Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. “Consciousness” is the name of a nonentity.Deborah Hodgkin & Alasdair I. Houston - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):611-612.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness, historical inversion, and cognitive science.Andrew W. Young - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):630-631.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness and accessibility.Ned Block - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):596-598.
    This is my first publication of the distinction between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness, though not using quite those terms. It ends with this: "The upshot is this: If Searle is using the access sense of "consciousness," his argument doesn't get to first base. If, as is more likely, he intends the what-it-is-like sense, his argument depends on assumptions about issues that the cognitivist is bound to regard as deeply unsettled empirical questions." Searle replies: "He refers to what he calls (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Intentionality: Some distinctions.Gilbert Harman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):607-608.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the differences between cognitive and noncognitive systems.D. C. Earle - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):177-178.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The virtues of chaos.Alan Garfinkel - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):178-179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chaos in brains: Fad or insight?Donald H. Perkel - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):180-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaos, symbols, and connectionism.John A. Barnden - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):174-175.
    The paper is a commentary on the target article by Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman, “How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world”, in the same issue of the journal, pp.161–195. -/- I confine my comments largely to some philosophical claims that Skarda & Freeman make and to the relationship of their model to connectionism. Some of the comments hinge on what symbols are and how they might sit in neural systems.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How brains make chaos in order to make sense of the world.Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):161-173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   448 citations  
  • On doing research on consciousness without being aware of it.Daniel Holender - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):612-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does cognitive science need “real” intentionality?Robert J. Matthews - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):616-617.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Somebody flew over Searle's ontological prison.Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):618-619.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Spatial analysis of brain function:Not the first.Robert M. Boynton - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):175-175.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Chaotic dynamics in brain activity.A. Babloyantz - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):173-174.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Consciousness, explanatory inversion and cognitive science.John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):585-642.
    Cognitive science typically postulates unconscious mental phenomena, computational or otherwise, to explain cognitive capacities. The mental phenomena in question are supposed to be inaccessible in principle to consciousness. I try to show that this is a mistake, because all unconscious intentionality must be accessible in principle to consciousness; we have no notion of intrinsic intentionality except in terms of its accessibility to consciousness. I call this claim the The argument for it proceeds in six steps. The essential point is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   289 citations  
  • Who is computing with the brain?John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):632-642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Matter, levels, and consciousness.Jerry R. Hobbs - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):610-611.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unintended thought and nonconscious inferences exist.James S. Uleman & Jennifer K. Uleman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):627-628.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Accessibility “in principle”.Noam Chomsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):600-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Language and the deep unconscious mind: Aspectualities of the theory of syntax.B. Elan Dresher & Norbert Hornstein - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):602-603.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Searle's Freudian slip.Hubert L. Dreyfus - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):603-604.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness as physiological self-organizing process.Walter J. Freeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):604-605.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Stable self-organization of sensory recognition codes: Is chaos necessary?Stephen Grossberg - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):179-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A non‐representational approach to imagined action.Iris Rooij, Raoul M. Bongers & F. G. Haselager - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (3):345-375.
    This study addresses the dynamical nature of a “representation‐hungry” cognitive task involving an imagined action. In our experiment, participants were handed rods that systematically increased or decreased in length on subsequent trials. Participants were asked to judge whether or not they thought they could reach for a distant object with the hand‐held rod. The results are in agreement with a dynamical model, extended from Tuller, Case, Ding, and Kelso (1994). The dynamical effects observed in this study suggest that predictive judgments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The possibility of irreducible intentionality.Charles Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):626-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Physiology: Is there any other game in town?Christine A. Skarda & Walter J. Freeman - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):183-195.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A non-representational approach to imagined action.I. van Rooij - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (3):345-375.
    This study addresses the dynamical nature of a “representation‐hungry” cognitive task involving an imagined action. In our experiment, participants were handed rods that systematically increased or decreased in length on subsequent trials. Participants were asked to judge whether or not they thought they could reach for a distant object with the hand‐held rod. The results are in agreement with a dynamical model, extended from Tuller, Case, Ding, and Kelso (1994). The dynamical effects observed in this study suggest that predictive judgments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Behavioral systems interpreted as autonomous agents and as coupled dynamical systems: A criticism.Fred A. Keijzer & Sacha Bem - 1996 - Philosophical Psychology 9 (3):323-46.
    Cognitive science's basic premises are under attack. In particular, its focus on internal cognitive processes is a target. Intelligence is increasingly interpreted, not as a matter of reclusive thought, but as successful agent-environment interaction. The critics claim that a major reorientation of the field is necessary. However, this will only occur when there is a distinct alternative conceptual framework to replace the old one. Whether or not a serious alternative is provided is not clear. Among the critics there is some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Zombies are people, too.Drew McDermott - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):617-618.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Constituent causation and the reality of mind.Georges Rey - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):620-621.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aspects and algorithms.Andy Clark - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):601-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unconscious mental processes.Clark Glymour - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):606-607.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Is the mind conscious, functional, or both?Max Velmans - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):629-630.
    What, in essence, characterizes the mind? According to Searle, the potential to be conscious provides the only definitive criterion. Thus, conscious states are unquestionably "mental"; "shallow unconscious" states are also "mental" by virtue of their capacity to be conscious (at least in principle); but there are no "deep unconscious mental states" - i.e. those rules and procedures without access to consciousness, inferred by cognitive science to characterize the operations of the unconscious mind are not mental at all. Indeed, according to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Conscious mental episodes and skill acquisition.Richard A. Carlson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):599-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unconscious mental states do have an aspectual shape.Howard Shevrin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):624-625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • When functions are causes.Jonathan Schull - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):622-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionist models as neural abstractions.Ronald Rosenfeld, David S. Touretzky & Boltzmann Group - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):181-182.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can brains make psychological sense of neurological data?Robert Brown - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):175-176.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intention itself will disappear when its mechanisms are known.Bruce Bridgeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):598-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Searle's vision of psychology.James Higginbotham - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):608-610.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Chaos can be overplayed.René Thom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):182-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Loose connections: Four problems in Searie's argument for the “Connection Principle”.Dan Lloyd - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):615-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Conscious and unconscious representation of aspectual shape in cognitive science.Geoffrey Underwood - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):628-629.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Is Searle conscious?John C. Kulli - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):614-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognition as self–organizing process.Gerhard Werner - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):183-183.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On being accessible to consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):621-621.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Ontogeny and intentionality.Philip David Zelazo & J. Steven Reznick - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):631-632.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • When the “chaos” is too chaotic and the “limit cycles” too limited, the mind boggles and the brain flounders.Michael A. Corner & Andre J. Noest - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):176-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is chaos the only alternative to rigidity?Daniel S. Levine - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (2):180-180.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The ability versus intentionality aspects of unconscious mental processes.Maria Czyzewska, Thomas Hill & Pawel Lewicki - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):602-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark