Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. “What’s that?” “What Went Wrong?” Positive and Negative Surprise and the Rostral–Ventral to Caudal–Dorsal Functional Gradient in the Brain.Mattie Tops & Maarten A. S. Boksem - 2012 - Frontiers in Psychology 3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Modulating Mimetic Preference with Theta Burst Stimulation of the Inferior Parietal Cortex.Luca F. Ticini, Cosimo Urgesi & Sonja A. Kotz - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The concept of voluntary motor control in the recent neuroscientific literature.Paul Tibbetts - 2004 - Synthese 141 (2):247-76.
    The concept of voluntary motor control(VMC) frequently appears in the neuroscientific literature, specifically in the context of cortically-mediated, intentional motor actions. For cognitive scientists, this concept of VMC raises a number of interesting questions:(i) Are there dedicated, modular-like structures within the motor system associated with VMC? Or (ii) is it the case that VMC is distributed over multiple cortical as well as subcortical structures?(iii) Is there any one place within the so-calledhierarchy of motor control where voluntary movements could be said (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Bayesian integration of position and orientation cues in perception of biological and non-biological forms.Steven M. Thurman & Hongjing Lu - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neural Representations Observed.Eric Thomson & Gualtiero Piccinini - 2018 - Minds and Machines 28 (1):191-235.
    The historical debate on representation in cognitive science and neuroscience construes representations as theoretical posits and discusses the degree to which we have reason to posit them. We reject the premise of that debate. We argue that experimental neuroscientists routinely observe and manipulate neural representations in their laboratory. Therefore, neural representations are as real as neurons, action potentials, or any other well-established entities in our ontology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   29 citations  
  • Grasping spheres, not planets.Lawrence J. Taylor & Rolf A. Zwaan - 2010 - Cognition 115 (1):39-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cortical activity and the explanatory gap.John G. Taylor - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (2):109-48.
    An exploration is given of neural network features now being uncovered in cortical processing which begins to go a little way to help bridge the ''Explanatory Gap'' between phenomenal consciousness and correlated brain activity. A survey of properties suggested as being possessed by phenomenal consciousness leads to a set of criteria to be required of the correlated neural activity. Various neural styles of processing are reviewed and those fitting the criteria are selected for further analysis. One particular processing style, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Altered attention for stimuli on the hands.J. Eric T. Taylor & Jessica K. Witt - 2014 - Cognition 133 (1):211-225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Neural Bases of Event Monitoring across Domains: a Simultaneous ERP-fMRI Study.Vincenza Tarantino, Ilaria Mazzonetto, Silvia Formica, Francesco Causin & Antonino Vallesi - 2017 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Image-based object recognition in man, monkey and machine.Michael J. Tarr & Heinrich H. Bülthoff - 1998 - Cognition 67 (1-2):1-20.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Whole-Body Roll Tilt Influences Goal-Directed Upper Limb Movements through the Perceptual Tilt of Egocentric Reference Frame.Keisuke Tani, Yoshihide Shiraki, Shinji Yamamoto, Yasushi Kodaka & Keisuke Kushiro - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Spatial task context makes short-latency reaches prone to induced Roelofs illusion.Bahareh Taghizadeh & Alexander Gail - 2014 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does sensitivity in binary choice tasks depend on response modality?Izabela Szumska, Rob H. J. van der Lubbe, Lukasz Grzeczkowski & Michael H. Herzog - 2016 - Consciousness and Cognition 43:57-65.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The contributions of vision and haptics to reaching and grasping.Kayla D. Stone & Claudia L. R. Gonzalez - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Modular architectures and informational encapsulation: A dilemma.Dustin Stokes & Vincent Bergeron - 2015 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 5 (3):315-38.
    Amongst philosophers and cognitive scientists, modularity remains a popular choice for an architecture of the human mind, primarily because of the supposed explanatory value of this approach. Modular architectures can vary both with respect to the strength of the notion of modularity and the scope of the modularity of mind. We propose a dilemma for modular architectures, no matter how these architectures vary along these two dimensions. First, if a modular architecture commits to the informational encapsulation of modules, as it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Modality-specificity of Selective Attention Networks.Hannah J. Stewart & Sygal Amitay - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Numeric comparison in a visually-guided manual reaching task.Joo-Hyun Song & Ken Nakayama - 2008 - Cognition 106 (2):994-1003.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Found and missed: Failing to recognize a search target despite moving it.Grayden Jf Solman, J. Allan Cheyne & Daniel Smilek - 2012 - Cognition 123 (1):100-118.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • In the dark about pointing: What's the point?John F. Soechting, Stephen I. Helms Tillery & Martha Flanders - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):354-362.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representation and knowledge are not the same thing.Leslie Smith - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5):784-785.
    Two standard epistemological accounts are conflated in Dienes & Perner's account of knowledge, and this conflation requires the rejection of their four conditions of knowledge. Because their four metarepresentations applied to the explicit-implicit distinction are paired with these conditions, it follows by modus tollens that if the latter are inadequate, then so are the former. Quite simply, their account misses the link between true reasoning and knowledge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Making sense of the libertarian’s semantic claim about agential phenomenology.Andrew Sims - 2018 - Philosophical Explorations 22 (1):16-32.
    Libertarians about free will sometimes argue for their position on the grounds that our phenomenology of action is such that determinism would need to be false for it to be veridical. Many, however, have thought that it would be impossible for us to have an experience that is in contradiction with determinism, since this would require us to have perceptual experience of metaphysical facts. In this paper I show how the libertarian claim is possible. In particular, if experience depicts the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Modelling ourselves: what the free energy principle reveals about our implicit notions of representation.Matt Sims & Giovanni Pezzulo - 2021 - Synthese 199 (3-4):7801-7833.
    Predictive processing theories are increasingly popular in philosophy of mind; such process theories often gain support from the Free Energy Principle —a normative principle for adaptive self-organized systems. Yet there is a current and much discussed debate about conflicting philosophical interpretations of FEP, e.g., representational versus non-representational. Here we argue that these different interpretations depend on implicit assumptions about what qualifies as representational. We deploy the Free Energy Principle instrumentally to distinguish four main notions of representation, which focus on organizational, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Change blindness: Past, present, and future. [REVIEW]Daniel J. Simons & Ronald A. Rensink - 2005 - Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (1):16-20.
    Change blindness is the striking failure to see large changes that normally would be noticed easily. Over the past decade this phenomenon has greatly contributed to our understanding of attention, perception, and even consciousness. The surprising extent of change blindness explains its broad appeal, but its counterintuitive nature has also engendered confusions about the kinds of inferences that legitimately follow from it. Here we discuss the legitimate and the erroneous inferences that have been drawn, and offer a set of requirements (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   119 citations  
  • Postdiction: its implications on visual awareness, hindsight, and sense of agency.Shinsuke Shimojo - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Visual Awareness Due to Neuronal Activities in Subcortical Structures: A Proposal.Terence V. Sewards & Mark A. Sewards - 2000 - Consciousness and Cognition 9 (1):86-116.
    It has been shown that visual awareness in the blind hemifield of hemianopic cats that have undergone unilateral ablations of visual cortex can be restored by sectioning the commissure of the superior colliculus or by destroying a portion of the substantia nigra contralateral to the cortical lesion (the Sprague effect). We propose that the visual awareness that is recovered is due to synchronized oscillatory activities in the superior colliculus ipsilateral to the cortical lesion. These oscillatory activities are normally partially suppressed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Neural darwinism and consciousness.Anil K. Seth & Bernard J. Baars - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):140-168.
    Neural Darwinism (ND) is a large scale selectionist theory of brain development and function that has been hypothesized to relate to consciousness. According to ND, consciousness is entailed by reentrant interactions among neuronal populations in the thalamocortical system (the ‘dynamic core’). These interactions, which permit high-order discriminations among possible core states, confer selective advantages on organisms possessing them by linking current perceptual events to a past history of value-dependent learning. Here, we assess the consistency of ND with 16 widely recognized (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • The functional neuroanatomy of prelexical processing in speech perception.Sophie K. Scott & Richard J. S. Wise - 2004 - Cognition 92 (1-2):13-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Movement plans for posture selection do not transfer across hands.Christoph Schütz & Thomas Schack - 2015 - Frontiers in Psychology 6.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What does linear vection tell us about the optokinetic pathway?Xavier M. Sauvan - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (2):330-330.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Limb apraxia and the “affordance competition hypothesis”.Elisabeth Rounis & Glyn Humphreys - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Implicit short-lived motor representations of space in brain damaged and healthy subjects.Yves Rossetti - 1998 - Consciousness and Cognition 7 (3):520-558.
    This article reviews experimental evidence for a specific sensorimotor function which can be dissociated from higher level representations of space. It attempts to delineate this function on the basis of results obtained by psychophysical experiments performed with brain damaged and healthy subjects. Eye and hand movement control exhibit automatic features, such that they are incompatible with conscious control. In addition, they rely on a reference frame different from the one used by conscious perception. Neuropsychological cases provide a strong support for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Attentional persistence for features of hierarchical patterns.Lynn C. Robertson - 1996 - Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 125 (3):227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Representation, space and Hollywood squares: Looking at things that aren't there anymore.Daniel C. Richardson & Michael J. Spivey - 2000 - Cognition 76 (3):269-295.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The role of size constancy for the integration of local elements into a global shape.Johannes Rennig, Hans-Otto Karnath & Elisabeth Huberle - 2013 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Change Blindness.Ronald A. Rensink - 2005 - In Laurent Itti, Geraint Rees & John K. Tsotsos (eds.), Neurobiology of Attention. Academic Press. pp. 76--81.
    Large changes that occur in clear view of an observer can become difficult to notice if made during an eye movement, blink, or other such disturbance. This change blindness is consistent with the proposal that focused visual attention is necessary to see change, with a change becoming difficult to notice whenever conditions prevent attention from being automatically drawn to it. -/- It is shown here how the phenomenon of change blindness can provide new results on the nature of visual attention, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Divisions within the posterior parietal cortex help touch meet vision.Catherine L. Reed - 2007 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (2):218-218.
    The parietal cortex is divided into two major functional regions: the anterior parietal cortex that includes primary somatosensory cortex, and the posterior parietal cortex (PPC) that includes the rest of the parietal lobe. The PPC contains multiple representations of space. In Dijkerman & de Haan's (D&dH's) model, higher spatial representations are separate from PPC functions. This model should be developed further so that the functions of the somatosensory system are integrated with specific functions within the PPC and higher spatial representations. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The phenomenal content of experience.Athanassios Raftopoulos & Vincent C. Müller - 2006 - Mind and Language 21 (2):187-219.
    We discuss at some length evidence from the cognitive science suggesting that the representations of objects based on spatiotemporal information and featural information retrieved bottomup from a visual scene precede representations of objects that include conceptual information. We argue that a distinction can be drawn between representations with conceptual and nonconceptual content. The distinction is based on perceptual mechanisms that retrieve information in conceptually unmediated ways. The representational contents of the states induced by these mechanisms that are available to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Perceptual systems and realism.Athanasios Raftopoulos - 2008 - Synthese 164 (1):61 - 91.
    Constructivism undermines realism by arguing that experience is mediated by concepts, and that there is no direct way to examine those aspects of objects that belong to them independently of our conceptualizations; perception is theory-laden. To defend realism one has to show first that perception relates us directly with the world without any intermediary conceptual framework. The result of this direct link is the nonconceptual content of experience. Second, one has to show that part of the nonconceptual content extracted from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is perception informationally encapsulated? The issue of the theory‐ladenness of perception.Athanassios Raftopoulos - 2001 - Cognitive Science 25 (3):423-451.
    Fodor has argued that observation is theory neutral, since the perceptual systems are modular, that is, they are domain‐specific, encapsulated, mandatory, fast, hard‐wired in the organism, and have a fixed neural architecture. Churchland attacks the theoretical neutrality of observation on the grounds that (a) the abundant top‐down pathways in the brain suggest the cognitive penetration of perception and (b) perceptual learning can change in the wiring of the perceptual systems. In this paper I introduce a distinction between sensation, perception, and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Defending realism on the proper ground.Athanassios Raftopoulos - 2006 - Philosophical Psychology 19 (1):47-77.
    'Epistemological constructivism' holds that vision is mediated by background preconceptions and is theory-laden. Hence, two persons with differing theoretical commitments see the world differently and they could agree on what they see only if they both espoused the same conceptual framework. This, in its turn, undermines the possibility of theory testing and choice on a common theory-neutral empirical basis. In this paper, I claim that the cognitive sciences suggest that a part of vision may be only indirectly penetrated by cognition (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Ambiguous figures and representationalism.Athanasios Raftopoulos - 2011 - Synthese 181 (3):489-514.
    Macpherson (Nous 40(1):82–117, 2006) argues that the square/regular diamond figure threatens representationalism, construed as the theory which holds that the phenomenal character is explained by the nonconceptual content of experience. Her argument is the claim that representationalism is committed to the thesis that differences in the experience of ambiguous figures, the gestalt switch, should be explained by differences in the NCC of perception of these figures. However, with respect to the square/regular diamond and some other ambiguous figure representationalism fails to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • XII—Why Are Indexicals Essential?Simon Prosser - 2015 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 115 (3pt3):211-233.
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 115, Issue 3pt3, Page 211-233, December 2015.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Synthetic synaesthesia and sensory substitution.Michael J. Proulx - 2010 - Consciousness and Cognition 19 (1):501-503.
    Visual information can be provided to blind users through sensory substitution devices that convert images into sound. Through extensive use to develop expertise, some blind users have reported visual experiences when using such a device. These blind expert users have also reported visual phenomenology to other sounds even when not using the device. The blind users acquired synthetic synaesthesia, with visual experience evoked by sounds only after gaining such expertise. Sensorimotor learning may facilitate and perhaps even be required to develop (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Affordances and Phenomenal Character in Spatial Perception.Simon Prosser - 2011 - Philosophical Review 120 (4):475-513.
    Intentionalism is the view that the phenomenal character of a conscious experience is wholly determined by, or even reducible to, its representational content. In this essay I put forward a version of intentionalism that allows (though does not require) the reduction of phenomenal character to representational content. Unlike other reductionist theories, however, it does not require the acceptance of phenomenal externalism (the view that phenomenal character does not supervene on the internal state of the subject). According the view offered here, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • S-O-R: Wrong model for pointing.William T. Powers - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (2):349-350.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Role for the Action Observation Network in Apraxia After Stroke.Gloria Pizzamiglio, Zuo Zhang, James Kolasinski, Jane M. Riddoch, Richard E. Passingham, Dante Mantini & Elisabeth Rounis - 2019 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 13.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How do the body schema and the body image interact?Victor Pitron, Adrian Alsmith & Frédérique de Vignemont - 2018 - Consciousness and Cognition 65 (C):352-358.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Visual adaptation and the purpose of perception.Ian Phillips & Chaz Firestone - 2023 - Analysis 83 (3):555-575.
    What is the purpose of perception? And how might the answer to this question help distinguish perception from other mental processes? Block’s landmark book, The.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The neural representation of Arabic digits in visual cortex.Lien Peters, Bert De Smedt & Hans P. Op de Beeck - 2015 - Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Uma abordagem naturalista da consciência humana.Alfredo Pereira Júnior - 2003 - Trans/Form/Ação 26 (2):109-141.
    This essay discusses some central philosophical problems concerning the naturalistic concept of consciousness, as well as evidence from neuropsychology and neurophysiology regarding the relation of brain activity and conscious experience. Initially I review the problem of defining "consciousness", the philosophical approach to the phenomenon and its relation to emotional processes. The next step is a proposal of three conditions for the attribution of consciousness to physical systems. In the following section, I identify different modalities of consciousness and their respective neural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark