Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. From 'perpetual peace' to 'the law of peoples': Kant, Habermas and Rawls on international relations.Thomas Mertens - 2002 - Kantian Review 6:60-84.
    It is hardly surprising that the two greatest Kantian philosophers of the twentieth century's second half would, at some point of time, reflect and comment on one of the most famous writings of the Königsberg sage, namely on Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch. Of course, in recent decades, and especially around the celebration of the 200th anniversary of its publication, many commentary articles and books have been published on Kant's little essay, but it makes a difference when Jürgen Habermas and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Contemporary scepticism and the cartesian God.Jennifer Nagel - 2005 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35 (3):465-497.
    Descartes claims that God is both incomprehensible and yet clearly and distinctly understood. This paper argues that Descartes’s development of the contrast between comprehension and understanding makes the role of God in his epistemology more interesting than is commonly thought. Section one examines the historical context of sceptical arguments about the difficulty of knowing God. Descartes describes the recognition of our inability to comprehend God as itself a source of knowledge of him; section two aims to explain how recognizing limits (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Socialism as Classical Political Philosophy*: LOREN E. LOMASKY.Loren E. Lomasky - 1989 - Social Philosophy and Policy 6 (2):112-138.
    A small puzzle: the terms ‘capitalism’ and ‘socialism’ initially present themselves as contraries, the one affirming what the other rejects. However, once removed from the dictionary, they function otherwise. The theory of capitalism is very much contained within the science of economics. The positive theory of capitalistic institutions, but also its normative superstructure, rest most easily within the language and methodology of the economist. What distinguishes the free market? It is efficient ; allocation of factors of production are optimized ; (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The New Science and the Public Sphere in the Premodern Era.Jan C. C. Rupp - 1995 - Science in Context 8 (3):487-507.
    The ArgumentThis paper argues that the New Science, which was seen as essentially a public enterprise, was moreover a major constituent of the public sphere in early modern era. In seventeenth-and eighteenth-century Western Europe the sphere of public experimentation, testing, and discussion related to the new science, manifested, itself as a highly diversified, contested, and complex social field.Two general problems arose in constructing this cultural public sphere: the selection of participants in the debate and the inclusion of a heterogenous public (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Individual Autonomy and Global Democracy.Michael Pendlebury - 2004 - Theoria 51 (103):43-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Serpent and the Dove.Susan Mendus - 1988 - Philosophy 63 (245):331 - 343.
    In his essay ‘The Simple Art of Murder’, Raymond Chandler describes the world of the American detective story as ‘a world in which gangsters can rule nations and almost rule cities, in which hotels and apartment houses and celebrated restaurants are owned by men who made their money out of brothels, in which a screen star can be the fingerman for a mob, and the nice man down the hall is a boss of the numbers racket; a world where a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Three Problems with Contractarian-Consequentialist Ways of Assessing Social Institutions*: THOMAS W. POGGE.Thomas W. Pogge - 1995 - Social Philosophy and Policy 12 (2):241-266.
    With each of our three criminal-law topics—defining offenses, apprehending suspects, and establishing punishments—we feel, I believe, strong moral resistance to the idea that our practices should be settled by a prospective-participant perspective. This becomes quite clear when we look at how the “reforms” suggested by institutional viewing might combine once we consider all three topics together: imagine a more extensive and swifter use of the death penalty in homicide cases coupled with somewhat lower standards of evidence; or think of backing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The Principle of Subsidiarity.Stefan Gosepath - 2005 - In Andreas Follesdal & Thomas Pogge (eds.), Real World Justice: Grounds, Principles, Human Rights, and Social Institutions. Springer. pp. 157-170.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Friedrich Schleiermacher’s Theory of the Limited Communitarian State.Jeffrey Hoover - 1990 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (2):241-260.
    While Friedrich Schleiermacher‘s thought has been of overwhelming importance for theology during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, his influence as a philosopher is much more circumscribed and as a social and political thinker it is almost nil.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Idea of "Free Public Reason".Catherine Audard - 1995 - Ratio Juris 8 (1):15-29.
    . In this paper the nature and the role of Rawls's idea of a “free public reason” are examined with an emphasis on the divide between the private and the public spheres, a divide which is the hallmark of a liberal democracy. Criticisms from both the so‐called Continental tradition and the Communitarian opponents to liberalism insist on the ineffectiveness of such a conception, on its inability to establish a political consensus on democracy. But it would be a mistake to see (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is Enlightenment: Can China Answer Kant's Question?Wei Zhang - 2010 - State University of New York Press.
    A cross-cultural work which reinvigorates the consideration of enlightenment.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Are the judgments of conscience unreasonable?Edward Andrew & Peter Lindsay - 2008 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 11 (2):235-254.
    This paper examines the tensions in classical liberal theory ? particularly that of Locke and Kant ? between reason and conscience, and in contemporary liberal theory between the demands of reasonableness and the dictates of conscience. We intend to show that the relationship between reasonableness and conscience is both unstable and necessary; on occasions there seems to exist a moral obligation to provide public reasons for our conduct and at other times the silent call of conscience precludes public justification of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The epistemology of mastery.Jonathan Derbyshire - 1997 - Angelaki 2 (2):103 – 112.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Property, Liberty and On Liberty.Alan Ryan - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 15:217-231.
    There are at least three tolerably distinct views about the connections between liberty and property; two of these I shall discuss fairly briefly in order to get on to Mill's central claims about the relationship between property rights and freedom, but in conclusion I shall return to them to show how they bear on what Mill has to say.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Utilitarianism and the Punishment of the Innocent: The Origins of a False Doctrine.F. Rosen - 1997 - Utilitas 9 (1):23-37.
    This paper examines the commonplace assertion that utilitarianism allows for and even, at times, requires the punishment of the innocent. It traces the origins of this doctrine to the writings of the British Idealists and the subsequent development of what is called the post-utilitarian paradigm which posits various justifications for punishment such as retribution, deterrence and reform, finds all of them inadequate, and then, with the addition of other ideas, reconciles them. The idea of deterrence is falsely depicted as the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Philosophy against and in Praise of Violence: Kant, Thoreau and the Revolutionary Spectator.Avram Alpert - 2016 - Theory, Culture and Society 33 (6):51-73.
    In this article, the author argues that the works of Immanuel Kant and Henry David Thoreau can help reframe current political discussions about violence and nonviolence within revolutionary movements. For both of them, the means and ends of political change must coincide. Since they seek a nonviolent state of affairs, each argues against violent political change. However, they are also concerned to articulate a relationship between armed and unarmed struggle. After all, Kant and Thoreau worked to find what was positive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Property, Liberty and On Liberty.Alan Ryan - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 15:217-231.
    There are at least three tolerably distinct views about the connections between liberty and property; two of these I shall discuss fairly briefly in order to get on to Mill's central claims about the relationship between property rights and freedom, but in conclusion I shall return to them to show how they bear on what Mill has to say.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reason and Justice: The Optimal and the Maximal.Amartya Sen - 2017 - Philosophy 92 (1):5-19.
    This paper is a revised version of the Royal Institute of Philosophy’s Annual Lecture, 2016. It discusses the demands of critical reasoning in ethical arguments, and focuses in particular on the assessment of justice. It disputes the belief that reasoning about choice remains unfinished until an optimal alternative has been identified. A successful closure of a reasoning may identify a maximal alternative, which is not judged to be worse than any other available option. A maximal alternative need not be optimal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Global Citizenship as the Completion of Cosmopolitanism.Luis Cabrera - 2008 - Journal of International Political Theory 4 (1):84-104.
    A conception of global citizenship should not be viewed as separate from, or synonymous with, the cosmopolitan moral orientation, but as a primary component of it. Global citizenship is fundamentally concerned with individual moral requirements in the global frame. Such requirements, framed here as belonging to the category of individual cosmopolitanism, offer guidelines on right action in the context of global human community. They are complementary to the principles of moral cosmopolitanism — those to be used in assessing the justice (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Global megatrends and the community.Masudul Alam Choudhury - 1999 - World Futures 53 (3):229-252.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant on Punishment.Susan Meld Shell - 1997 - Kantian Review 1:115-135.
    Unlike that of most liberal thinkers, Kant's theory of punishment is unabashedly retributive. For classical liberals punishment is justified only by the harms it can prevent, not by any allegedly intrinsic good served by making the guilty suffer. Here Hobbes' blunt insistence that the aim of punishment ‘is not a revenge, but terror’ is prototypical in substance, if not in style. Hobbes, Locke, Mill, Bentham and Beccaria, for all their differences, agree that punishment must look to future good rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The new politics of Afrikaans.Andrew Nash - 2000 - South African Journal of Philosophy 19 (4):340-364.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conflicts in Kant's account of the right to go to war.Georg Cavallar - 1997 - The European Legacy 2 (6):991-999.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Liberalism and fear of violence.Bruce Buchan - 2001 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 4 (3):27-48.
    Liberal political thought is underwritten by an enduring fear of civil and state violence. It is assumed within liberal thought that self?interest characterises relations between individuals in civil society, resulting in violence. In absolutist doctrines, such as Hobbes?, the pacification of private persons depended on the Sovereign's command of a monopoly of violence. Liberals, by contrast, sought to claim that the state itself must be pacified, its capacity for cruelty (e.g., torture) removed, its capacity for violence (e.g., war) reduced and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Confucian Democracy: A Deweyan Reconstruction.Sor-Hoon Tan - 2012 - SUNY Press.
    Using both Confucian texts and the work of American pragmatist John Dewey, this book offers a distinctly Confucian model of democracy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The ethical implications of the straight-commission compensation system — an agency perspective.Nancy B. Kurland - 1991 - Journal of Business Ethics 10 (10):757 - 766.
    This paper examines the role of the straight-commissioned salesperson in the context of agency theory and asserts that because the agent acts to benefit two principals, potential conflicts of interest arise. Temporal differences in receipt of rewards create a major conflict, while the firm's exhibition of both espoused and actual behaviors and information asymmetries intensify this conflict. Finally, in light of these inconsistencies, the ethical implications of the straight-commission compensation system are examined.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • The need for plans, projects and reasoning about ends: Kant and Williams.Salim Kemal - 1997 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (2):187 – 215.
    Critics deny that Kant's moral theory has the resources it needs to guide our actual actions. They reject the power of reason to establish moral rules and they propose alternative notions of person and project. This paper first develops aspects of Kant's moral theory, setting out briefly his notions of personality and the primacy of moral reason. Second it considers an alternative account that has been influential in recent Anglo-American philosophy to show that its understanding of persons and projects fails (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant, Morality and Society.Salim Kemal - 1998 - Kantian Review 2:14-50.
    One usual understanding of Kant's moral theory identifies agents as solitary individuals who reflect on the moral quality of actions ‘in the loneliness of their souls’. Their reflection is autonomous, independent and ‘monological’, with the result that ‘by presupposing autonomy’ Kant ‘expels moral action from the very domain of morality itself’. Instead of an ‘interplay of an intersubjectivity’ in which moral issues arise and are resolved, the autonomous solitary individual seems to derive rules for action from a categorical imperative. Yet (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation