Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Kant’s post-1800 Disavowal of the Highest Good Argument for the Existence of God.Samuel Kahn - 2018 - Kant Yearbook 10 (1):63-83.
    I have two main goals in this paper. The first is to argue for the thesis that Kant gave up on his highest good argument for the existence of God around 1800. The second is to revive a dialogue about this thesis that died out in the 1960s. The paper is divided into three sections. In the first, I reconstruct Kant’s highest good argument. In the second, I turn to the post-1800 convolutes of Kant’s Opus postumum to discuss his repeated (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • What is the Scandal of Philosophy?Roberto Horácio de Sá Pereira - 2018 - International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 8 (3):141-166.
    The central question of this paper is: what has Kant’s Refutation of Idealism argument proven, if anything? What is the real scandal of philosophy and universal human reason? I argue that Kant’s Refutation argument can only be considered sound if we assume that his target is what I call ‘metaphysical external-world skepticism.’ What is in question is not the ‘existence’ of outside things but their very ‘nature,’ that is, the claim that the thing outside us, which appears to us as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Absolute Positing, the Frege Anticipation Thesis, and Kant's Definitions of Judgment.Timothy Rosenkoetter - 2010 - European Journal of Philosophy 18 (4):539-566.
    Abstract: Kant follows a substantial tradition by defining judgment so that it must involve a relation of concepts, which raises the question of why he thinks that single-term existential judgments should still qualify as judgments. There is a ready explanation if Kant is somehow anticipating a Fregean second-order account of existence, an interpretation that is already widely held for separate reasons. This paper examines Kant's early (1763) critique of Wolffian accounts of existence, finding that it provides the key idea in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • L’empirismo di Kant: illusione, menzogna e biasimo.Mariannina Failla - 2016 - Con-Textos Kantianos 3:55-80.
    Il saggio intende mettere a fuoco il concetto di empirismo kantiano intendendolo come mediazione di finito e infinito. Si analizzano, pertanto, le affinità di Kant con la fenomenologia analitica di Lambert e le giovanili critiche hegeliane alla filosofia kantiana per poi occuparsi dell’illusione e della menzogna. Esse vengono interpretare come due figure differenziate dell’empirismo kantiano: con la prima si mettono al centro gli studi antropologici e il tema dell’integrazione sociale; con la seconda si affronta il problema della disgregazione sociale, la (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Schopenhauer, Kant and Compassion.Paul Guyer - 2012 - Kantian Review 17 (3):403-429.
    Schopenhauer presents his moral philosophy as diametrically opposed to that of Kant: for him, pure practical reason is an illusion and morality can arise only from the feeling of compassion, while for Kant it cannot be based on such a feeling and can be based only on pure practical reason. But the difference is not as great as Schopenhauer makes it seem, because for him compassion is supposed to arise from metaphysical insight into the unity of all being, thus from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Kant's noumenon and sunyata.Laura E. Weed - 2002 - Asian Philosophy 12 (2):77 – 95.
    This paper compares Kant's positions on space, time, the relational character of noumena, and the relational character of the self, with the somewhat similar accounts of those things in two philosophers of the Kyoto school: Keiji Nishitani and Nishida Kitaro. I will argue that the philosophers of the Kyoto school had a more coherent and better integrated account of those ideas, that was open to Kant. I think that the comparison both clarifies Kant's position on these topics, and elucidates the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Nothing: Kant’s analysis and the Hegelian critique.Gungor Tolga - unknown
    This thesis aims to throw an illuminating light on the as yet neglected concept of nothing in Kant’s system, a concept which is taken into consideration, by Kant, in accordance with the guiding thread of the categories of the understanding. My main argument is that Kant has a fourfold division of nothing and each has a transcendental function in his system. This function is basically a limiting one; setting up negative determinations without which Kant’s system would have never been constituted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Role of Magnitude in Kant's Critical Philosophy.Daniel Sutherland - 2004 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34 (3):411-441.
    In theCritique of Pure Reason,Kant argues for two principles that concern magnitudes. The first is the principle that ‘All intuitions are extensive magnitudes,’ which appears in the Axioms of Intuition (B202); the second is the principle that ‘In all appearances the real, which is an object of sensation, has an intensive magnitude, that is, a degree,’ which appears in the Anticipations of Perception (B207). A circle drawn in geometry and the space occupied by an object such as a book are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • The Coextensiveness Thesis and Kant's Modal Agnosticism in the ‘Postulates’.Uygar Abaci - 2013 - European Journal of Philosophy 24 (1):129-158.
    In the Critique of Pure Reason, following his elucidation of the ‘postulates’ of possibility, actuality, and necessity, Kant makes a series of puzzling remarks. He seems to deny the somewhat metaphysically intuitive contention that the extension of possibility is greater than that of actuality, which, in turn, is greater than that of necessity. Further, he states that the actual adds nothing to the possible. This leads to the view, fairly common in the literature, that Kant holds that all modal categories, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The Understanding in Transition: Fascicles X, XI and VII of Opus postumum.Terrence Thomson - 2019 - Con-Textos Kantianos 9:23-48.
    This essay investigates the transformation of the faculty of understanding in Kant’s Transition from Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science to Physics drafts found in Opus postumum. I argue that in fascicles X and XI Kant implicitly reverses the architectonic order of sensibility and understanding. Without an account of this reversal, Kant’s critique of Isaac Newton’s conception of phenomena and the so called Selbstsetzungslehre in fascicle VII fall apart. I argue that what is at stake is a challenge Kant makes to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant's argument for the categorical imperative.Patricia Kitcher - 2004 - Noûs 38 (4):555-584.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Transandantal metafiziğin olanaği: Kant ve Wıttgensteın.Cengiz İskender Özkan - 2016 - Ethos: Dialogues in Philosophy and Social Sciences 9 (1).
    Bu çalışmada Kant’ın ve Wittgenstein’ın felsefeleri metafiziğin olanağı bağlamında karşılaştırılmıştır. Her ikisinin felsefelerinin transcendental olup olmadığı ele alınmış ve metafizik anlayışları ortaya konmuştur. Metafiziğe karşı tutumları benzer olan iki düşünürün metafizik konusunda neden farklı sonuçlara vardıkları sorgulanmıştır. Dolayısıyla burada Kant’ın sentetik apriori önermelerin olanağı ile metafiziğin olanağı arasında kurduğu ilişki ifade edilmelidir. Kant’a göre bilgi olmanın ölçütü sentetik apriori yargıların olanaklı olmasıyla ilişkilidir. Wittgenstein’ın birinci dönemindeki felsefe anlayışında da benzer yönler bulunmaktadır. Bu benzerlik de, burada, onun dil ile dünya arasında (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The End of Eternity.Jamie Carlin Watson - 2017 - Sophia 56 (2):147-162.
    A popular critique of the kalām cosmological argument is that one argument for its second premise illicitly assumes a finite starting point for the series of past temporal events, thereby begging the question against opponents. Rejecting this assumption, opponents say, eliminates any objections to the possibility that the past is infinitely old and undermines the IFA’s ability to support premise 2. I contend that the plausibility of this objection depends on ambiguities in extant formulations of the IFA and that we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • (1 other version)O despertar do sonho dogmático.Orlando Bruno Linhares - 2005 - Trans/Form/Ação 28 (2):53-81.
    : Neste artigo argumento contra a interpretação muito difundida segundo a qual o ano de 1769 representou um marco na formação da filosofia transcendental e a Dissertação de 1770 corresponde ao primeiro texto crítico. O objetivo deste artigo é investigar a origem das antinomias nas Reflexões da década de 1770. Não se trata de esboçá-las, pois sobre elas Kant é reticente nesse período. Elas são objeto da atenção dele somente às vésperas da redação da Crítica da razão pura. Eu me (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contraddizione, pensabilità, impossibilità.Venanzio Raspa - 2015 - In P. Di Lucia & S. Colloca (eds.), L’impossibilità normativa. LED. pp. 127-148.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kant’s Microcosmic Doctrine(s) and his Transcendental Philosophy.Richard McDonough - 2016 - Meta: Research in Hermeneutics, Phenomenology, and Practical Philosophy 8 (1):99-120.
    Despite Conger’s classic view that one can find very little of the microcosmic doctrine in any of the Idealists, the paper argues that Kant develops several little known microcosmic doctrines over the course of his development from his first Critique to his second Critiqueto his Opus Postumum and that these are intimately connected with his various notions of “transcendental” philosophy. First, the roots of the microcosmic doctrine in Plato are explored. Second, Kant’s most basic microcosmic doctrine and its connection with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Kant's Anti-Scientism and the Origins of Phenomenology.Richard McDonough - 1998 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 29 (3):281-298.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Heidegger on Kant on the Alternative to the Scientism of the Enlightenment.Richard Mcdonough - 1997 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 28 (3):236-254.
    The paper argues that a philosopher who describes his main works as "critiques" of reason cannot be the simple defender of rational science that he is sometimes taken to be. Rather, as Heidegger argues, Kant's program is much deeper and more problematic.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)A most affecting view: Transcendental affection as causation de-schematized.Chad Mohler - 2004 - Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 8 (1).
    Kant claims that things-in-themselves produce in us sensible representations. Unfortunately, this “transcendental affection” appears to be inconsistent with Kant’s prohibition against applying the category of causality to things-in-themselves. This paper gives an account of transcendental affection that does not require it to be seen as a type of causation. Transcendental affection, properly understood, is the logical relation of the ground of things-in-themselves to the consequent of an affected subject. This relation is what one gets when one de-schematizes causation, revealing the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reflective judgment vs. investigation of things – a comparative study of Kant and Zhu Xi.Yangxiao Ou - unknown
    This thesis is devoted to studying two historical philosophical events that happened in the West and the East. A metaphysical crisis stimulated Kant’s writings during his late critical period towards the notion of the supersensible. It further motivated a methodological shift and his coining of reflective judgment, which eventually brought about a systemic unfolding of his critical philosophy via Kantian moral teleology. Zhu Xi and his Neo-Confucian contemporaries confronted a transformed intellectual landscape resulting from the Neo-Daoist and Buddhist discourses of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark