Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Experimental Skills and Experiment Appraisal.Xiang Chen - 1994 - In Peter Achinstein & Laura J. Snyder (eds.), Scientific methods: conceptual and historical problems. Malabar, Fla.: Krieger Pub. Co.. pp. 45--66.
    Traditional philosophy of science believes that scientists can achieve agreement on every experimental result provided it can be replicated in an appropriate way, that is, reproducible with the same experimen­tal arrangement and procedure. By analyzing the role of skills in experiment appraisal, I explain why in fact scientists do not always have consensus on experimental results despite their replication attempts. Based on a detailed analysis of a historical case, I argue that experiment replications inevitably involve a processor skill­ transference, which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Thomas solly (1816–1875):an unknown pioneer of the mathematization of logic in england, 1839.M. Pabteki - 1993 - History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2):133-169.
    (1993). Thomas solly (1816–1875):an unknown pioneer of the mathematization of logic in england, 1839. History and Philosophy of Logic: Vol. 14, No. 2, pp. 133-169.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Hamilton, Hamiltonian Mechanics, and Causation.Christopher Gregory Weaver - 2023 - Foundations of Science:1-45.
    I show how Sir William Rowan Hamilton’s philosophical commitments led him to a causal interpretation of classical mechanics. I argue that Hamilton’s metaphysics of causation was injected into his dynamics by way of a causal interpretation of force. I then detail how forces are indispensable to both Hamilton’s formulation of classical mechanics and what we now call Hamiltonian mechanics (i.e., the modern formulation). On this point, my efforts primarily consist of showing that the contemporary orthodox interpretation of potential energy is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Canonical transformations from Jacobi to Whittaker.Craig Fraser & Michiyo Nakane - 2023 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 77 (3):241-343.
    The idea of a canonical transformation emerged in 1837 in the course of Carl Jacobi's researches in analytical dynamics. To understand Jacobi's moment of discovery it is necessary to examine some background, especially the work of Joseph Lagrange and Siméon Poisson on the variation of arbitrary constants as well as some of the dynamical discoveries of William Rowan Hamilton. Significant figures following Jacobi in the middle of the century were Adolphe Desboves and William Donkin, while the delayed posthumous publication in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Praise of Clausius Entropy: Reassessing the Foundations of Boltzmannian Statistical Mechanics.Christopher Gregory Weaver - 2021 - Foundations of Physics 51 (3):1-64.
    I will argue, pace a great many of my contemporaries, that there's something right about Boltzmann's attempt to ground the second law of thermodynamics in a suitably amended deterministic time-reversal invariant classical dynamics, and that in order to appreciate what's right about (what was at least at one time) Boltzmann's explanatory project, one has to fully apprehend the nature of microphysical causal structure, time-reversal invariance, and the relationship between Boltzmann entropy and the work of Rudolf Clausius.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Decline, Then Recovery: An Overview of Activity in the History of Mathematics during the Twentieth Century.I. Grattan-Guinness - 2004 - History of Science 42 (3):279-312.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Interactions between mechanics and differential geometry in the 19th century.Jesper Lützen - 1995 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 49 (1):1-72.
    79. This study of the interaction between mechanics and differential geometry does not pretend to be exhaustive. In particular, there is probably more to be said about the mathematical side of the history from Darboux to Ricci and Levi Civita and beyond. Statistical mechanics may also be of interest and there is definitely more to be said about Hertz (I plan to continue in this direction) and about Poincaré's geometric and topological reasonings for example about the three body problem [Poincaré (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Geometry, mechanics, and experience: a historico-philosophical musing.Olivier Darrigol - 2022 - European Journal for Philosophy of Science 12 (4):1-36.
    Euclidean geometry, statics, and classical mechanics, being in some sense the simplest physical theories based on a full-fledged mathematical apparatus, are well suited to a historico-philosophical analysis of the way in which a physical theory differs from a purely mathematical theory. Through a series of examples including Newton’s Principia and later forms of mechanics, we will identify the interpretive substructure that connects the mathematical apparatus of the theory to the world of experience. This substructure includes models of experiments, models of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Corpore cadente... : Historians Discuss Newton’s Second Law.Stuart Pierson - 1993 - Perspectives on Science 1 (4):627-658.
    For about the last thirty years Newton scholars have carried on a discussion on the meaning of Newton’s second law and its place in the stucture of his physics. E. J. Dijksterhuis, Brian D. Ellis, R. G. A. Dolby, I. Bernard Cohen, and R. S. Westfall in their treatments of these matters all quote a passage that Newton added to the third edition of the Principia. This passage, beginning “Corpore cadente” (“when a body is falling”), was inserted into the Scholium (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Richard whately and the rise of modern logic.James Van Evra - 1984 - History and Philosophy of Logic 5 (1):1-18.
    Despite its basically syllogistic character, Richard Whately's Elements of logic presents the subject in a modern theoretical setting. Whately, for instance, regarded logic as an abstract science, and defined the syllogism as a purely formal device to be used as a means of determining the validity of all arguments. In this paper, I argue that such instances of abstractive ascent place Whately's theory in closer proximity to later 19th-century developments than to the work of his 17th-century predecessors. In addition to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • ‘The emergency which has arrived’: the problematic history of nineteenth-century British algebra – a programmatic outline.Menachem Fisch - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Science 27 (3):247-276.
    More than any other aspect of the Second Scientific Revolution, the remarkable revitalization or British mathematics and mathematical physics during the first half of the nineteenth century is perhaps the most deserving of the name. While the newly constituted sciences of biology and geology were undergoing their first revolution, as it were, the reform of British mathematics was truly and self-consciously the story of a second coming of age. ‘Discovered by Fermat, cocinnated and rendered analytical by Newton, and enriched by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Work and Waste: Political Economy and Natural Philosophy in Nineteenth Century Britain (II).M. Norton Wise & Crosbie Smith - 1989 - History of Science 27 (4):391-449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The debate on the “polarity of light” during the optical revolution.Xiang Chen - 1997 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 50 (3-4):359-393.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Jacobi and the birth of Lie's theory of groups.Thomas Hawkins - 1991 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 42 (3):187-278.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Newton and Hamilton: In defense of truth in algebra.Janet Folina - 2012 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 50 (3):504-527.
    Although it is clear that Sir William Rowan Hamilton supported a Kantian account of algebra, I argue that there is an important sense in which Hamilton's philosophy of mathematics can be situated in the Newtonian tradition. Drawing from both Niccolo Guicciardini's (2009) and Stephen Gaukroger's (2010) readings of the Newton–Leibniz controversy over the calculus, I aim to show that the very epistemic ideals that underpin Newton's argument for the superiority of geometry over algebra also motivate Hamilton's philosophy of algebra. Namely, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Joseph H. M. Wedderburn and the structure theory of algebras.Karen Hunger Parshall - 1985 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 32 (3):223-349.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How and Why I Write History of Science.Menachem Fisch - 2013 - Science in Context 26 (4):573-585.
    I have always been a philosopher at heart. I write history of science and history of its philosophy primarily as a philosopher wary of his abstractions and broad conceptualizations. But that has not always been the case. Lakatos famously portrayed history of science as the testing ground for theories of scientific rationality. But he did so along the crudest Hegelian lines that did injury both to Hegel and to the history and methodology of science. Since science is ultimately rational, he (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Practical reason and mathematical argument.John O'Neill - 1998 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (2):195-205.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Early History of Hamilton-Jacobi Dynamics 1834?1837.Michiyo Nakane & Craig G. Fraser - 2002 - Centaurus 44 (3-4):161-227.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On Defining the Hamiltonian Beyond Quantum Theory.Dominic Branford, Oscar C. O. Dahlsten & Andrew J. P. Garner - 2018 - Foundations of Physics 48 (8):982-1006.
    Energy is a crucial concept within classical and quantum physics. An essential tool to quantify energy is the Hamiltonian. Here, we consider how to define a Hamiltonian in general probabilistic theories—a framework in which quantum theory is a special case. We list desiderata which the definition should meet. For 3-dimensional systems, we provide a fully-defined recipe which satisfies these desiderata. We discuss the higher dimensional case where some freedom of choice is left remaining. We apply the definition to example toy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The physical interpretation of the wave theory of light.Frank A. J. L. James - 1984 - British Journal for the History of Science 17 (1):47-60.
    There existed essentially two theories of light during the early nineteenth century: the particulate theory and the wave theory. This we realise today is a gross over-simplification, since there were many varieties of each theory. But to the supporters of one theory the other theory had faults so fundamental that no distinction between varieties of the same theory was sufficient to placate opposition to that theory. This meant that opponents of either the wave or the particulate theory seldom, in their (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intertextual Reference in Nineteenth-Century Mathematics.John O'Neill - 1993 - Science in Context 6 (2):435-468.
    The ArgumentA scientific work presupposes a body of texts that are a condition for its intelligibility. This paper shows that the study of intertextual reference — of the ways a text indicates its relation to other texts — provides a fruitful perspective in the study of science that deserves more attention than it has hitherto received. The paper examines intertextual reference in early nineteenth-century mathematics, first surveying a variety of mathematical texts in the period and then examining in detail W.R. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Révolution industrielle logique et signification de l'opératoire.Marie-José Durand-Richard - 2001 - Revue de Synthèse 122 (2-4):319-346.
    Dans la première moitié du xixe siècle en Angleterre, autour de Charles babbage (1791–1871), John F. W. Herschel (1792–1871), George Peacock (1791–1858), Duncan F. Gregory (1813–1844), Augustus de Morgan (1806–1871), George Boole (1815–1864), et d'autres auteurs moins connus, un réseau d'algébristes renouvelle singulièrement la conception de l'algèbre, à tel point que leur travail est le plus souvent interprété comme émergence des travaux sur l'algèbre abstraite. Comme ces algébristes sont également des réformateurs impliqués dans la réorganisation de la science, il s'agira (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation