematically connectionist.Lars F. Niklasson & Tim van Gelder - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (3):288-30.
    In 1988 Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a challenge to the newly-popular connectionism: explain the systematicity of cognition without merely implementing a so-called classical architecture. Since that time quite a number of connectionist models have been put forward, either by their designers or by others, as in some measure demonstrating that the challenge can be met (e.g., Pollack, 1988, 1990; Smolensky, 1990; Chalmers, 1990; Niklasson and Sharkey, 1992; Brousse, 1993). Unfortu- nately, it has generally been unclear whether these models actually do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Cognition, systematicity, and nomic necessity.Robert F. Hadley - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (2):137-53.
    In their provocative 1988 paper, Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a formidable challenge to connectionists, i.e. to provide a non‐classical explanation of the empirical phenomenon of systematicity in cognitive agents. Since the appearance of F&P's challenge, a number of connectionist systems have emerged which prima facie meet this challenge. However, Fodor and McLaughlin (1990) advance an argument, based upon a general principle of nomological necessity, to show that one of these systems (Smolensky's) could not satisfy the Fodor‐Pylyshyn challenge. Yet, if Fodor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Cognition, Systematicity and Nomic Necessity.Robert F. Hadley - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (2):137-153.
    In their provocative 1988 paper, Fodor and Pylyshyn issued a formidable challenge to connectionists, i.e. to provide a non‐classical explanation of the empirical phenomenon of systematicity in cognitive agents. Since the appearance of F&P's challenge, a number of connectionist systems have emerged which prima facie meet this challenge. However, Fodor and McLaughlin (1990) advance an argument, based upon a general principle of nomological necessity, to show that one of these systems (Smolensky's) could not satisfy the Fodor‐Pylyshyn challenge. Yet, if Fodor (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Explaining systematicity.Kenneth Aizawa - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (2):115-36.
    Despite the considerable attention that the systematicity argument has enjoyed, it is worthwhile examining the argument within the context of similar explanatory arguments from the history of science. This kind of analysis helps show that Connectionism, qua Connectionism, really does not have an explanation of systematicity. Second, and more surprisingly, one finds that the systematicity argument sets such a high explanatory standard that not even Classicism can explain the systematicity of thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Explaining Systematicity.Kenneth Aizawa - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (2):115-136.
    Despite the considerable attention that the systematicity argument has enjoyed, it is worthwhile examining the argument within the context of similar explanatory arguments from the history of science. This kind of analysis helps show that Connectionism, qua Connectionism, really does not have an explanation of systematicity. Second, and more surprisingly, one finds that the systematicity argument sets such a high explanatory standard that not even Classicism can explain the systematicity of thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Functional distinctions within the medical temporal lobe memory system: What is the evidence?Stuart Zola-Morgan & Pablo Alvarez - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):495-496.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Smell's puzzling discrepancy: Gifted discrimination, yet pitiful identification.Benjamin D. Young - 2019 - Mind and Language 35 (1):90-114.
    Mind &Language, Volume 35, Issue 1, Page 90-114, February 2020.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Ethereal oscillations.Malcolm P. Young - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):476-477.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hippocampal neuronal activity in rat and primate: Memory and movement.Frasar A. W. Wilson - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):499-500.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Turing's Analysis of Computation and Theories of Cognitive Architecture.A. J. Wells - 1998 - Cognitive Science 22 (3):269-294.
    Turing's analysis of computation is a fundamental part of the background of cognitive science. In this paper it is argued that a re‐interpretation of Turing's work is required to underpin theorizing about cognitive architecture. It is claimed that the symbol systems view of the mind, which is the conventional way of understanding how Turing's work impacts on cognitive science, is deeply flawed. There is an alternative interpretation that is more faithful to Turing's original insights, avoids the criticisms made of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A parallel approach to syntax for generation.Nigel Ward - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 57 (2-3):183-225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What do animal models of memory model?Endel Tulving & Hans J. Markowitsch - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):498-499.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Dynamic-binding theory is not plausible without chaotic oscillation.Ichiro Tsuda - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):475-476.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reconstructing Physical Symbol Systems.David S. Touretzky & Dean A. Pomerleau - 1994 - Cognitive Science 18 (2):345-353.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Should first-order logic be neurally plausible?David S. Touretzky & Scott E. Fahlman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):474-475.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Temporal synchrony and the speed of visual processing.Simon J. Thorpe - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):473-474.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What can neuroanatomy tell us about the functional components of the hippocampal memory system?Wendy A. Suzuki - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):496-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phase logic is biologically relevant logic.Gary W. Strong - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):472-473.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What are the best strategies for understanding hippocampal function?Paul R. Solomon & Bo-Yi Yang - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):494-495.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Do simple associations lead to systematic reasoning?Steven Sloman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • From simple associations to systematic reasoning: A connectionist representation of rules, variables, and dynamic binding using temporal synchrony.Lokendra Shastri & Venkat Ajjanagadde - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):417-51.
    Human agents draw a variety of inferences effortlessly, spontaneously, and with remarkable efficiency – as though these inferences were a reflexive response of their cognitive apparatus. Furthermore, these inferences are drawn with reference to a large body of background knowledge. This remarkable human ability seems paradoxical given the complexity of reasoning reported by researchers in artificial intelligence. It also poses a challenge for cognitive science and computational neuroscience: How can a system of simple and slow neuronlike elements represent a large (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   122 citations  
  • From Heisenberg's cat to Eichenbaum's rat: Uncertainty in predicting the neural requirements for animal behavior.Matthew L. Shapiro - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):493-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A step toward modeling reflexive reasoning.Lokendra Shastri & Venkat Ajjanagadde - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):477-494.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Linguistic Subversion of Mental Representation.Whit Schonbein - 2012 - Minds and Machines 22 (3):235-262.
    Embedded and embodied approaches to cognition urge that (1) complicated internal representations may be avoided by letting features of the environment drive behavior, and (2) environmental structures can play an enabling role in cognition, allowing prior cognitive processes to solve novel tasks. Such approaches are thus in a natural position to oppose the ‘thesis of linguistic structuring’: The claim that the ability to use language results in a wholesale recapitulation of linguistic structure in onboard mental representation. Prominent examples of researchers (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Arguing about representation.Mark Rowlands - 2017 - Synthese 194 (11):4215-4232.
    The question of whether cognition requires representations has engendered heated discussion during the last two decades. I shall argue that the question is, in all likelihood, a spurious one. There may or may not be a fact of the matter concerning whether a given item qualifies as a representation. However, even if there is, attempts to establish whether cognition requires representation have neither practical nor theoretical utility.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Useful ideas for exploiting time to engineer representations.Richard Rohwer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does it still make sense to develop a declarative memory theory of hippocampal function?J. N. P. Rawlins, R. M. J. Deacon, B. K. Yee & H. J. Cassaday - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):492-493.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functional components of the hippocampal memory system: Implications for future learning and memory research in nonhuman primates.Peter R. Rapp - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):491-492.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Computational Origin of Representation.Steven T. Piantadosi - 2020 - Minds and Machines 31 (1):1-58.
    Each of our theories of mental representation provides some insight into how the mind works. However, these insights often seem incompatible, as the debates between symbolic, dynamical, emergentist, sub-symbolic, and grounded approaches to cognition attest. Mental representations—whatever they are—must share many features with each of our theories of representation, and yet there are few hypotheses about how a synthesis could be possible. Here, I develop a theory of the underpinnings of symbolic cognition that shows how sub-symbolic dynamics may give rise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Mathematical fixation: Search viewed through a cognitive lens.Steven Phillips & Yuji Takeda - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Darwin's mistake: Explaining the discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds.Derek C. Penn, Keith J. Holyoak & Daniel J. Povinelli - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (2):109-130.
    Over the last quarter century, the dominant tendency in comparative cognitive psychology has been to emphasize the similarities between human and nonhuman minds and to downplay the differences as (Darwin 1871). In the present target article, we argue that Darwin was mistaken: the profound biological continuity between human and nonhuman animals masks an equally profound discontinuity between human and nonhuman minds. To wit, there is a significant discontinuity in the degree to which human and nonhuman animals are able to approximate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   227 citations  
  • On the difficulty of really considering a radical novelty.Derek Partridge - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (3):391-410.
    The fundamental assumptions in Dijkstra''s influential article on computing science teaching are challenged. Dijkstra''s paper presents the radical novelties of computing, and the consequent problems that we must tackle through a formal, logic-based approach to program derivation. Dijkstra''s main premise is that the algorithmic programming paradigm is the only one, in fact, the only possible one. It is argued that there is at least one other, the network-programming paradigm, which itself is a radical novelty with respect to the implementation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Making reasoning more reasonable: Event-coherence and assemblies.Günther Palm - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):470-470.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychological implications of the synchronicity hypothesis.Stellan Ohlsson - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):469-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computational and biological constraints in the psychology of reasoning.Mike Oaksford & Mike Malloch - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):468-469.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Puzzle concerning Compositionality in Machines.Ryan M. Nefdt - 2020 - Minds and Machines 30 (1):47-75.
    This paper attempts to describe and address a specific puzzle related to compositionality in artificial networks such as Deep Neural Networks and machine learning in general. The puzzle identified here touches on a larger debate in Artificial Intelligence related to epistemic opacity but specifically focuses on computational applications of human level linguistic abilities or properties and a special difficulty with relation to these. Thus, the resulting issue is both general and unique. A partial solution is suggested.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hippocampus, space, and relations.Lynn Nadel - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):490-491.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Relational but not spatial memory: The task at hand.Elisabeth A. Murray - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):489-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What we know and the LTKB.Stanley Munsat - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):466-467.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neocortical memory traces.Earl K. Miller - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):488-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The hippocampus: Relational processor or antiprocessor?Neil McNaughton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):487-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The connectionism/classicism battle to win souls.Brian P. McLaughlin - 1993 - Philosophical Studies 71 (2):163-190.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • What exactly do amnesics fail to store normally?Andrew R. Mayes - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):486-487.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflections on reflexive reasoning.David L. Martin - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):466-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Replies to my critics. [REVIEW]Edouard Machery - 2010 - Philosophical Studies 149 (3):429 - 436.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Mental Structures.Kevin J. Lande - 2020 - Noûs (3):649-677.
    An ongoing philosophical discussion concerns how various types of mental states fall within broad representational genera—for example, whether perceptual states are “iconic” or “sentential,” “analog” or “digital,” and so on. Here, I examine the grounds for making much more specific claims about how mental states are structured from constituent parts. For example, the state I am in when I perceive the shape of a mountain ridge may have as constituent parts my representations of the shapes of each peak and saddle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Synchronization and cognitive carpentry: From systematic structuring to simple reasoning. E. Koerner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):465-466.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hippocampus and memory for time.Raymond P. Kesner - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):485-486.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How long do relational representations in the hippocampus last during classical eyelid conditioning?Donald B. Katz & Joseph E. Steinmetz - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):484-485.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Maps, languages, and manguages: Rival cognitive architectures?Kent Johnson - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (6):815-836.
    Provided we agree about the thing, it is needless to dispute about the terms. —David Hume, A treatise of human nature, Book 1, section VIIMap-like representations are frequently invoked as an alternative type of representational vehicle to a language of thought. This view presupposes that map-systems and languages form legitimate natural kinds of cognitive representational systems. I argue that they do not, because the collections of features that might be taken as characteristic of maps or languages do not themselves provide (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations