Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Epistemic action, extended knowledge, and metacognition.Joëlle Proust - 2014 - Philosophical Issues 24 (1):364-392.
    How should one attribute epistemic credit to an agent, and hence, knowledge, when cognitive processes include an extensive use of human or mechanical enhancers, informational tools, and devices which allow one to complement or modify one's own cognitive system? The concept of integration of a cognitive system has been used to address this question. For true belief to be creditable to a person's ability, it is claimed, the relevant informational processes must be or become part of the cognitive character of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Neuronal models of cognitive functions.Jean-Pierre Changeux & Stanislas Dehaene - 1989 - Cognition 33 (1-2):63-109.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   49 citations  
  • The significance of the basal ganglia for schizophrenia.Reuven Sandyk & Stanley R. Kay - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):45-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is schizophrenia?Janice R. Stevens & James M. Gold - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):50-51.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • The neuropsychology of schizophrenia: In step but not in time.Jonathan H. Williams - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):55-56.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contiguity, contingency, adaptiveness, and controls.Glenda MacQueen, James MacRae & Shepard Siegel - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):154-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Extending the “new hegemony” of classical conditioning.Dan Lloyd - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):152-153.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning and functional utility.Barry R. Dworkin - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):139-141.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A neuron doctrine in the philosophy of neuroscience.Ian Gold & Daniel Stoljar - 1999 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5):809-830.
    It is widely held that a successful theory of the mind will be neuroscientific. In this paper we ask, first, what this claim means, and, secondly, whether it is true. In answer to the first question, we argue that the claim is ambiguous between two views--one plausible but unsubstantive, and one substantive but highly controversial. In answer to the second question, we argue that neither the evidence from neuroscience itself nor from other scientific and philosophical considerations supports the controversial view.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Sidestepping the semantics of “consciousness”.Michael V. Antony - 2004 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (2):289-290.
    Block explains the conflation of phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness by appeal to the ambiguity of the term “consciousness.” However, the nature of ambiguity is not at all clear, and the thesis that “consciousness” is ambiguous between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness is far from obvious. Moreover, the conflation can be explained without supposing that the term is ambiguous. Block's argument can thus be strengthened by avoiding controversial issues in the semantics of “consciousness.”.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Quine’s Eliminativism and the Crystal Spheres.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (2):315 - 327.
    Quine’s eliminativist theory has largely been ignored by the philosophical community. This is highly regrettable because Quine’s theory is probably close to correct. Now, the probable correctness of Quine’s theory has an important consequence since, according to the theory, there are no mental entities (events, states, phenomena, properties, etc.) nor do such entities play any role in a scientific account of the relevant phenomena. But the hundreds or probably thousands of publications that deal with issues such as mental causation, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reduction, elimination, and levels: The case of the LTP-learning link.Maurice K. D. Schouten & Huib Looren De Jong - 1999 - Philosophical Psychology 12 (3):237 – 262.
    We argue in this paper that so-called new wave reductionism fails to capture the nature of the interlevel relations between psychology and neuroscience. Bickle (1995, Psychoneural reduction of the genuinely cognitive: some accomplished facts, Philosophical Psychology, 8, 265-285; 1998, Psychoneural reduction: the new wave, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press) has claimed that a (bottom-up) reduction of the psychological concepts of learning and memory to the concepts of neuroscience has in fact already been accomplished. An investigation of current research on the phenomenon (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Reductionist and anti-reductionist perspectives on dynamics.Catholijn M. Jonker, Jan Treur & Wouter C. A. Wijngaards - 2002 - Philosophical Psychology 15 (4):381 – 409.
    In this paper, reduction and its pragmatics are discussed in light of the development in computer science of languages to describe processes. The design of higher-level description languages within computer science has had the aim of allowing for description of the dynamics of processes in the (physical) world on a higher level avoiding all (physical) details of these processes. The higher description levels developed have dramatically increased the complexity of applications that came within reach. The pragmatic attitude of a (scientific) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • When is a brain like the planet?Clark Glymour - 2007 - Philosophy of Science 74 (3):330-347.
    Time series of macroscopic quantities that are aggregates of microscopic quantities, with unknown one‐many relations between macroscopic and microscopic states, are common in applied sciences, from economics to climate studies. When such time series of macroscopic quantities are claimed to be causal, the causal relations postulated are representable by a directed acyclic graph and associated probability distribution—sometimes called a dynamical Bayes net. Causal interpretations of such series imply claims that hypothetical manipulations of macroscopic variables have unambiguous effects on variables “downstream” (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The mind-body problem and Quine's repudiation theory.Nathan Stemmer - 2001 - Behavior and Philosophy 29:187-202.
    Most scholars who presently deal with the Mind-Body problem consider themselves monist materialists. Nevertheless, many of them also assume that there exist (in some sense of existence) mental entities. But since these two positions do not harmonize quite well, the literature is full of discussions about how to reconcile the positions. In this paper, I will defend a materialist theory that avoids all these problems by completely rejecting the existence of mental entities. This is Quine's repudiation theory. According to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Psychoneural reduction of the genuinely cognitive: Some accomplished facts.John Bickle - 1995 - Philosophical Psychology 8 (3):265-85.
    The need for representations and computations over their contents in psychological explanations is often cited as both the mark of the genuinely cognitive and a source of skepticism about the reducibility of cognitive theories to neuroscience. A generic version of this anti-reductionist argument is rejected in this paper as unsound, since (i) current thinking about associative learning emphasizes the need for cognitivist resources in theories adequate to explain even the simplest form of this phenomena (Pavlovian conditioning), and yet (ii) the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Mental representation from the bottom up.Dan Lloyd - 1987 - Synthese 70 (January):23-78.
    Commonsense psychology and cognitive science both regularly assume the existence of representational states. I propose a naturalistic theory of representation sufficient to meet the pretheoretical constraints of a "folk theory of representation", constraints including the capacities for accuracy and inaccuracy, selectivity of proper objects of representation, perspective, articulation, and "efficacy" or content-determined functionality. The proposed model states that a representing device is a device which changes state when information is received over multiple information channels originating at a single source. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Problems in the Development of Cognitive Neuroscience Effective Communication between Scientific Domains.Edward Manier - 1986 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1986 (1):183-197.
    Could anything provide a philosophically convincing mark of the mental in simple organisms (Lloyd 1984)? Individual organisms’ capacities to modify behavior adaptively as a result of past encounters with the environment might mark the first step in the phylogeny of minds. The simplest examples of mental representation are likely to be found in the simplest forms of animal learning.The most scientifically rigorous test case of “bottom- up” strategies in cognitive neuroscience is provided by current studies of the cellular and molecular (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psychoneural reduction: a perspective from neural circuits.David Parker - 2019 - Biology and Philosophy 34 (4):44.
    Psychoneural reduction has been debated extensively in the philosophy of neuroscience. In this article I will evaluate metascientific approaches that claim direct molecular and cellular explanations of cognitive functions. I will initially consider the issues involved in linking cellular properties to behaviour from the general perspective of neural circuits. These circuits that integrate the molecular and cellular components underlying cognition and behaviour, making consideration of circuit properties relevant to reductionist debates. I will then apply this general perspective to specific systems (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism in Pavlovian Harness.George Graham - 1988 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 26 (S1):73-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Deep and beautiful. The reward prediction error hypothesis of dopamine.Matteo Colombo - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 45 (1):57-67.
    According to the reward-prediction error hypothesis of dopamine, the phasic activity of dopaminergic neurons in the midbrain signals a discrepancy between the predicted and currently experienced reward of a particular event. It can be claimed that this hypothesis is deep, elegant and beautiful, representing one of the largest successes of computational neuroscience. This paper examines this claim, making two contributions to existing literature. First, it draws a comprehensive historical account of the main steps that led to the formulation and subsequent (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Quine’s Eliminativism and the Crystal Spheres.Nathan Stemmer - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (2):315-327.
    Quine’s eliminativist theory has largely been ignored by the philosophical community. This is highly regrettable because Quine’s theory is probably close to correct. Now, the probable correctness of Quine’s theory has an important consequence since, according to the theory, there are no mental entities (events, states, phenomena, properties, etc.) nor do such entities play any role in a scientific account of the relevant phenomena. But the hundreds or probably thousands of publications that deal with issues such as mental causation, the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Behavioural Explanation in the Realm of Non-mental Computing Agents.Bernardo Aguilera - 2015 - Minds and Machines 25 (1):37-56.
    Recently, many philosophers have been inclined to ascribe mentality to animals on the main grounds that they possess certain complex computational abilities. In this paper I contend that this view is misleading, since it wrongly assumes that those computational abilities demand a psychological explanation. On the contrary, they can be just characterised from a computational level of explanation, which picks up a domain of computation and information processing that is common to many computing systems but is autonomous from the domain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neural networks and psychopharmacology.Sbg Park - 1998 - In Dan J. Stein & Jacques Ludik (eds.), Neural Networks and Psychopathology: Connectionist Models in Practice and Research. Cambridge University Press. pp. 57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Impossible project of Ivan Pavlov.David Joravsky - 1992 - Science in Context 5 (2):265-280.
    The ArgumentIn different contexts, beginning with different concerns, Pavlov, James, and Freud tried to achieve a neurophysiological explanation of mind, and suffered defeat. James and Freud acknowledged the defeat and attempted, in radically different ways, to construct an interim psychology, hoping that neural explanation would be achieved in the future. Pavlov came to the effort in his fifties, after decades of research that took for granted a sharp separation between neurophysiology and psychology. He changed his mind as he noticed the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism in Pavlovian harness.George Graham - 1991 - In Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson (eds.), Connectionism and the Philosophy of Mind. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 143--166.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What should a theory of schizophrenia be able to do?Kurt Salzinger - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):44-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Dopamine-GABA-cholinergic interactions and negative schizophrenic symptomatology.Martin Sarter - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):46-47.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A hippocampal theory of schizophrenia.Nestor A. Schmajuk & James J. DiCarlo - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):47-49.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A plausible theory marred by certain inconsistencies.Herbert E. Spohn - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):49-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuropsychology of schizophrenia: The “hole” thing is wrong.Neal R. Swerdlow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):51-53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A focalized deficit within an elegant system.Irene J. Elkins & Rue L. Cromwell - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In what context is latent inhibition relevant to the symptoms of schizophrenia?Chris Frith - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):28-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Novelty value in associative learning.Jonathan C. Gewirtz - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):29-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Schizophrenia and stored memories: Left hemisphere dysfunction after all?Elkhonon Goldberg - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):30-30.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The role of long-term memory and monitoring in schizophrenia: Multiple functions.Martin Harrow & Marshall Silverstein - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):30-31.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A cardinal principle for neuropsychology, with implications for schizophrenia and mania.David Hestenes - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):31-32.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The mechanism of positive symptoms in schizophrenia.Ralph E. Hoffman - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):33-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A neuropsychology of psychosis.Loring J. Ingraham - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):34-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Excitatory amino acids, NMDA and sigma receptors: A role in schizophrenia?Karl L. R. Jansen & Richard L. M. Faull - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):34-35.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Schizophrenia and attention: In and out of context.R. E. Lubow - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):35-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Approximations to a neuropsychological model of schizophrenia.Theo C. Manschreck & Brendan A. Maher - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):36-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuropsychological vulnerability or episode factors in schizophrenia?Keith H. Nuechterlein & Michael Foster Green - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):37-38.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Bases for irrelevant information processing in schizophrenia: Room for manoeuvre.R. D. Oades - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):38-39.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is another loop needed to explain schizophrenia?Arvin F. Oke & Ralph N. Adams - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):39-40.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A realistic model will be much more complex and will consider longitudinal neuropsychodevelopment.Terry Patterson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):40-41.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Why don't preschizophrenic children have delusions and hallucinations?Lyn Pilowsky & Robin M. Murray - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):41-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A heuristically useful but empirically weak neuropsychological model of schizophrenia.M. Pisa & J. M. Cleghorn - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):42-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Neuro-developmental, brain imaging and psychophysiological perspectives on the neuropsychology of schizophrenia.Adrian Raine & Tyrone D. Cannon - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):43-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A faulty negative feedback control underlies the schizophrenic syndrome?Arvid Carlsson & Maria Carlsson - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (1):20-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark