Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. On the presumption of equality.Juha Räikkä - 2019 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 22 (7):809-822.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Can the empirical sciences contribute to the moral realism/anti-realism debate?Thomas Pölzler - 2018 - Synthese 195 (11):4907-4930.
    An increasing number of moral realists and anti-realists have recently attempted to support their views by appeal to science. Arguments of this kind are typically criticized on the object-level. In addition, however, one occasionally also comes across a more sweeping metatheoretical skepticism. Scientific contributions to the question of the existence of objective moral truths, it is claimed, are impossible in principle; most prominently, because such arguments impermissibly derive normative from descriptive propositions, such arguments beg the question against non-naturalist moral realism, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • An Introduction to Metaethics.Jeremiah Joven Joaquin - 2013 - In Exploring the Philosophical Terrain. C&E.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defence of speciesism.J. A. Gray - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):22-23.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Consumer demand theory and social behavior: All chickens are not equal.Joy A. Mench & W. Ray Stricklin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):28-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ethics and animals.Peter Singer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-48.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Towards an adequate ethical theory.Aleksandar T. Dobrijević - 2003 - Filozofija I Društvo 2003 (22):65-114.
    Autor preispituje Herovu tvrdnju o univerzalnom preskriptivizmu kao najadekvatnijoj etickoj teoriji u uzem smislu. Validnost tog stanovista odmerava se u odnosu na neke konkurentne koncepcije, i to preko uslova koji moraju da se ispune kako bi jedna eticka teorija mogla da se nazove adekvatnom.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Helping doctors become better doctors: Mary Lobjoit—an unsung heroine of medical ethics in the UK.Margaret R. Brazier, Raanan Gillon & John Harris - 2012 - Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (6):383-385.
    Medical Ethics has many unsung heros and heroines. Here we celebrate one of these and on telling part of her story hope to place modern medical ethics and bioethics in the UK more centrally within its historical and human contex.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Factualism, Normativism and the Bounds of Normativity.Thomas M. Besch - 2011 - Dialogue 50 (2):347-365.
    The paper argues that applications of the principle that “ought” implies “can” (OIC) depend on normative considerations even if the link between “ought” and “can” is logical in nature. Thus, we should reject a common, “factualist” conception of OIC and endorse weak “normativism”. Even if we use OIC as the rule ““cannot” therefore “not ought””, applying OIC is not a mere matter of facts and logic, as factualists claim, but often draws on “proto-ideals” of moral agency.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Disentangling the thick concept argument.Olle Blomberg - 2007 - SATS: Northern European Journal of Philosophy 8 (2):63-78.
    Critics argue that non-cognitivism cannot adequately account for the existence and nature of some thick moral concepts. They use the existence of thick concepts as a lever in an argument against non-cognitivism, here called the Thick Concept Argument (TCA). While TCA is frequently invoked, it is unfortunately rarely articulated. In this paper, TCA is first reconstructed on the basis of John McDowell’s formulation of the argument (from 1981), and then evaluated in the light of several possible non-cognitivist responses. In general, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Philosophy and Cognitive Sciences: Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein Symposium (Kirchberg Am Wechsel, Austria 1993).Roberto Casati & Barry Smith (eds.) - 1994 - Vienna: Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.
    Online collection of papers by Devitt, Dretske, Guarino, Hochberg, Jackson, Petitot, Searle, Tye, Varzi and other leading thinkers on philosophy and the foundations of cognitive Science. Topics dealt with include: Wittgenstein and Cognitive Science, Content and Object, Logic and Foundations, Language and Linguistics, and Ontology and Mereology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • From an animal's point of view: Motivation, fitness, and animal welfare.Marian Stamp Dawkins - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):1-9.
    To study animal welfare empirically we need an objective basis for deciding when an animal is suffering. Suffering includes a wide range ofunpleasant emotional states such as fear, boredom, pain, and hunger. Suffering has evolved as a mechanism for avoiding sources ofdanger and threats to fitness. Captive animals often suffer in situations in which they are prevented from doing something that they are highly motivated to do. The an animal is prepared to pay to attain or to escape a situation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   79 citations  
  • The Expansion View of Thick Concepts.Brent G. Kyle - 2019 - Noûs 54 (4):914-944.
    This paper proposes a new Separabilist account of thick concepts, called the Expansion View (or EV). According to EV, thick concepts are expanded contents of thin terms. An expanded content is, roughly, the semantic content of a predicate along with modifiers. Although EV is a form of Separabilism, it is distinct from the only kind of Separabilism discussed in the literature, and it has many features that Inseparabilists want from an account of thick concepts. EV can also give non-cognitivists a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Happiness and Human Flourishing in Kant's Ethics: THOMAS E. HILL, JR.Thomas E. Hill - 1999 - Social Philosophy and Policy 16 (1):143-175.
    Ancient moral philosophers, especially Aristotle and his followers, typically shared the assumption that ethics is primarily concerned with how to achieve the final end for human beings, a life of “happiness” or “human flourishing.” This final end was not a subjective condition, such as contentment or the satisfaction of our preferences, but a life that could be objectively determined to be appropriate to our nature as human beings. Character traits were treated as moral virtues because they contributed well toward this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From one subjectivity to another.S. J. Shettleworth & N. Mrosovsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):37-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there a Human Right to Medical Insurance?Walter E. Block - 2008 - Business and Professional Ethics Journal 27 (1-4):1-33.
    This paper claims that health insurance is not a human right; that the reason the medical care industry is in such an unsatisfactorystate is that there is not enough competition in the field. To wit, there are government interferences on both the supply and demand sides of health care; the former in terms of restrictions on entry for physicians, the latter based on the moral hazard attendant on the subsidization of medicine.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Intention et faiblesse de la volonté.Renée Bilodeau - 2002 - Dialogue 41 (1):27-44.
    Akrasia is both an intentional and an irrational phenomenon. These two characteristics can be reconciled by a careful reconstruction of practical reasoning. I undertake this task along Davidsonian lines, arguing against his critics that the notion of unconditional judgment is the key to an adequate account of akrasia. Unless akrasia is conceived as a failure of the agent to form an unconditional judgment that conforms to her best judgment "all things considered," the intentionality of akrasia is lost. Likewise, I show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Practice, Sensibility and Moral Education.David Bakhurst - 2018 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 52 (4):677-694.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Mill's Metaethical Non-cognitivism.Peter Zuk - 2018 - Utilitas 30 (3):271-293.
    In section I, I lay out key components of my favoured non-cognitivist interpretation of Mill's metaethics. In section II, I respond to several objections to this style of interpretation posed by Christopher Macleod. In section III, I respond to David Brink's treatment of the well-known ‘competent judges’ passage in Mill'sUtilitarianism. I argue that important difficulties face both Brink'sevidential interpretationand the rivalconstitutive interpretationthat he proposes but rejects. I opt for a third interpretative option that I call thepsychological interpretation. This interpretation makes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Uncertainty and Probability within Utilitarian Theory.Jonathan Baron - 2017 - Diametros 53:6-25.
    Probability is a central concept in utilitarian moral theory, almost impossible to do without. I attempt to clarify the role of probability, so that we can be clear about what we are aiming for when we apply utilitarian theory to real cases. I point out the close relationship between utilitarianism and expected-utility theory, a normative standard for individual decision-making. I then argue that the distinction between “ambiguity” and risk is a matter of perception. We do not need this distinction in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Imperatives and Meaning.C. K. Grant - 1968 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 1:181-195.
    In recent years philosophers have given a good deal of attention to imperatives. They have concerned themselves mainly with the logical grammar of sentences of this kind, that is to say their relations to each other and to interrogative and indicative sentences. Very often this topic has been raised in terms of the problem ‘Is imperative inference possible, and if so, what kind of inference is it?’. Many philosophers have contended that there are logically valid inferences that involve imperative sentences. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Animal well-being: There are many paths to enlightenment.Evalyn F. Segal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):36-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On Singer: More argument, less prescriptivism.David DeGrazia - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):18-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The concept of the moral domain in moral foundations theory and cognitive developmental theory: Horses for courses?Bruce Maxwell & Guillaume Beaulac - 2013 - Journal of Moral Education 42 (3):360-382.
    Moral foundations theory chastises cognitive developmental theory for having foisted on moral psychology a restrictive conception of the moral domain which involves arbitrarily elevating the values of justice and caring. The account of this negative influence on moral psychology, referred to in the moral foundations theory literature as the ?great narrowing?, involves several interrelated claims concerning the scope of the moral domain construct in cognitive moral developmentalism, the procedure by which it was initially elaborated, its empirical grounds and the influence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Weakness of Will as a Species of Executive Cowardice.Christine Swanton - 1991 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21 (2):123 - 140.
    In this paper, I am concerned to show that a wide and interesting range of phenomena commonly described as ‘weakness of will’ should be understood as manifesting a defect of what I shall call ‘executive cowardice’ rather than a strong kind of irrationality. More specifically, I claim that such cases should not be understood as an irrational bypassing of an all-things-considered judgment about the thing to do—a view succinctly described by Peacocke thus: The akrates is irrational because although he intentionally (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • IV—Empathy and First-Personal Imagining.Rae Langton - 2019 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 119 (1):77-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • El alcance del escepticismo moral.Martín Farrell - 2013 - Análisis Filosófico 33 (1):47-66.
    El escepticismo moral sostiene que las proposiciones morales no son verdaderas ni falsas de acuerdo al criterio de verdad por correspondencia, y que el criterio de verdad por coherencia no es aplicable en moral. Para refutarlo, habría que mostrar la existencia de hechos morales, o demostrar que la coherencia es suficiente para una buena teoría moral. El artículo sostiene que esto no puede hacerse. Moral skepticism maintains that moral propositions are no true, nor false, according with the correspondence theory of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Interpersonal comparisons of utility: Why and how they are and should be made.Peter J. Hammond - 1991 - In Jon Elster & John E. Roemer (eds.), Interpersonal comparisons of well-being. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 200--254.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • To suffer, or not to suffer? That is the question.Andrew N. Rowan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Emotion, empathy, and suffering.Eric A. Salzen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Perceived cost” may reveal frustration, but not boredom.Françoise Wemelsfelder - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):44-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consumer demand theory and animal welfare: Value and limitations.Tina Widowski - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):45-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)The Origins of Morality: An Essay in Philosophical Anthropology.Andrew Oldenquist - 1990 - Social Philosophy and Policy 8 (1):121.
    By what steps, historically, did morality emerge? Our remote ancestors evolved into social animals. Sociality requires, among other things, restraints on disruptive sexual, hostile, aggressive, vengeful, and acquisitive behavior. Since we are innately social and not social by convention, we can assume the biological evolution of the emotional equipment – numerous predispositions to want, fear, feel anxious or secure – required for social living, just as we can assume cultural evolution of various means to control antisocial behavior and reinforce the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Naturalism and psychological explanation.Paul K. Moser - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (1):63-84.
    This article explores the possibility of naturalized theory of action. It distinguishes ontological naturalism from conceptual naturalism, and asks whether a defensible theory of action can be either ontologically or conceptually naturalistic. The distinction between conditions for an ontology and conditions for a concept receives support from Donald Davidson's identification of two modes of explanation for action: rational and physical causal explanation. Davidson's action theory provides a naturalized ontology for action theory, but not a naturalized concept of intentional action. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Practical reasoning and practical knowledge.Rowland Stout - 2019 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49 (4):564-579.
    The judgement that provides the content of intention and coincides with the conclusion of practical reasoning is a normative judgement about what to do, and not, as Anscombe and McDowell argue, a factual judgement about what one is doing. Treating the conclusion of practical reasoning as expressing a recommendation rather than a verdict undermines McDowell’s argument; the special nature of practical reasoning does not preclude its conclusions being normative. Anscombe’s and McDowell’s claim that practical self-knowledge is productive of action may (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Seeking the sources of simian suffering.Melinda A. Novak & Jerrold S. Meyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Science and value.Bernard E. Rollin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):32-33.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradoxical experimental outcomes and animal suffering.Jaylan Sheila Turkkan - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):42-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Impossible Obligations are not Necessarily Deliberatively Pointless.Christopher Jay - 2013 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 113 (3pt3):381-389.
    Many philosophers accept that ought implies can (OIC), but it is not obvious that we have a good argument for that principle. I consider one sort of argument for it, which seems to be a development of an Aristotelian idea about practical deliberation and which is endorsed by, amongst others, R. M. Hare and James Griffin. After briefly rehearsing some well-known objections to that sort of argument (which is based on the supposed pointlessness of impossible obligations), I present a further (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The significance of seeking the animal's perspective.Arnold Arluke - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):13-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Having the imagination to suffer, and to prevent suffering.Richard W. Byrne - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):15-16.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Obtaining and applying objective criteria in animal welfare.Anne E. Magurran - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Who suffers?P. D. Wall - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):43-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (2 other versions)Blackburn's Problem: On Its Not Insignificant Residue.Jordan Howard Sobel - 2001 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (2):361-383.
    Moral properties would supervene upon non‐moral properties and be conceptually autonomous. That, according to Simon Blackburn, would make them if not impossible at least mysterious, and evidence for them best explained by theorists who say they are not real. In fact moral properties would not challenge in ways Blackburn has contended. There is, however, something new that can be gathered from his arguments. What would the supervenience of moral properties and their conceptual autonomy from at least total non‐moral properties entail (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The meaning of speciesism and the forms of animal suffering.S. F. Sapontzis - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):35-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The importance of measures of poor welfare.D. M. Broom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):14-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Desire's Desire for Moral Realism: A Phenomenological Objection to Non-Cognitivism.James Lindemann Nelson - 1989 - Dialogue 28 (3):449-.
    Roughly thirty years ago, R. M. Hare told an Anglo-French philosophy conference about a young Swiss student who came to stay with his family in Oxford. It seems that the student was doing very nicely, until, in a burst of misguided hospitality, the Hares provided him with one of their few French books, Camus's L'Etranger. Reading Camus had the effect of changing the student from an affable, altogether attractive young man into a chain-smoking recluse for whom “rien, rien n'avait d'importance”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Moral Deadlock.Ronald D. Milo - 1986 - Philosophy 61 (238):453 - 471.
    Very often moral disagreements can be resolved by appealing to factual considerations because in these cases the parties to the dispute agree as to which factual considerations are relevant. They agree, that is, with respect to their basic moral standards. Hence, when their disagreement about the non-moral facts is resolved, so is their moral disagreement. But sometimes moral disagreement persists in spite of agreement on factual considerations. When this happens, and when neither party is guilty of illogical thinking, we have (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Needs and Capabilities.Sabina Alkire - 2005 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 57:229-252.
    How should actions to redress absolute human deprivation be framed? Current international coordinated actions on absolute poverty are framed by human rights or by goals such as the Millennium Development Goals. But appropriate, effective and sustained responses to needs require localized participation in the definition of those rights/goals/needs and in measures taken to redress them. Human rights or the MDGs do not seem necessarily to require such processes. For this reason some argue that no universal framework can describe economic, social, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On the neurobiological basis of suffering.C. Richard Chapman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):16-17.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation