Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The nature of cerebral hemispheric specialisation in man: Quantitative vs. qualitative differences.Maria A. Wyke - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):78-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The pre-reflective experience of “I” as a continuously existing being: The role of temporal functional binding.Peter A. White - 2015 - Consciousness and Cognition 31:98-114.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Singular Clues to Causality and Their Use in Human Causal Judgment.Peter A. White - 2014 - Cognitive Science 38 (1):38-75.
    It is argued that causal understanding originates in experiences of acting on objects. Such experiences have consistent features that can be used as clues to causal identification and judgment. These are singular clues, meaning that they can be detected in single instances. A catalog of 14 singular clues is proposed. The clues function as heuristics for generating causal judgments under uncertainty and are a pervasive source of bias in causal judgment. More sophisticated clues such as mechanism clues and repeated interventions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Can you tickle yourself if you swap bodies with someone else?George Van Doorn, Jakob Hohwy & Mark Symmons - 2014 - Consciousness and Cognition 23:1-11.
    The effect of the body transfer illusion on the perceived strength of self- and externally-generated “tickle” sensations was investigated. As expected, externally generated movement produced significantly higher ratings of tickliness than those associated with self-generated movements. Surprisingly, the body transfer illusion had no influence on the ratings of tickliness, suggesting that highly surprising, and therefore hard to predict, experiences of body image and first-person perspective do not abolish the attenuation of tickle sensations. In addition, evidence was found that a version (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Dynamic Touch as Common Ground for Enactivism and Ecological Psychology.David Travieso, Lorena Lobo, Carlos de Paz, Thijme E. Langelaar, Jorge Ibáñez-Gijón & David M. Jacobs - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Temporal processing as related to hemispheric specialization for speech perception in normal and language impaired populations.Paula Tallal - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Cerebral hemispheres: Specialized for the analysis of what?Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Modality-specific and amodal aspects of object perception in infancy: The case of active touch.Arlette Streri, Elizabeth Spelke & E. Rameix - 1993 - Cognition 47 (3):251-279.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Further analysis of active and passive touch in pattern discrimination.Arthur S. Schwartz, Alan J. Perey & Alan Azulay - 1975 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 6 (1):7-9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Do things look the way they feel?John Schwenkler - 2013 - Analysis 73 (1):86-96.
    Do spatial features appear the same whether they are perceived through vision or touch? This question is at stake in the puzzle that William Molyneux posed to John Locke, concerning whether a man born blind whose sight was restored would be able immediately to identify the shapes of the things he saw. A recent study purports to answer the question negatively, but I argue here that the subjects of the study likely could not see well enough for the result to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Two theories of the intentionality of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1983 - Synthese 54 (January):85-94.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • James J. Gibson's revolution in perceptual psychology: A case study of the transformation of scientific ideas.Edward S. Reed - 1986 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 17 (1):65-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Gibson's theory of perception: A case of hasty epistemologizing?Edward S. Reed & Rebecca K. Jones - 1978 - Philosophy of Science 45 (4):519-530.
    Hintikka has criticized psychologists for "hasty epistemologizing," which he takes to be an unwarranted transfer of ideas from psychology (a discipline dealing with questions of fact) into epistemology (a discipline dealing with questions of method and theory). Hamlyn argues, following Hintikka, that Gibson's theory of perception is an example of such an inappropriate transfer, especially insofar as Hamlyn feels Gibson does not answer several important questions. However, Gibson's theory does answer the relevant questions, albeit in a new and radical way, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Divisions within the posterior parietal cortex help touch meet vision.Catherine L. Reed - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (2):218-218.
    The parietal cortex is divided into two major functional regions: the anterior parietal cortex that includes primary somatosensory cortex, and the posterior parietal cortex (PPC) that includes the rest of the parietal lobe. The PPC contains multiple representations of space. In Dijkerman & de Haan's (D&dH's) model, higher spatial representations are separate from PPC functions. This model should be developed further so that the functions of the somatosensory system are integrated with specific functions within the PPC and higher spatial representations. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is Touch?Matthew Ratcliffe - 2012 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (3):413 - 432.
    This paper addresses the nature of touch or ?tactual perception?. I argue that touch encompasses a wide range of perceptual achievements, that treating it as a number of separate senses will not work, and that the permissive conception we are left with is so permissive that it is unclear how touch might be distinguished from the other senses. I conclude that no criteria will succeed in individuating touch. Although I do not rule out the possibility that this also applies to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • The alleged manipulospatiality explanation of right hemisphere visuospatial superiority.Roland Puccetti - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Movement for Movement’s Sake?Mark Paterson - 2012 - Essays in Philosophy 13 (2):471-497.
    Movement and, more particularly, kinesthesia as a modality and as a metaphor has become of interest at the intersection of phenomenology and cognitive science. In this paper I wish to combine three historically related strands, aisthêsis, kinesthesis and aesthetics, to advance an argument concerning the aesthetic value of certain somatic sensations. Firstly, by capitalizing on a recent regard for somatic or inner bodily senses, including kinesthesia, proprioception and the vestibular system by drawing lines of historical continuity from earlier philosophical investigations (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Scanning movements during haptic search: similarity with fixations during visual search.Achille Pasqualotto - 2017 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dwelling in the Virtual Sonic Environment: A Phenomenological Analysis of Dancers' Learning Processes.Jaana Parviainen - 2011 - The European Legacy 16 (5):633 - 647.
    This article discusses the Embodied Generative Music (EGM) project carried out at the Institute of Electronic Music and Acoustics IEM in Austria. In investigating a new interface that combines motion capture and sound processing software with movement improvisation and performance, I focus on dancers? learning processes of dwelling in the virtual sonic environment. Applying phenomenology and its concepts, I describe how dancers explore reversibility of sound and movement to shape this connection in an artistically expressive manner. The article proposes that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-reported vividness of tactile imagery for object properties and body regions: An exploratory study.A. O' Dowd, S. M. Cooney & F. N. Newell - 2022 - Consciousness and Cognition 103:103376.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does hemispheric specialization of function reflect the needs of an executive side?Fernando Nottebohm - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):75-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Material Basis of Perceptual Information知覚を可能にするマテリアル.Tetsushi Nonaka - 2020 - Kagaku Tetsugaku 52 (2):21-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Touching intelligence.David Morris - 2002 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 29 (149-162):149-162.
    Touch requires that one move in concert with one's tactile object. This provokes the question how joint movement of this sort yields perception of tactile qualities of the object vs. tactile qualities of an object-augmented body. Phenomenological analysis together with results of dynamic systems theory (in psychology) suggest that the difference stems from 'resonant' vs. 'reverberant' modalities of body-object movement. The further suggestion is that tactile movement is itself a form of discriminative intelligence, and that the peculiar intimacy of touch (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Hemispheric specialization and spatiotemporal interactions.M. J. Morgan - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):74-75.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Touch and Bodily Transparency.Vivian Mizrahi - 2023 - Mind 132 (527):803-827.
    As most philosophers recognize, the body’s central role in touch differs from the role it plays in the other sense modalities. Any account of touch must then explain the pivotal nature of the body’s involvement in touch. Unlike most accounts of touch, this paper argues that the body’s centrality in touch is not phenomenological or experiential: the body is not felt in any special way in tactile experiences. Building on Aristotle’s account in De Anima, I argue that the body is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A resource for resistance: Power-knowledge and affordance. [REVIEW]Mike Michael & Arthur Still - 1992 - Theory and Society 21 (6):869-888.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On laterality research and dichotomania.Walter F. McKeever - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):73-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Taking a conscious look at the body schema.Jonathan P. Maxwell, Richard S. W. Masters & John van der Kamp - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (2):216-217.
    Dijkerman & de Haan (D&dH) propose a somatosensory perceptual pathway that informs a consciously accessible body image, and an action pathway that provides information to a body schema, which is not consciously accessible. We argue that the body schema may become accessible to consciousness in some circumstances, possibly resulting from cross talk, but that this may be detrimental to skilled movement production.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How to Be Sure.Mohan Matthen - 2014 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1):38-69.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • How to Be Sure: Sensory Exploration and Empirical Certainty.Mohan Matthen - 2012 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1):38-69.
    I can be wrong about things I seem to perceive; the conditions might lead me to be mistaken about them. Since I can't rule out the possibility that the conditions are misleading, I can't be sure that I am perceiving this thing in my hand correctly. But suppose that I am able to examine it actively—handling it, looking closer, shining a light on it, and so on. Then, my level of uncertainty goes down; in the limit it is eliminated entirely. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Hemispheric specialization: What, how and why.John C. Marshall - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):72-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The Tactual Ground, Immersion, and the “Space Between”.Clare Mac Cumhaill - 2017 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 55 (1):5-31.
    I ask whether figure-ground structure can be realized in touch, and, if so, how. Drawing on the taxonomy of touch sketched in Katz's 1925 The World of Touch, I argue that the form of touch that is relevant to such consideration is a species of immersed touch. I consider whether we can feel the space we are immersed in and, more specifically, the empty space against which the surfaces of objects, as I shall urge, “stand out.” Harnessing M. G. F. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • James J. Gibson's ecological approach: Perceiving what exists.William M. Mace - 2005 - Ethics and the Environment 10 (2):195-216.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:James J. Gibson's Ecological Approach:Perceiving What ExistsWilliam M. Mace (bio)Environmental Philosophy and EpistemologyThe purpose of this paper is to help an audience attracted to environmental philosophy get to the core of Gibson's system in a compact form and to appreciate the necessity for an account of the environment in epistemology. I hope to show that Gibson's is a consistent and scientifically progressive account of knowing that gives the environment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • James J. Gibson's Ecological Approach: Perceiving What Exists.William M. Mace - 2005 - Ethics and the Environment 10 (2):195-216.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:James J. Gibson's Ecological Approach:Perceiving What ExistsWilliam M. Mace (bio)Environmental Philosophy and EpistemologyThe purpose of this paper is to help an audience attracted to environmental philosophy get to the core of Gibson's system in a compact form and to appreciate the necessity for an account of the environment in epistemology. I hope to show that Gibson's is a consistent and scientifically progressive account of knowing that gives the environment (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The History and Philosophy of Ecological Psychology.Lorena Lobo, Manuel Heras-Escribano & David Travieso - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Seeing and touching aesthetic objects: I. Judgments.Martin S. Lindauer, Eleni A. Stergiou & David L. Penn - 1986 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 24 (2):121-124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • 'Contact' as a Manifestation of Sensorimotor Empathy: The Experience of Expert Écuyers in Interaction with Horses.Marine Leblanc, Benoît Huet & Jacques Saury - 2022 - Journal of Consciousness Studies 29 (11-12):80-107.
    Chemero's concept of sensorimotor empathy offers a relevant introduction to the study of human/non-human relationships. This article proposes an empirical characterization of this phenomenon occurring in human–horse interactions through the notion of 'contact', which is a core concept in the technical tradition of the equestrian world. According to the assumptions of 4E cognition, we approach the notion of contact with a broader meaning than how it is usually defined, i.e.as the connection of the rider's hand with the horse's mouth. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial representation of objects in the young blind child.Barbara Landau - 1991 - Cognition 38 (2):145-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Moving and sensing without input and output: early nervous systems and the origins of the animal sensorimotor organization.Fred Keijzer - 2015 - Biology and Philosophy 30 (3):311-331.
    It remains a standing problem how and why the first nervous systems evolved. Molecular and genomic information is now rapidly accumulating but the macroscopic organization and functioning of early nervous systems remains unclear. To explore potential evolutionary options, a coordination centered view is discussed that diverges from a standard input–output view on early nervous systems. The scenario involved, the skin brain thesis, stresses the need to coordinate muscle-based motility at a very early stage. This paper addresses how this scenario with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Effect of Visual Information on Active Touch During Mirror Visual Feedback.Narumi Katsuyama, Eriko Kikuchi-Tachi, Nobuo Usui, Hideyuki Yoshizawa, Aya Saito & Masato Taira - 2018 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 12.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The experience of spatiality for congenitally blind people: A phenomenological-psychological study. [REVIEW]Gunnar Karlsson - 1996 - Human Studies 19 (3):303 - 330.
    This phenomenological-psychological study aims at discovering the essential constituents involved in congenitally blind people's spatial experiences. Nine congenitally blind persons took part in this study. The data were made up of half structured (thorough) interviews. The analysis of the data yielded the following three comprehension forms of spatiality; (i) Comprehension in terms of image-experience; (ii) Comprehension in terms of notions; (iii) Comprehension in terms of knowledge.Comprehension in terms of image experience is the form which is most concretely and clearly experienced. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Influence of writing style and categorical information on identification of tactile numerals and letters.Morton A. Heller, Kimberly D. Nesbitt & Danette K. Scrofano - 1991 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 29 (4):365-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Improving the passive tactile digit span.Morton A. Heller - 1987 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 25 (4):257-258.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Active and passive tactile braille recognition.Morton A. Heller - 1986 - Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 24 (3):201-202.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Consciousness of Embodied Cognition, Affordances, and the Brain.Valerie Gray Hardcastle - 2020 - Topoi 39 (1):23-33.
    Tony Chemero advances the radical thesis that cognition and consciousness are actually the same thing. I question this conclusion. Even if we are the brain–body environmental synergies that Chemero and others claim, we will not be able to conclude that consciousness is just cognition because this view actually expands cognition beyond being the sort of natural kind upon which to hook phenomenal experience. Identifying consciousness with cognition either means consciousness exists at multiple levels of organization in the universe, or more (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implications of differences between perceptual systems for the analysis of hemispheric specialization.Lauren Julius Harris & Thomas H. Cart - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):71-72.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human haptic perception is interrupted by explorative stops of milliseconds.Martin Grunwald, Manivannan Muniyandi, Hyun Kim, Jung Kim, Frank Krause, Stephanie Mueller & Mandayam A. Srinivasan - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Clinical neuropsychology and the left-hemisphere dominance for language.G. Gainotti - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):70-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Empirical Evidence for Extended Cognitive Systems.Luis H. Favela, Mary Jean Amon, Lorena Lobo & Anthony Chemero - 2021 - Cognitive Science 45 (11):e13060.
    Cognitive Science, Volume 45, Issue 11, November 2021.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Intelligibility of Haptic Perception in Instructional Sequences: When Visually Impaired People Achieve Object Understanding.Brian L. Due & Louise Lüchow - 2023 - Human Studies 46 (1):163-182.
    In this paper, we study the interactional organization of an instructed object exploration among sighted and visually impaired people (VIPs) in order to contribute to studies of instructional activities and the observable accomplishment of haptic perception. We do this by showing the situated, interactional, and co-operative organization of achieving object understanding. We focus on the dynamics of haptic perception as being reliant on instructions, while at the same time being an observable production that furnishes further instructions. We show the organization (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark