Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The link between brain learning, attention, and consciousness.Stephen Grossberg - 1999 - Consciousness and Cognition 8 (1):1-44.
    The processes whereby our brains continue to learn about a changing world in a stable fashion throughout life are proposed to lead to conscious experiences. These processes include the learning of top-down expectations, the matching of these expectations against bottom-up data, the focusing of attention upon the expected clusters of information, and the development of resonant states between bottom-up and top-down processes as they reach an attentive consensus between what is expected and what is there in the outside world. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Explaining behavior: Bringing the brain back in.S. Skarda - 1986 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 29 (June):187-201.
    What is needed today is a biologically grounded explanation of behavior, one that moves beyond the so?called mind?body problem. Yet no solution will be found by philosophers who refuse to learn about how brains and bodies work, or by neuroscientists pursuing experimental research based on outmoded or blatantly anti?biological theories. Churchland's book proposes a solution: to come by a unified theory of the mind?brain philosophers have to work together with neuroscientists. Yet Churchland's vision of a unified theory is based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Precis of the modularity of mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):1-42.
    The Modularity of Mind proposes an alternative to the or view of cognitive architecture that has dominated several decades of cognitive science. Whereas interactionism stresses the continuity of perceptual and cognitive processes, modularity theory argues for their distinctness. It is argued, in particular, that the apparent plausibility of New Look theorizing derives from the failure to distinguish between the (correct) claim that perceptual processes are inferential and the (dubious) claim that they are unencapsidated, that is, that they are arbitrarily sensitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   279 citations  
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   665 citations  
  • Are connectionist models cognitive?Benny Shanon - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (3):235-255.
    In their critique of connectionist models Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) dismiss such models as not being cognitive or psychological. Evaluating Fodor and Pylyshyn's critique requires examining what is required in characterizating models as 'cognitive'. The present discussion examines the various senses of this term. It argues the answer to the title question seems to vary with these different senses. Indeed, by one sense of the term, neither representa-tionalism nor connectionism is cognitive. General ramifications of such an appraisal are discussed and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • The thesis of theory-Laden observation in the light of cognitive psychology.Anna Estany - 2001 - Philosophy of Science 68 (2):203-217.
    The aim of this paper is to analyze a philosophical question (neutrality vs. theory-ladenness of observation) taking into consideration the empirical results of Cognitive Psychology (theories of perception). This is an important debate because the objectivity of science is at stake. In the Philosophy of Science there are two main positions with regard to observation, those of C. Hempel and N. R. Hanson. In the Philosophy of Mind there are also two important contrasting positions, those of J. Fodor and Paul (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Life, mind, agency: Why Markov blankets fail the test of evolution.Walter Veit & Heather Browning - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e214.
    There has been much criticism of the idea that Friston's free-energy principle can unite the life and mind sciences. Here, we argue that perhaps the greatest problem for the totalizing ambitions of its proponents is a failure to recognize the importance of evolutionary dynamics and to provide a convincing adaptive story relating free-energy minimization to organismal fitness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Connectionist learning procedures.Geoffrey E. Hinton - 1989 - Artificial Intelligence 40 (1-3):185-234.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • A Neurodynamic Model of Feature-Based Spatial Selection.Mateja Marić & Dražen Domijan - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Validity of Simulating Stagewise Development by Means of PDP Networks: Application of Catastrophe Analysis and an Experimental Test of Rule‐Like Network Performance.Maartje E. J. Raijmakers, Sylvester von Koten & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (1):101-136.
    This article addresses the ability of Parallel Distributed Processing (PDP) networks to generate stagewise cognitive development in accordance with Piaget's theory of cognitive epigenesis. We carried out a replication study of the simulation experiments by McClelland (1989) and McClelland and Jenkins (1991) in which a PDP network learns to solve balance scale problems. In objective tests motivated from catastrophe theory, a mathematical theory of transitions in epigenetical systems, no evidence for stage transitions in network performance was found. It is concluded (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Why do some neurons in cortex respond to information in a selective manner? Insights from artificial neural networks.Jeffrey S. Bowers, Ivan I. Vankov, Markus F. Damian & Colin J. Davis - 2016 - Cognition 148 (C):47-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Näätänen's auditory model from a visual perspective.Marinus N. Verbaten - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):256-257.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attentional influence on the mismatch negativity.Marty G. Woldorff & Steven A. Hillyard - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):258-260.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Attention and recognition learning by adaptive resonance.Stephen Grossberg - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):241-242.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is ERP the right key to open the “black box”?George Karmos & Valéria Csépe - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):245-246.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ERPs and the fate of unattended stimuli.Michael D. Rugg - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):251-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward an evolutionary perspective on hemispheric specialization.Michael C. Corballis - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):69-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Psychology and computational architecture.John Haugeland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaos can be overplayed.René Thom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):182-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chaos, symbols, and connectionism.John A. Barnden - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):174-175.
    The paper is a commentary on the target article by Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman, “How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world”, in the same issue of the journal, pp.161–195. -/- I confine my comments largely to some philosophical claims that Skarda & Freeman make and to the relationship of their model to connectionism. Some of the comments hinge on what symbols are and how they might sit in neural systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Direct vs. representational views of cognition: A parallel between vision and phonology.Samuel Jay Keyser & Steven Pinker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):389-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Visual perception is underdetermined by stimulation.John W. Gyr - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):386-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sanity surrounded by madness.Georges Rey - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):48-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • On the proper treatment of Smolensky.Hubert L. Dreyfus & Stuart E. Dreyfus - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Preparatory response hypotheses: A muddle of causal and functional analyses.Karen L. Hollis - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):145-146.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Associative theory versus classical conditioning: Their proper relationship.E. James Kehoe - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):147-147.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Complexity at the organismic and neuronal levels.R. W. Kentridge - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):147-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Beyond Pavlovian classical conditioning.Beatrix T. Gardner & R. Allen Gardner - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):143-144.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classical conditioning: A parsimonious analysis?Anthony L. Riley - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):157-158.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the conceptual foundations of cognitive psychophysiology.Emanuel Donchin & Michael G. H. Coles - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):408.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classical conditioning: The new hegemony.Jaylan Sheila Turkkan - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):121-137.
    Converging data from different disciplines are showing the role of classical conditioning processes in the elaboration of human and animal behavior to be larger than previously supposed. Restricted views of classically conditioned responses as merely secretory, reflexive, or emotional are giving way to a broader conception that includes problem-solving, and other rule-governed behavior thought to be the exclusive province of either operant conditiońing or cognitive psychology. These new views have been accompanied by changes in the way conditioning is conducted and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Reflections on closure and context, with a note on the hippocampus.R. E. Hampson & S. A. Deadwyler - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Event-related potentials and cognition: A critique of the context updating hypothesis and an alternative interpretation of P3.Rolf Verleger - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):343.
    P3 is the most prominent of the electrical potentials of the human electroencephalogram that are sensitive to psychological variables. According to the most influential current hypothesis about its psychological significance [E. Donchin's], the “context updating” hypothesis, P3 reflects the updating of working memory. This hypothesis cannot account for relevant portions of the available evidence and it entails some basic contradictions. A more general formulation of this hypothesis is that P3 reflects the updating of expectancies. This version implies that P3-evoking stimuli (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • The value of modeling visual attention.Gary W. Strong & Bruce A. Whitehead - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):419-433.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the tag necessary?Ron Sun & Emmanuel Schalit - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):415-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On choosing the “right” stimulus and rule.Robin M. Hogarth - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):596-596.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can Skinner define a problem?Geir Kaufmann - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):599-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implementations, algorithms, and more.John R. Anderson - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):498-505.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nonverbal knowledge as algorithms.Chris Mortensen - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):487-488.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Applying Marr to memory.Keith Stenning - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):494-495.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On Spearman's “problem of correlation”.John B. Carroll - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):7-7.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Gall's reputation and some recent “new phrenology”.C. G. Gross - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):16-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue.Martin J. Pickering & Simon Garrod - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (2):169-190.
    Traditional mechanistic accounts of language processing derive almost entirely from the study of monologue. Yet, the most natural and basic form of language use is dialogue. As a result, these accounts may only offer limited theories of the mechanisms that underlie language processing in general. We propose a mechanistic account of dialogue, the interactive alignment account, and use it to derive a number of predictions about basic language processes. The account assumes that, in dialogue, the linguistic representations employed by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   261 citations  
  • Consciousness, art, and the brain: Lessons from Marcel Proust.Russell Epstein - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (2):213-40.
    In his novel Remembrance of Things Past, Marcel Proust argues that conventional descriptions of the phenomenology of consciousness are incomplete because they focus too much on the highly-salient sensory information that dominates each moment of awareness and ignore the network of associations that lies in the background. In this paper, I explicate Proust’s theory of conscious experience and show how it leads him directly to a theory of aesthetic perception. Proust’s division of awareness into two components roughly corresponds to William (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Autonomous processing in parallel distributed processing networks.Michael R. W. Dawson & Don P. Schopflocher - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (2):199-219.
    This paper critically examines the claim that parallel distributed processing (PDP) networks are autonomous learning systems. A PDP model of a simple distributed associative memory is considered. It is shown that the 'generic' PDP architecture cannot implement the computations required by this memory system without the aid of external control. In other words, the model is not autonomous. Two specific problems are highlighted: (i) simultaneous learning and recall are not permitted to occur as would be required of an autonomous system; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • On the proper treatment of connectionism.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):1-23.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   750 citations  
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Cortical dynamics of three-dimensional figure–ground perception of two-dimensional pictures.Stephen Grossberg - 1997 - Psychological Review 104 (3):618-658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A Neural Theory of Visual Attention: Bridging Cognition and Neurophysiology.Claus Bundesen, Thomas Habekost & Søren Kyllingsbæk - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (2):291-328.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Binocular fusion and invariant category learning due to predictive remapping during scanning of a depthful scene with eye movements.Stephen Grossberg, Karthik Srinivasan & Arash Yazdanbakhsh - 2014 - Frontiers in Psychology 5.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations