Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Successive approximation in targeted movement: An alternative hypothesis.Paul J. Cordo & Leslie Bevan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):729-730.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Equilibrium-point hypothesis, minimum effort control strategy and the triphasic muscle activation pattern.Ning Lan & Patrick E. Crago - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):769-771.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Does the nervous system depend on kinesthetic information to control natural limb movements?S. C. Gandevia & David Burke - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):614-632.
    This target article draws together two groups of experimental studies on the control of human movement through peripheral feedback and centrally generated signals of motor commands. First, during natural movement, feedback from muscle, joint, and cutaneous afferents changes; in human subjects these changes have reflex and kinesthetic consequences. Recent psychophysical and microneurographic evidence suggests that joint and even cutaneous afferents may have a proprioceptive role. Second, the role of centrally generated motor commands in the control of normal movements and movements (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   82 citations  
  • Implications of neural networks for how we think about brain function.David A. Robinson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):644-655.
    Engineers use neural networks to control systems too complex for conventional engineering solutions. To examine the behavior of individual hidden units would defeat the purpose of this approach because it would be largely uninterpretable. Yet neurophysiologists spend their careers doing just that! Hidden units contain bits and scraps of signals that yield only arcane hints about network function and no information about how its individual units process signals. Most literature on single-unit recordings attests to this grim fact. On the other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The representation of egocentric space in the posterior parietal cortex.J. F. Stein - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):691-700.
    The posterior parietal cortex (PPC) is the most likely site where egocentric spatial relationships are represented in the brain. PPC cells receive visual, auditory, somaesthetic, and vestibular sensory inputs; oculomotor, head, limb, and body motor signals; and strong motivational projections from the limbic system. Their discharge increases not only when an animal moves towards a sensory target, but also when it directs its attention to it. PPC lesions have the opposite effect: sensory inattention and neglect. The PPC does not seem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Does the nervous system use equilibrium-point control to guide single and multiple joint movements?E. Bizzi, N. Hogan, F. A. Mussa-Ivaldi & S. Giszter - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):603-613.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • (1 other version)Connectionist Sentence Processing in Perspective.Mark Steedman - 1999 - Cognitive Science 23 (4):615-634.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Cognitive systems as dynamic systems.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1992 - Topoi 11 (1):27-43.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A nonclassical framework for cognitive science.Terence E. Horgan & John L. Tienson - 1994 - Synthese 101 (3):305-45.
    David Marr provided a useful framework for theorizing about cognition within classical, AI-style cognitive science, in terms of three levels of description: the levels of (i) cognitive function, (ii) algorithm and (iii) physical implementation. We generalize this framework: (i) cognitive state transitions, (ii) mathematical/functional design and (iii) physical implementation or realization. Specifying the middle, design level to be the theory of dynamical systems yields a nonclassical, alternative framework that suits (but is not committed to) connectionism. We consider how a brain's (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wittgenstein and connectionism: A significant complementarity?Stephen L. Mills - 1993 - Philosophy 34:137-157.
    Between the later views of Wittgenstein and those of connectionism 1 on the subject of the mastery of language there is an impressively large number of similarities. The task of establishing this claim is carried out in the second section of this paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Representations don't need rules: Reply to James Garson.Terence Horgan & John Tienson - 1994 - Mind and Language 9 (1):1-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • On the potential of non-classical constituency.W. F. G. Haselager - 1999 - Acta Analytica 144:23-42.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Connectionism, systematicity, and the frame problem.W. F. G. Haselager & J. F. H. Van Rappard - 1998 - Minds and Machines 8 (2):161-179.
    This paper investigates connectionism's potential to solve the frame problem. The frame problem arises in the context of modelling the human ability to see the relevant consequences of events in a situation. It has been claimed to be unsolvable for classical cognitive science, but easily manageable for connectionism. We will focus on a representational approach to the frame problem which advocates the use of intrinsic representations. We argue that although connectionism's distributed representations may look promising from this perspective, doubts can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Is stiffness the mainspring of posture and movement?Z. Hasan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):756-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • How does the nervous system control the equilibrium trajectory?S. V. Adamovich - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):704-705.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   40 citations  
  • Reasoning, nonmonotonicity and learning in connectionist networks that capture propositional knowledge.Gadi Pinkas - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 77 (2):203-247.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • From Implausible Artificial Neurons to Idealized Cognitive Models: Rebooting Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence.Catherine Stinson - 2020 - Philosophy of Science 87 (4):590-611.
    There is a vast literature within philosophy of mind that focuses on artificial intelligence, but hardly mentions methodological questions. There is also a growing body of work in philosophy of science about modeling methodology that hardly mentions examples from cognitive science. Here these discussions are connected. Insights developed in the philosophy of science literature about the importance of idealization provide a way of understanding the neural implausibility of connectionist networks. Insights from neurocognitive science illuminate how relevant similarities between models and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • (1 other version)Wittgenstein and Connectionism: a Significant Complementarity?Stephen Mills - 1993 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 34:137-157.
    Between the later views of Wittgenstein and those of connectionism on the subject of the mastery of language there is an impressively large number of similarities. The task of establishing this claim is carried out in the second section of this paper.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Convolution and modal representations in Thagard and Stewart’s neural theory of creativity: a critical analysis.Jean-Frédéric de Pasquale & Pierre Poirier - 2016 - Synthese 193 (5):1535-1560.
    According to Thagard and Stewart :1–33, 2011), creativity results from the combination of neural representations, and combination results from convolution, an operation on vectors defined in the holographic reduced representation framework. They use these ideas to understand creativity as it occurs in many domains, and in particular in science. We argue that, because of its algebraic properties, convolution alone is ill-suited to the role proposed by Thagard and Stewart. The semantic pointer concept allows us to see how we can apply (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The cerebellum and memory.Richard F. Thompson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):801-802.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A bound on synchronically interpretable structure.Jon M. Slack - 2004 - Mind and Language 19 (3):305–333.
    Multiple explanatory frameworks may be required to provide an adequate account of human cognition. This paper embeds the classical account within a neural network framework, exploring the encoding of syntacticallystructured objects over the synchronicdiachronic characteristics of networks. Synchronic structure is defined in terms of temporal binding and the superposition of states. To accommodate asymmetric relations, synchronic structure is subject to the type uniqueness constraint. The nature of synchronic structure is shown to underlie Xbar theory that characterizes the phrasal structure of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A parallel approach to syntax for generation.Nigel Ward - 1992 - Artificial Intelligence 57 (2-3):183-225.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations