Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness.J. Kevin O’Regan & Alva Noë - 2001 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24 (5):883-917.
    Many current neurophysiological, psychophysical, and psychological approaches to vision rest on the idea that when we see, the brain produces an internal representation of the world. The activation of this internal representation is assumed to give rise to the experience of seeing. The problem with this kind of approach is that it leaves unexplained how the existence of such a detailed internal representation might produce visual consciousness. An alternative proposal is made here. We propose that seeing is a way of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   741 citations  
  • Perception and action: Alternative views.Susan Hurley - 2001 - Synthese 129 (1):3-40.
    A traditional view of perception and action makestwo assumptions: that the causal flow betweenperception and action is primarily linear or one-way,and that they are merely instrumentally related toeach other, so that each is a means to the other.Either or both of these assumptions can be rejected. Behaviorism rejects the instrumental but not theone-way aspect of the traditional view, thus leavingitself open to charges of verificationism. Ecologicalviews reject the one-way aspect but not theinstrumental aspect of the traditional view, so thatperception and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   84 citations  
  • The reflexive theory of perception.John Dilworth - 2005 - Behavior and Philosophy 33 (1):17-40.
    ABSTRACT: The Reflexive Theory of Perception (RTP) claims that perception of an object or property X by an organism Z consists in Z being caused by X to acquire some disposition D toward X itself. This broadly behavioral perceptual theory explains perceptual intentionality and correct versus incorrect, plus successful versus unsuccessful, perception in a plausible evolutionary framework. The theory also undermines cognitive and perceptual modularity assumptions, including informational or purely epistemic views of perception in that, according to the RTP, any (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Neural plasticity and consciousness.Susan Hurley & Alva Noë - 2003 - Biology and Philosophy 18 (1):131-168.
    and apply it to various examples of neural plasticity in which input is rerouted intermodally or intramodally to nonstandard cortical targets. In some cases but not others, cortical activity ‘defers’ to the nonstandard sources of input. We ask why, consider some possible explanations, and propose a dynamic sensorimotor hypothesis. We believe that this distinction is important and worthy of further study, both philosophical and empirical, whether or not our hypothesis turns out to be correct. In particular, the question of how (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   109 citations  
  • The Weirdness of the World.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2024 - Princeton University Press.
    How all philosophical explanations of human consciousness and the fundamental structure of the cosmos are bizarre—and why that’s a good thing Do we live inside a simulated reality or a pocket universe embedded in a larger structure about which we know virtually nothing? Is consciousness a purely physical matter, or might it require something extra, something nonphysical? According to the philosopher Eric Schwitzgebel, it’s hard to say. In The Weirdness of the World, Schwitzgebel argues that the answers to these fundamental (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hylomorphism and the Construct of Consciousness.William Jaworski - 2020 - Topoi 39 (5):1125-1139.
    The hard problem of consciousness has held center stage in the philosophy of mind for the past two decades. It claims that the phenomenal character of conscious experiences—what it’s like to be in them—cannot be explained by appeal to the operation of physiological subsystems. The hard problem arises, however, only given the assumption that hylomorphism is false. Hylomorphism claims that structure is a basic ontological and explanatory principle. A human is not a random collection of physical materials, but an individual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Neural plasticity and the limits of scientific knowledge.Pasha Parpia - 2015 - Dissertation, University of Sussex
    Western science claims to provide unique, objective information about the world. This is supported by the observation that peoples across cultures will agree upon a common description of the physical world. Further, the use of scientific instruments and mathematics is claimed to enable the objectification of science. In this work, carried out by reviewing the scientific literature, the above claims are disputed systematically by evaluating the definition of physical reality and the scientific method, showing that empiricism relies ultimately upon the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Verkörperlichung und situative Einbettung.Holger Lyre - 2013 - In Achim Stephan & Sven Walter (eds.), Handbuch Kognitionswissenschaft. Metzler, Stuttgart, S. , 2013. Metzler. pp. 186-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Precis of Action in Perception.Alva Noë - 2006 - PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12.
    The main idea of this book is that perceiving is a way of acting. Perception is not something that happens to us, or in us. It is something we do. Think of a blind person tap-tapping his or her way around a cluttered space, perceiving that space by touch, not all at once, but through time, by skillful probing and movement. This is, or at least ought to be, our paradigm of what perceiving is. The world makes itself available to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A provisional sensory/motor “complementarity” model for adaptation effects.Ivo Kohler - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):73-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Through the inverting glass: first-person observations on spatial vision and imagery. [REVIEW]Jan Degenaar - 2014 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (2):373-393.
    Experience with inverting glasses reveals key factors of spatial vision. Interpretations of the literature based on the metaphor of a “visual image” have raised the question whether visual experience with inverting glasses remains inverted or whether it may turn back to normal after adaptation to the glasses. Here, I report on my experience with left/right inverting glasses and argue that a more fine-grained sensorimotor analysis can resolve the issue. Crucially, inverting glasses introduce a conflict at the very heart of spatial (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Cognitive Penetrability of Perception.Dustin Stokes - 2013 - Philosophy Compass 8 (7):646-663.
    Perception is typically distinguished from cognition. For example, seeing is importantly different from believing. And while what one sees clearly influences what one thinks, it is debatable whether what one believes and otherwise thinks can influence, in some direct and non-trivial way, what one sees. The latter possible relation is the cognitive penetration of perception. Cognitive penetration, if it occurs, has implications for philosophy of science, epistemology, philosophy of mind, and cognitive science. This paper offers an analysis of the phenomenon, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   107 citations  
  • Against direct perception.Shimon Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):333-81.
    Central to contemporary cognitive science is the notion that mental processes involve computations defined over internal representations. This view stands in sharp contrast to the to visual perception and cognition, whose most prominent proponent has been J.J. Gibson. In the direct theory, perception does not involve computations of any sort; it is the result of the direct pickup of available information. The publication of Gibson's recent book (Gibson 1979) offers an opportunity to examine his approach, and, more generally, to contrast (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   174 citations  
  • Looks as powers.Philip Pettit - 2003 - Philosophical Issues 13 (1):221-52.
    Although they may differ on the reason why, many philosophers hold that it is a priori that an object is red if and only if it is such as to look red to normal observers in normal conditions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   61 citations  
  • Being Somewhere. Egocentic spatial representation as self-representation.Ferdinand Pöhlmann - 2017 - Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.
    Ferdinand Pöhlmann argues that a sense of one’s own basic abilities to move is a constitutive condition on the ability to perceive the world spatially. This constitutive relation explains why egocentric spatial representation is to be regarded as a kind of self-representation. In arguing for these claims, conceptual as well as empirical questions are discussed and an overview of accounts that take action as a constitutive condition on spatial representation is given. The picture that emerges is linked to the phenomenological (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Problem of Known Illusion and the Resemblance of Experience to Reality.Eric Schwitzgebel - 2014 - Philosophy of Science 81 (5):954-960.
    Are objects in convex passenger-side mirrors “closer than they appear”? If one adapts to inverting goggles, does the world go back to looking the way it was before, or does the world look approximately the same throughout the course of adaptation, only losing its normative sense of wrongness? The answers to these empirical, introspective questions might help cast light on the classic philosophical debate about the degree of resemblance between our visual experience of reality and things as they are in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Three functions of motor-sensory feedback in object perception.Hans Wallach - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):84-85.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Direct perception and perceptual processes.Gunnar Johansson, Claes von Hofsten & Gunnar Jansson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):388-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Difficulties with a direct theory of perception.Irvin Rock - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):398-399.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Functionalism and inverted spectra.David J. Cole - 1990 - Synthese 82 (2):207-22.
    Functionalism, a philosophical theory, has empirical consequences. Functionalism predicts that where systematic transformations of sensory input occur and are followed by behavioral accommodation in which normal function of the organism is restored such that the causes and effects of the subject's psychological states return to those of the period prior to the transformation, there will be a return of qualia or subjective experiences to those present prior to the transform. A transformation of this type that has long been of philosophical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Re-afference in space and movement perception.Austin H. Riesen - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):78-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A stationary subject does perceive curvature when wearing a prism in a spotted drum.Brian Craske - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):66-66.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Prospects for a cognitive ethology.Donald R. Griffin - 1978 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4):527-538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   159 citations  
  • An efferent component in the visual perception of direction and extent.Stanley Coren - 1986 - Psychological Review 93 (4):391-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • Oculomotor hysteresis: implications for testing sensorimotor and ecological optics theories.Wayne L. Shebilske - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):80-80.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Perception, information, and computation.S. Ullman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):408-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the nature of information in behalf of direct perception.Rebecca K. Jones & Anne D. Pick - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):388-389.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Why argue about direct perception?J. J. Koenderink - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):390-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Direct perception or mediated perception: a comparison of rival viewpoints.William Epstein - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Achieving Transparency: An Argument For Enactivism.Dave Ward - 2015 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (3):650-680.
    The transparency of perceptual experience has been invoked in support of many views about perception. I argue that it supports a form of enactivism—the view that capacities for perceptual experience and for intentional agency are essentially interdependent. I clarify the perceptual phenomenon at issue, and argue that enactivists should expect to find a parallel instance of transparency in our agentive experience, and that the two forms of transparency are constitutively interdependent. I then argue that i) we do indeed find such (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Non-Visual Determinants of Perception.Arien Mack - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):75-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The problem of adaptation to prismatically-altered shape.Irvin Rock - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):78-79.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Motor system changes are not necessary for changes in perception.George Singer, Meredith Wallace & John K. Collins - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):80-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Inferring the meaning of direct perception.Geoffrey E. Hinton - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):387-388.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representing the impossible.Jennifer Matey - 2013 - Philosophical Psychology 26 (2):188 - 206.
    A theory of perception must be capable of explaining the full range of conscious perception, including amodal perception. In amodal perception we perceive the world to contain physical features that are not directly detectable by the sensory receptors. According to the active-externalist theory of perception, amodal perception depends on active engagement with perceptual objects. This paper focuses on amodal visual perception and presents a counter-example to the idea that active-externalism can account for amodal perception. The counterexample involves the experience of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Kicking the Kohler habit.Colin Klein & Gabriel Love - 2007 - Philosophical Psychology 20 (5):609 – 619.
    Kohler's experiments with inverting goggles are often thought to support enactivism by showing that visual re-inversion occurs simultaneous with the return of sensorimotor skill. Closer examination reveals that Kohler's work does not show this. Recent work by Linden et al. shows that re-inversion, if it occurs at all, does not occur when the enactivist predicts. As such, the empirical evidence weighs against enactivism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Evaluating nonreplication: more theory and background necessary.Lewis O. Harvey - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):70-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When is sensory-motor information necessary, when only useful, and when superfluous?Ralph Norman Haber - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):68-70.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can the brain be divided into a sensory and a motor part?Volker Henn - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):70-71.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Attention as an explanatory concept in perceptual adaptation.Gordon M. Redding - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):77-78.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • There is more to psychological meaningfulness than computation and representation.Sverker Runeson - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):399-400.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • What kind of indirect process is visual perception?Aaron Sloman - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):401-404.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In defense of invariances and higher-order stimuli.K. von Fieandt - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):404-405.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visual perception is underdetermined by stimulation.John W. Gyr - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):386-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptation of the distortion of shape is different from adaptation to the distortion of space.H. H. Mikaelian - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):76-76.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Position information versus motor programs: two levels of sensorimotor theory.Kenneth R. Paap - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):77-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Nonrandom curvature adaptation to random visual displays.Ronald A. Finke - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (1):68-68.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are mediating representations the ghosts in the machine?Alan K. Mackworth - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):393-394.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information pickup is the activity of perceiving.Edward S. Reed - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):397-398.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Visual perception: the shifting domain of discourse.Geoffrey R. Loftus & Elizabeth F. Loftus - 1980 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (3):391-392.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark