Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Procedural Semantics for Hyperintensional Logic: Foundations and Applications of Transparent Intensional Logic.Marie Duží, Bjorn Jespersen & Pavel Materna - 2010 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    The book is about logical analysis of natural language. Since we humans communicate by means of natural language, we need a tool that helps us to understand in a precise manner how the logical and formal mechanisms of natural language work. Moreover, in the age of computers, we need to communicate both with and through computers as well. Transparent Intensional Logic is a tool that is helpful in making our communication and reasoning smooth and precise. It deals with all kinds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Ellipsis and higher-order unification.Mary Dalrymple, Stuart M. Shieber & Fernando C. N. Pereira - 1991 - Linguistics and Philosophy 14 (4):399 - 452.
    We present a new method for characterizing the interpretive possibilities generated by elliptical constructions in natural language. Unlike previous analyses, which postulate ambiguity of interpretation or derivation in the full clause source of the ellipsis, our analysis requires no such hidden ambiguity. Further, the analysis follows relatively directly from an abstract statement of the ellipsis interpretation problem. It predicts correctly a wide range of interactions between ellipsis and other semantic phenomena such as quantifier scope and bound anaphora. Finally, although the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Demonstratives as individual concepts.Paul Elbourne - 2008 - Linguistics and Philosophy 31 (4):409-466.
    Using a version of situation semantics, this article argues that bare and complex demonstratives are interpreted as individual concepts.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • The Computational Origin of Representation.Steven T. Piantadosi - 2020 - Minds and Machines 31 (1):1-58.
    Each of our theories of mental representation provides some insight into how the mind works. However, these insights often seem incompatible, as the debates between symbolic, dynamical, emergentist, sub-symbolic, and grounded approaches to cognition attest. Mental representations—whatever they are—must share many features with each of our theories of representation, and yet there are few hypotheses about how a synthesis could be possible. Here, I develop a theory of the underpinnings of symbolic cognition that shows how sub-symbolic dynamics may give rise (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • (1 other version)Godel's functional interpretation.Jeremy Avigad & Solomon Feferman - 1998 - In Samuel R. Buss (ed.), Handbook of proof theory. New York: Elsevier. pp. 337-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Explaining crossover and superiority as left-to-right evaluation.Chung-Chieh Shan & Chris Barker - 2005 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (1):91 - 134.
    We present a general theory of scope and binding in which both crossover and superiority violations are ruled out by one key assumption: that natural language expressions are normally evaluated (processed) from left to right. Our theory is an extension of Shan’s (2002) account of multiple-wh questions, combining continuations (Barker, 2002) and dynamic type-shifting. Like other continuation-based analyses, but unlike most other treatments of crossover or superiority, our analysis is directly compositional (in the sense of, e.g., Jacobson, 1999). In particular, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Understanding programming languages.Raymond Turner - 2007 - Minds and Machines 17 (2):203-216.
    We document the influence on programming language semantics of the Platonism/formalism divide in the philosophy of mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Principal type-schemes and condensed detachment.J. Roger Hindley & David Meredith - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):90-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The placeholder view of assumptions and the Curry–Howard correspondence.Ivo Pezlar - 2020 - Synthese (11):1-17.
    Proofs from assumptions are amongst the most fundamental reasoning techniques. Yet the precise nature of assumptions is still an open topic. One of the most prominent conceptions is the placeholder view of assumptions generally associated with natural deduction for intuitionistic propositional logic. It views assumptions essentially as holes in proofs, either to be filled with closed proofs of the corresponding propositions via substitution or withdrawn as a side effect of some rule, thus in effect making them an auxiliary notion subservient (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The senses of functions in the logic of sense and denotation.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 16 (2):153-188.
    This paper discusses certain problems arising within the treatment of the senses of functions in Alonzo Church's Logic of Sense and Denotation. Church understands such senses themselves to be "sense-functions," functions from sense to sense. However, the conditions he lays out under which a sense-function is to be regarded as a sense presenting another function as denotation allow for certain undesirable results given certain unusual or "deviant" sense-functions. Certain absurdities result, e.g., an argument can be found for equating any two (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Discontinuity in categorial grammar.Glyn Morrill - 1995 - Linguistics and Philosophy 18 (2):175 - 219.
    Discontinuity refers to the character of many natural language constructions wherein signs differ markedly in their prosodic and semantic forms. As such it presents interesting demands on monostratal computational formalisms which aspire to descriptive adequacy. Pied piping, in particular, is argued by Pollard (1988) to motivate phrase structure-style feature percolation. In the context of categorial grammar, Bach (1981, 1984), Moortgat (1988, 1990, 1991) and others have sought to provide categorial operators suited to discontinuity. These attempts encounter certain difficulties with respect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Semantics for dual and symmetric combinatory calculi.Katalin Bimbó - 2004 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (2):125-153.
    We define dual and symmetric combinatory calculi (inequational and equational ones), and prove their consistency. Then, we introduce algebraic and set theoretical relational and operational - semantics, and prove soundness and completeness. We analyze the relationship between these logics, and argue that inequational dual logics are the best suited to model computation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Systems of illative combinatory logic complete for first-order propositional and predicate calculus.Henk Barendregt, Martin Bunder & Wil Dekkers - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (3):769-788.
    Illative combinatory logic consists of the theory of combinators or lambda calculus extended by extra constants (and corresponding axioms and rules) intended to capture inference. The paper considers systems of illative combinatory logic that are sound for first-order propositional and predicate calculus. The interpretation from ordinary logic into the illative systems can be done in two ways: following the propositions-as-types paradigm, in which derivations become combinators or, in a more direct way, in which derivations are not translated. Both translations are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Wittgenstein and Brouwer.Mathieu Marion - 2003 - Synthese 137 (1-2):103 - 127.
    In this paper, I present a summary of the philosophical relationship betweenWittgenstein and Brouwer, taking as my point of departure Brouwer's lecture onMarch 10, 1928 in Vienna. I argue that Wittgenstein having at that stage not doneserious philosophical work for years, if one is to understand the impact of thatlecture on him, it is better to compare its content with the remarks on logics andmathematics in the Tractactus. I thus show that Wittgenstein's position, in theTractactus, was already quite close to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The mathematical work of S. C. Kleene.J. R. Shoenfield & S. C. Kleene - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):8-43.
    §1. The origins of recursion theory. In dedicating a book to Steve Kleene, I referred to him as the person who made recursion theory into a theory. Recursion theory was begun by Kleene's teacher at Princeton, Alonzo Church, who first defined the class of recursive functions; first maintained that this class was the class of computable functions ; and first used this fact to solve negatively some classical problems on the existence of algorithms. However, it was Kleene who, in his (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Uniqueness of normal proofs of minimal formulas.Makoto Tatsuta - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (3):789-799.
    A minimal formula is a formula which is minimal in provable formulas with respect to the substitution relation. This paper shows the following: (1) A β-normal proof of a minimal formula of depth 2 is unique in NJ. (2) There exists a minimal formula of depth 3 whose βη-normal proof is not unique in NJ. (3) There exists a minimal formula of depth 3 whose βη-normal proof is not unique in NK.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Abstraction in Algorithmic Logic.Wayne Aitken & Jeffrey A. Barrett - 2008 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 37 (1):23-43.
    We develop a functional abstraction principle for the type-free algorithmic logic introduced in our earlier work. Our approach is based on the standard combinators but is supplemented by the novel use of evaluation trees. Then we show that the abstraction principle leads to a Curry fixed point, a statement C that asserts C ⇒ A where A is any given statement. When A is false, such a C yields a paradoxical situation. As discussed in our earlier work, this situation leaves (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)PM's Circumflex, Syntax and Philosophy of Types.Kevin C. Klement - 2011 - In Kenneth Blackwell, Nicholas Griffin & Bernard Linsky (eds.), Principia mathematica at 100. Hamilton, Ontario: Bertrand Russell Research Centre. pp. 218-246.
    Along with offering an historically-oriented interpretive reconstruction of the syntax of PM ( rst ed.), I argue for a certain understanding of its use of propositional function abstracts formed by placing a circum ex on a variable. I argue that this notation is used in PM only when de nitions are stated schematically in the metalanguage, and in argument-position when higher-type variables are involved. My aim throughout is to explain how the usage of function abstracts as “terms” (loosely speaking) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Extending the first-order theory of combinators with self-referential truth.Andrea Cantini - 1993 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 58 (2):477-513.
    The aim of this paper is to introduce a formal system STW of self-referential truth, which extends the classical first-order theory of pure combinators with a truth predicate and certain approximation axioms. STW naturally embodies the mechanisms of general predicate application/abstraction on a par with function application/abstraction; in addition, it allows non-trivial constructions, inspired by generalized recursion theory. As a consequence, STW provides a smooth inner model for Myhill's systems with levels of implication.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A combinatory account of internal structure.Barry Jay & Thomas Given-Wilson - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (3):807 - 826.
    Traditional combinatory logic uses combinators S and K to represent all Turing-computable functions on natural numbers, but there are Turing-computable functions on the combinators themselves that cannot be so represented, because they access internal structure in ways that S and K cannot. Much of this expressive power is captured by adding a factorisation combinator F. The resulting SF-calculus is structure complete, in that it supports all pattern-matching functions whose patterns are in normal form, including a function that decides structural equality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The church-Rosser property in dual combinatory logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (1):132-152.
    Dual combinators emerge from the aim of assigning formulas containing ← as types to combinators. This paper investigates formally some of the properties of combinatory systems that include both combinators and dual combinators. Although the addition of dual combinators to a combinatory system does not affect the unique decomposition of terms, it turns out that some terms might be redexes in two ways (with a combinator as its head, and with a dual combinator as its head). We prove a general (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pure type systems with more liberal rules.Martin Bunder & Wil Dekkers - 2001 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (4):1561-1580.
    Pure Type Systems, PTSs, introduced as a generalisation of the type systems of Barendregt's lambda-cube, provide a foundation for actual proof assistants, aiming at the mechanic verification of formal proofs. In this paper we consider simplifications of some of the rules of PTSs. This is of independent interest for PTSs as this produces more flexible PTS-like systems, but it will also help, in a later paper, to bridge the gap between PTSs and systems of Illative Combinatory Logic. First we consider (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Bunder’s paradox.Michael Caie - 2020 - Review of Symbolic Logic 13 (4):829-844.
    Systems ofillative logicare logical calculi formulated in the untypedλ-calculus supplemented with certain logical constants.1In this short paper, I consider a paradox that arises in illative logic. I note two prima facie attractive ways of resolving the paradox. The first is well known to be consistent, and I briefly outline a now standard construction used by Scott and Aczel that establishes this. The second, however, has been thought to be inconsistent. I show that this isn’t so, by providing a nonempty class (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic based on combinators.Yuichi Komori - 1989 - Bulletin of the Section of Logic 18 (3):100-104.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Basic simple type theory, J. Roger Hindley.Hans-Joerg Tiede - 1999 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 8 (4):473-476.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Uniqueness of normal proofs in implicational intuitionistic logic.Takahito Aoto - 1999 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 8 (2):217-242.
    A minimal theorem in a logic L is an L-theorem which is not a non-trivial substitution instance of another L-theorem. Komori (1987) raised the question whether every minimal implicational theorem in intuitionistic logic has a unique normal proof in the natural deduction system NJ. The answer has been known to be partially positive and generally negative. It is shown here that a minimal implicational theorem A in intuitionistic logic has a unique -normal proof in NJ whenever A is provable without (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On adding (ξ) to weak equality in combinatory logic.Martin W. Bunder, J. Roger Hindley & Jonathan P. Seldin - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (2):590-607.
    Because the main difference between combinatory weak equality and λβ-equality is that the rule \begin{equation*}\tag{\xi} X = Y \vdash \lambda x.X = \lambda x.Y\end{equation*} is valid for the latter but not the former, it is easy to assume that another way of defining combinatory β-equality is to add rule (ξ) to the postulates for weak equality. However, to make this true, one must choose the definition of combinatory abstraction in (ξ) very carefully. If one tries to use one of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some results on combinators in the system TRC.Thomas Jech - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (4):1811-1819.
    We investigate the system TRC of untyped illative combinatory logic that is equiconsistent with New Foundations. We prove that various unstratified combinators do not exist in TRC.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Church-Rosser Property in Symmetric Combinatory Logic.Katalin Bimbó - 2005 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 70 (2):536 - 556.
    Symmetic combinatory logic with the symmetric analogue of a combinatorially complete base (in the form of symmetric λ-calculus) is known to lack the Church-Rosser property. We prove a much stronger theorem that no symmetric combinatory logic that contains at least two proper symmetric combinators has the Church-Rosser property. Although the statement of the result looks similar to an earlier one concerning dual combinatory logic, the proof is different because symmetric combinators may form redexes in both left and right associated terms. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Advances in Natural Deduction: A Celebration of Dag Prawitz's Work.Luiz Carlos Pereira & Edward Hermann Haeusler (eds.) - 2012 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    This collection of papers, celebrating the contributions of Swedish logician Dag Prawitz to Proof Theory, has been assembled from those presented at the Natural Deduction conference organized in Rio de Janeiro to honour his seminal research. Dag Prawitz’s work forms the basis of intuitionistic type theory and his inversion principle constitutes the foundation of most modern accounts of proof-theoretic semantics in Logic, Linguistics and Theoretical Computer Science. The range of contributions includes material on the extension of natural deduction with higher-order (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the role of implication in formal logic.Jonathan Seldin - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (3):1076-1114.
    Evidence is given that implication (and its special case, negation) carry the logical strength of a system of formal logic. This is done by proving normalization and cut elimination for a system based on combinatory logic or λ-calculus with logical constants for and, or, all, and exists, but with none for either implication or negation. The proof is strictly finitary, showing that this system is very weak. The results can be extended to a "classical" version of the system. They can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analytic proof systems for λ-calculus: the elimination of transitivity, and why it matters. [REVIEW]Pierluigi Minari - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (5):385-424.
    We introduce new proof systems G[β] and G ext[β], which are equivalent to the standard equational calculi of λβ- and λβη- conversion, and which may be qualified as ‘analytic’ because it is possible to establish, by purely proof-theoretical methods, that in both of them the transitivity rule admits effective elimination. This key feature, besides its intrinsic conceptual significance, turns out to provide a common logical background to new and comparatively simple demonstrations—rooted in nice proof-theoretical properties of transitivity-free derivations—of a number (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation