Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Mind reading, pretence and imitation in monkeys and apes.A. Whiten - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):170-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Grasping schemas is (are) difficult.H. T. A. Whiting - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):450-451.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct remembering and the correspondence metaphor.K. Geoffrey White - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (2):208-209.
    The correspondence view is consistent with a theory of direct remembering that assumes continuity between perception and memory. Two implications of direct remembering for correspondence are suggested. It is assumed that forgetting is exponential, and that remembering at one time is independent of factors influencing remembering at another. Elaboration of the correspondence view in the same terms as perception offers a novel approach to the study of memory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A perspective for viewing the present of psychophysics.Paul Whittle - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):165-166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science Friction: Phenomenology, Naturalism and Cognitive Science.Michael Wheeler - 2013 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 72:135-167.
    Recent years have seen growing evidence of a fruitful engagement between phenomenology and cognitive science. This paper confronts an in-principle problem that stands in the way of this intellectual coalition, namely the fact that a tension exists between the transcendentalism that characterizes phenomenology and the naturalism that accompanies cognitive science. After articulating the general shape of this tension, I respond as follows. First, I argue that, if we view things through a kind of neo-McDowellian lens, we can open up a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Minding Nature: Gallagher and the Relevance of Phenomenology to Cognitive Science.Michael Wheeler & María Jimena Clavel Vázquez - 2018 - Australasian Philosophical Review 2 (2):145-158.
    In ‘Rethinking Nature: Phenomenology and a Non-reductionist Cognitive Science’, Gallagher [2019] sets out to overcome resistance to the idea that phenomenology is relevant to cognitive science. He argues that the relevance in question may be secured if we rethink the concept of nature. For Gallagher, this transformed concept of nature—which is to be distinguished from the classic scientific conception of nature in that it embraces irreducible subjectivity—is already at work in some contemporary enactive phenomenological approaches to cognitive science. Following a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Cognition and simulation.N. E. Wetherick - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):462-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dialogue as Habit-Taking in Peirce’s Continuum: The Call to Absolute Chance.Donna E. West - 2015 - Dialogue 54 (4):685-702.
    Dans cette enquête, j’affirme que les signes occupent une place centrale dans la cosmologie de Peirce, et que le fait de soutenir de nouvelles propositions à travers le dialogue a le pouvoir de favoriser l’unité nécessaire pour souder les membres de son continuum. Le dialogue tel que conçu par Peirce devient le moyen de souder chaque membre du continuum. Le principal moteur dans la réalisation de cette «soudure», selon Peirce, est le hasard/l’habitude dans l’utilisation des signes elle-même. Bien que la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Which Moral Properties Are Eligible for Perceptual Awareness?Preston J. Werner - 2020 - Journal of Moral Philosophy 17 (3):290-319.
    Moral perception has made something of a comeback in recent work on moral epistemology. Many traditional objections to the view have been argued to fail upon closer inspection. But it remains an open question just how far moral perception might extend. In this paper, I provide the beginnings of an answer to this question by assessing the relationship between the metaphysical structure of different normative properties and a plausible constraint on which properties are eligible for perceptual awareness which I call (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Little Word “as.” On Making Contexts and Aspects Explicit.Konrad Werner - 2020 - Axiomathes 30 (1):69-90.
    The word “as” enables one to make contexts and aspects of things explicit while attributing properties or descriptions to them. For example “John is rational as a mathematician”; “John is irrational as a driver.” This paper examines the idea according to which all propositions containing “as” should be targeted as potential inferences about the subject; as for the examples given—about John. If the inference is valid—the conception in question holds—one can get rid of “as.” I argue against that view by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Motion perception: Rights, wrongs and further speculations.Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):340-355.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Motion perception during selfmotion: The direct versus inferential controversy revisited.Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):293-311.
    According to the traditional inferential theory of perception, percepts of object motion or stationarity stem from an evaluation of afferent retinal signals (which encode image motion) with the help of extraretinal signals (which encode eye movements). According to direct perception theory, on the other hand, the percepts derive from retinally conveyed information only. Neither view is compatible with a perceptual phenomenon that occurs during visually induced sensations of ego motion (vection). A modified version of inferential theory yields a model in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Fixations or smooth eye movements?Alexander H. Wertheim - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):281-282.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Enactment and Construction of the Cognitive Niche: Toward an Ontology of the Mind- World Connection.Konrad Werner - 2020 - Synthese 197 (3):1313-1341.
    The paper discusses the concept of the cognitive niche and distinguishes the latter from the metabolic niche. By using these posits I unpack certain ideas that are crucial for the enactivist movement, especially for its original formulation proposed by Varela, Thompson and Rosh. Drawing on the ontology of location, boundaries, and parthood, I argue that enacting the world can be seen as the process of cognitive niche construction. Moreover, it turns out that enactivism—as seen through the lens of the conceptual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Cognition as self–organizing process.Gerhard Werner - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):183-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Cross-cultural research needs crossfertilisation.Peter Wenderoth - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):97-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Conceptual and Computational Model of Moral Decision Making in Human and Artificial Agents.Wendell Wallach, Stan Franklin & Colin Allen - 2010 - Topics in Cognitive Science 2 (3):454-485.
    Recently, there has been a resurgence of interest in general, comprehensive models of human cognition. Such models aim to explain higher-order cognitive faculties, such as deliberation and planning. Given a computational representation, the validity of these models can be tested in computer simulations such as software agents or embodied robots. The push to implement computational models of this kind has created the field of artificial general intelligence (AGI). Moral decision making is arguably one of the most challenging tasks for computational (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • The Object Orientation Effect in Exocentric Distances.Marlene Weller, Kohske Takahashi, Katsumi Watanabe, Heinrich H. Bülthoff & Tobias Meilinger - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Percepts, intervening variables, and neural mechanisms.Wally Welker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Missing variables in studies of animal learning.Wally Welker - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):161-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logical atomism and computation do not refute Gibson.Walter B. Welmer - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):405-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Cognitive Boundaries of Responsibility.Martin Weichold - 2017 - Grazer Philosophische Studien 94 (1-2):226-267.
    This paper poses a new challenge to control-based theories of moral responsibility. Control-based theories – as defended, for instance, by Aristotle and John Martin Fischer – hold that an agent is responsible for an action only if she acted voluntarily and knew what she was doing. However, this paper argues that there is a large class of cases of unreflective behavior of which the following is true: the persons involved did not have the kind of control required by control-based theories, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Situated agency: towards an affordance-based, sensorimotor theory of action.Martin Weichold - 2018 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17 (4):761-785.
    Recent empirical findings from social psychology, ecological psychology, and embodied cognitive science indicate that situational factors crucially shape the course of human behavior. For instance, it has been shown that finding a dime, being under the influence of an authority figure, or just being presented with food in easy reach often influences behavior tremendously. These findings raise important new questions for the philosophy of action: Are these findings a threat to classical conceptions of human agency? Are humans passively pushed around (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Medial versus lateral motor control.Michael Weinrich - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):600-600.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Looking backward: Progress in outer psychophysics.David J. Weiss - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):165-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Embodied cognition and linguistic comprehension.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2010 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 41 (3):294-304.
    Traditionally, the language faculty was supposed to be a device that maps linguistic inputs to semantic or conceptual representations. These representations themselves were supposed to be distinct from the representations manipulated by the hearer’s perceptual and motor systems. Recently this view of language has been challenged by advocates of embodied cognition. Drawing on empirical studies of linguistic comprehension, they have proposed that the language faculty reuses the very representations and processes deployed in perceiving and acting. I review some of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Cognition is not computation, for the reasons that computers don't solve the mind-body problems.Walter B. Weimer - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Anthropic Concepts.Daniel A. Weiskopf - 2020 - Noûs 54 (2):451-468.
    Natural kind concepts have the function of tracking categories that exist independently of our beliefs and purposes. But not all ways of tracking categories in the natural world involve conceiving of them as natural kinds. Anthropic concepts represent groups of natural, mind‐independent entities that are apt for serving various human interests, goals, and projects. They represent the natural world under a practical mode of presentation, as a set of material resources that can be transformed to further a host of functions (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Moved by Masses? Shared Moods and Their Impact on Immoral Behavior.Eva Weber-Guskar - 2017 - Philosophia 45 (4):1663-1679.
    It is often suggested that people in large groups behave and act differently than when they are alone. More precisely, it is an often-repeated claim that they tend to act in a morally problematic or plainly reprehensible way. Still, a fully satisfying explanation has not yet been given for why this is the case. In this paper, I suggest that the phenomenon of shared moods may play a crucial role here. In order to explicate and support this thesis, first, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Perceptions in perspective.R. A. Weale - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):96-97.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Different World: Embodied Experience and Linguistic Relativity on the Epistemological Path to Somewhere.Karen Ann Watson-Gegeo - 2004 - Anthropology of Consciousness 15 (2):1-23.
    This article explores the role of limit experiences (Tracy) and linguistic relativity (Whorf) in shaping our ontological and epistemological understandings of the world. Specifically, I trace the transformations in embodied understanding I have undergone in three situations across my life course–in Hawai'i, Solomon Islands, and as an acutely ill and disabled patient in a live-in clinic in Dallas, Texas. I give examples of how our perceptions, conceptions, and proprioceptions are positioned, constrained, opened to interpretation, and even denied by our culture (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The physics of light and the physical correlate theory of sensory scaling.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):210-211.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quantal basis of iconic dispersion.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):40-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Comparable context effects exist in physical, physiological, and psychophysical scales.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):764-766.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dynamics of perception and action.William H. Warren - 2006 - Psychological Review 113 (2):358-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   63 citations  
  • Sensation: A relativist's view.W. Dixon Ward - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):208-209.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Relation of sensory scales to physical scales.Richard M. Warren - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):586-587.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Psychophysics and ecometrics.William H. Warren & Robert E. Shaw - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):209-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Introduction: The Varieties of Enactivism.Dave Ward, David Silverman & Mario Villalobos - 2017 - Topoi 36 (3):365-375.
    This introduction to a special issue of Topoi introduces and summarises the relationship between three main varieties of 'enactivist' theorising about the mind: 'autopoietic', 'sensorimotor', and 'radical' enactivism. It includes a brief discussion of the philosophical and cognitive scientific precursors to enactivist theories, and the relationship of enactivism to other trends in embodied cognitive science and philosophy of mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   65 citations  
  • Direct Perception.William H. Warren - 2005 - Philosophical Topics 33 (1):335-361.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Confusion of sensations and their physical correlates.Richard M. Warren - 2003 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (1):51-51.
    The authors favor a “color realism” theory that considers colors to be physical properties residing in objects that reflect, emit, or transmit light. It is opposed to the theory that colors are sensations or visual experiences. This commentary suggests that both theories are correct, and that context usually indicates which of these dual aspects is being considered.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The illusion of self-motion in virtual reality environments.John Wann & Simon Rushton - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):338-340.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Sound of Silence: Merleau‐Ponty on Conscious Thought.Philip J. Walsh - 2017 - European Journal of Philosophy 25 (2):312-335.
    We take ourselves to have an inner life of thought, and we take ourselves to be capable of linguistically expressing our thoughts to others. But what is the nature of this “inner life” of thought? Is conscious thought necessarily carried out in language? This paper takes up these questions by examining Merleau-Ponty’s theory of expression. For Merleau-Ponty, language expresses thought. Thus it would seem that thought must be independent of, and in some sense prior to, the speech that expresses it. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The Bow and Arrow and Early Human Sociality: an Enactive Perspective on Communities and Technical Practice in the Middle Stone Age.Matthew Walls - 2019 - Philosophy and Technology 32 (2):265-281.
    In this paper, I draw on postphenomenology and material engagement theory to consider the material and emergent character of sociality in Homo faber. I approach this through the context of the bow and arrow, which is a technology that has received recent attention in cognitive archeology as a proxy for assessing criteria that made early human cognition distinct from that of other hominins. Through an ethnographic case study, I scrutinize the forms of knowledge that are required to use the technology (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Penrose's grand unified mystery.David Waltz & James Pustejovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):688-690.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Potential disparities between imagining and preparing motor skills.Charles B. Walter & Stephan P. Swinnen - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):227-228.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ways of coloring the ecological approach.Johan Wagemans & Charles M. M. de Weert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (1):54-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Schemas and bridging gaps in the behavioral and brain sciences.Johan P. Wagemans - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):449-450.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception-action as reciprocal, continuous, and prospective.Jeffrey B. Wagman - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (2):219-220.
    From the perspective of ecological psychology, perception and action are not separate, linear, and mechanistic processes that refer to the immediate present. Rather, they are reciprocal and continuous and refer to the impending future. Therefore, from the perspective of ecological psychology, delays in perception and action are impossible, and delay compensation mechanisms are unnecessary.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the construction of psychophysical reality.Mark Wagner - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):164-165.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark