Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Cortical dynamics of three-dimensional figure–ground perception of two-dimensional pictures.Stephen Grossberg - 1997 - Psychological Review 104 (3):618-658.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Toward a mechanistic psychology of dialogue.Martin J. Pickering & Simon Garrod - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (2):169-190.
    Traditional mechanistic accounts of language processing derive almost entirely from the study of monologue. Yet, the most natural and basic form of language use is dialogue. As a result, these accounts may only offer limited theories of the mechanisms that underlie language processing in general. We propose a mechanistic account of dialogue, the interactive alignment account, and use it to derive a number of predictions about basic language processes. The account assumes that, in dialogue, the linguistic representations employed by the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   260 citations  
  • An integrated theory of language production and comprehension.Martin J. Pickering & Simon Garrod - 2013 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (4):329-347.
    Currently, production and comprehension are regarded as quite distinct in accounts of language processing. In rejecting this dichotomy, we instead assert that producing and understanding are interwoven, and that this interweaving is what enables people to predict themselves and each other. We start by noting that production and comprehension are forms of action and action perception. We then consider the evidence for interweaving in action, action perception, and joint action, and explain such evidence in terms of prediction. Specifically, we assume (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   158 citations  
  • The role of attention in auditory information processing as revealed by event-related potentials and other brain measures of cognitive function.Risto Näätänen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):201-233.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Cerebral hemispheres: Specialized for the analysis of what?Michael Studdert-Kennedy - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Premature closure of controversial issues concerning animal memory representations.William A. Roberts - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Memory representations in animals: Some metatheoretical issues.Roy Lachman & Janet L. Lachman - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):380-381.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The meaning of representation in animal memory.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):353-372.
    A representation is a remnant of previous experience that allows that experience to affect later behavior. This paper develops a metatheoretical view of representation and applies it to issues concerning representation in animals. To describe a representational system one must specify the following: thedomainor range of situations in the represented world to which the system applies; thecontentor set of features encoded and preserved by the system; thecodeor transformational rules relating features of the representation to the corresponding features of the represented (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   312 citations  
  • Functional architectures for cognition: are simple inferences possible?Steven W. Zucker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):153-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plasticity: conceptual and neuronal.Paul M. Churchland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chaos, symbols, and connectionism.John A. Barnden - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):174-175.
    The paper is a commentary on the target article by Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman, “How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world”, in the same issue of the journal, pp.161–195. -/- I confine my comments largely to some philosophical claims that Skarda & Freeman make and to the relationship of their model to connectionism. Some of the comments hinge on what symbols are and how they might sit in neural systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychology and computational architecture.John Haugeland - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):138-139.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaos in brains: Fad or insight?Donald H. Perkel - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):180-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world.Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):161-173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   448 citations  
  • On the nature of information in behalf of direct perception.Rebecca K. Jones & Anne D. Pick - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):388-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Direct vs. representational views of cognition: A parallel between vision and phonology.Samuel Jay Keyser & Steven Pinker - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):389-390.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Difficulties with a direct theory of perception.Irvin Rock - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Inferring the meaning of direct perception.Geoffrey E. Hinton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):387-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Putting together connectionism – again.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):59-74.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Connectionism and the study of language.R. Freidin - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Smolensky, semantics, and the sensorimotor system.George Lakoff - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):39-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Two constructive themes.Richard K. Belew - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):25-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pavlovian conditioning: Providing a bridge between cognition and biology.Marvin D. Krank - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):151-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Classical conditioning: The role of interdisciplinary theory.Stephen Grossberg - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):144-145.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Response utility in classical and operant conditioning.Edmund Fantino - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):141-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mis-representations.J. Bruce Overmier - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):156-157.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning and functional utility.Barry R. Dworkin - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):139-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Novelty and the P3.Marinus N. Verbaten - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is the P300 component a manifestation of context updating?Emanuel Donchin & Michael G. H. Coles - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):357.
    To understand the endogenous components of the event-related brain potential (ERP), we must use data about the components' antecedent conditions to form hypotheses about the information-processing function of the underlying brain activity. These hypotheses, in turn, generate testable predictions about the consequences of the component. We review the application of this approach to the analysis of the P300 component. The amplitude of the P300 is controlled multiplicatively by the subjective probability and the task relevance of the eliciting events, whereas its (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   194 citations  
  • Event-related potentials and cognition: A critique of the context updating hypothesis and an alternative interpretation of P3.Rolf Verleger - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):343.
    P3 is the most prominent of the electrical potentials of the human electroencephalogram that are sensitive to psychological variables. According to the most influential current hypothesis about its psychological significance [E. Donchin's], the “context updating” hypothesis, P3 reflects the updating of working memory. This hypothesis cannot account for relevant portions of the available evidence and it entails some basic contradictions. A more general formulation of this hypothesis is that P3 reflects the updating of expectancies. This version implies that P3-evoking stimuli (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   115 citations  
  • Experimental test of a network theory of vision.David H. Foster - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (4):664.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Simultaneous processing of features may not be possible.D. M. Parker - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):411-411.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • New wine in old glasses?Joseph M. Scandura - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):602-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there such a thing as a problem situation?Kjell Raaheim - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):600-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An operant analysis of problem solving.B. F. Skinner - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):583-591.
    Behavior that solves a problem is distinguished by the fact that it changes another part of the solver's behavior and is strengthened when it does so. Problem solving typically involves the construction of discriminative stimuli. Verbal responses produce especially useful stimuli, because they affect other people. As a culture formulates maxims, laws, grammar, and science, its members behave more effectively without direct or prolonged contact with the contingencies thus formulated. The culture solves problems for its members, and does so by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • Underestimating the importance of the implementational level.Michael Van Kleeck - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):497-498.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Competitive Learning: From Interactive Activation to Adaptive Resonance.Stephen Grossberg - 1987 - Cognitive Science 11 (1):23-63.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   245 citations  
  • The link between brain learning, attention, and consciousness.Stephen Grossberg - 1999 - Consciousness and Cognition 8 (1):1-44.
    The processes whereby our brains continue to learn about a changing world in a stable fashion throughout life are proposed to lead to conscious experiences. These processes include the learning of top-down expectations, the matching of these expectations against bottom-up data, the focusing of attention upon the expected clusters of information, and the development of resonant states between bottom-up and top-down processes as they reach an attentive consensus between what is expected and what is there in the outside world. It (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Precis of the modularity of mind.Jerry A. Fodor - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (1):1-42.
    The Modularity of Mind proposes an alternative to the or view of cognitive architecture that has dominated several decades of cognitive science. Whereas interactionism stresses the continuity of perceptual and cognitive processes, modularity theory argues for their distinctness. It is argued, in particular, that the apparent plausibility of New Look theorizing derives from the failure to distinguish between the (correct) claim that perceptual processes are inferential and the (dubious) claim that they are unencapsidated, that is, that they are arbitrarily sensitive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   277 citations  
  • Computation and cognition: Issues in the foundation of cognitive science.Zenon W. Pylyshyn - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (1):111-32.
    The computational view of mind rests on certain intuitions regarding the fundamental similarity between computation and cognition. We examine some of these intuitions and suggest that they derive from the fact that computers and human organisms are both physical systems whose behavior is correctly described as being governed by rules acting on symbolic representations. Some of the implications of this view are discussed. It is suggested that a fundamental hypothesis of this approach is that there is a natural domain of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   664 citations  
  • Autonomous processing in parallel distributed processing networks.Michael R. W. Dawson & Don P. Schopflocher - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (2):199-219.
    This paper critically examines the claim that parallel distributed processing (PDP) networks are autonomous learning systems. A PDP model of a simple distributed associative memory is considered. It is shown that the 'generic' PDP architecture cannot implement the computations required by this memory system without the aid of external control. In other words, the model is not autonomous. Two specific problems are highlighted: (i) simultaneous learning and recall are not permitted to occur as would be required of an autonomous system; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • On the proper treatment of connectionism.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):1-23.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   746 citations  
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Mechanisms for the generation and regulation of sequential behaviour.Richard P. Cooper - 2003 - Philosophical Psychology 16 (3):389 – 416.
    A critical aspect of much human behaviour is the generation and regulation of sequential activities. Such behaviour is seen in both naturalistic settings such as routine action and language production and laboratory tasks such as serial recall and many reaction time experiments. There are a variety of computational mechanisms that may support the generation and regulation of sequential behaviours, ranging from those underlying Turing machines to those employed by recurrent connectionist networks. This paper surveys a range of such mechanisms, together (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Consciousness, art, and the brain: Lessons from Marcel Proust.Russell Epstein - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (2):213-40.
    In his novel Remembrance of Things Past, Marcel Proust argues that conventional descriptions of the phenomenology of consciousness are incomplete because they focus too much on the highly-salient sensory information that dominates each moment of awareness and ignore the network of associations that lies in the background. In this paper, I explicate Proust’s theory of conscious experience and show how it leads him directly to a theory of aesthetic perception. Proust’s division of awareness into two components roughly corresponds to William (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Explaining behavior: Bringing the brain back in.S. Skarda - 1986 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 29 (June):187-201.
    What is needed today is a biologically grounded explanation of behavior, one that moves beyond the so?called mind?body problem. Yet no solution will be found by philosophers who refuse to learn about how brains and bodies work, or by neuroscientists pursuing experimental research based on outmoded or blatantly anti?biological theories. Churchland's book proposes a solution: to come by a unified theory of the mind?brain philosophers have to work together with neuroscientists. Yet Churchland's vision of a unified theory is based on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Are connectionist models cognitive?Benny Shanon - 1992 - Philosophical Psychology 5 (3):235-255.
    In their critique of connectionist models Fodor and Pylyshyn (1988) dismiss such models as not being cognitive or psychological. Evaluating Fodor and Pylyshyn's critique requires examining what is required in characterizating models as 'cognitive'. The present discussion examines the various senses of this term. It argues the answer to the title question seems to vary with these different senses. Indeed, by one sense of the term, neither representa-tionalism nor connectionism is cognitive. General ramifications of such an appraisal are discussed and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Brain symbols and computationalist explanation.William S. Robinson - 1995 - Minds and Machines 5 (1):25-44.
    Computationalist theories of mind require brain symbols, that is, neural events that represent kinds or instances of kinds. Standard models of computation require multiple inscriptions of symbols with the same representational content. The satisfaction of two conditions makes it easy to see how this requirement is met in computers, but we have no reason to think that these conditions are satisfied in the brain. Thus, if we wish to give computationalist explanations of human cognition, without committing ourselvesa priori to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The thesis of theory-Laden observation in the light of cognitive psychology.Anna Estany - 2001 - Philosophy of Science 68 (2):203-217.
    The aim of this paper is to analyze a philosophical question (neutrality vs. theory-ladenness of observation) taking into consideration the empirical results of Cognitive Psychology (theories of perception). This is an important debate because the objectivity of science is at stake. In the Philosophy of Science there are two main positions with regard to observation, those of C. Hempel and N. R. Hanson. In the Philosophy of Mind there are also two important contrasting positions, those of J. Fodor and Paul (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • The Emperor's New Markov Blankets.Jelle Bruineberg, Krzysztof Dołęga, Joe Dewhurst & Manuel Baltieri - 2022 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45:e183.
    The free energy principle, an influential framework in computational neuroscience and theoretical neurobiology, starts from the assumption that living systems ensure adaptive exchanges with their environment by minimizing the objective function of variational free energy. Following this premise, it claims to deliver a promising integration of the life sciences. In recent work, Markov blankets, one of the central constructs of the free energy principle, have been applied to resolve debates central to philosophy (such as demarcating the boundaries of the mind). (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations