Switch to: References

Citations of:

Handbook of Philosophical Logic

[author unknown]
(1983)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Modal sequents for normal modal logics.Claudio Cerrato - 1993 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1):231-240.
    We present sequent calculi for normal modal logics where modal and propositional behaviours are separated, and we prove a cut elimination theorem for the basic system K, so as completeness theorems both for K itself and for its most popular enrichments. MSC: 03B45, 03F05.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Alonzo church:his life, his work and some of his miracles.Maía Manzano - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (4):211-232.
    This paper is dedicated to Alonzo Church, who died in August 1995 after a long life devoted to logic. To Church we owe lambda calculus, the thesis bearing his name and the solution to the Entscheidungsproblem.His well-known book Introduction to Mathematical LogicI, defined the subject matter of mathematical logic, the approach to be taken and the basic topics addressed. Church was the creator of the Journal of Symbolic Logicthe best-known journal of the area, which he edited for several decades This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Completeness and categoricity: Frege, gödel and model theory.Stephen Read - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (2):79-93.
    Frege’s project has been characterized as an attempt to formulate a complete system of logic adequate to characterize mathematical theories such as arithmetic and set theory. As such, it was seen to fail by Gödel’s incompleteness theorem of 1931. It is argued, however, that this is to impose a later interpretation on the word ‘complete’ it is clear from Dedekind’s writings that at least as good as interpretation of completeness is categoricity. Whereas few interesting first-order mathematical theories are categorical or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • A new semantics for first-order logic, multivalent and mostly intensional.Hugues Leblanc - 1984 - Topoi 3 (1):55-62.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the logic of nonmonotonic conditionals and conditional probabilities: Predicate logic. [REVIEW]James Hawthorne - 1998 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 27 (1):1-34.
    In a previous paper I described a range of nonmonotonic conditionals that behave like conditional probability functions at various levels of probabilistic support. These conditionals were defined as semantic relations on an object language for sentential logic. In this paper I extend the most prominent family of these conditionals to a language for predicate logic. My approach to quantifiers is closely related to Hartry Field's probabilistic semantics. Along the way I will show how Field's semantics differs from a substitutional interpretation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Tarski on “essentially richer” metalanguages.David DeVidi & Graham Solomon - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (1):1-28.
    It is well known that Tarski proved a result which can be stated roughly as: no sufficiently rich, consistent, classical language can contain its own truth definition. Tarski's way around this problem is to deal with two languages at a time, an object language for which we are defining truth and a metalanguage in which the definition occurs. An obvious question then is: under what conditions can we construct a definition of truth for a given object language. Tarski claims that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Probabilistic Semantics and Calculi for Multi-valued and Paraconsistent Logics.Jaime Ramos, João Rasga & Cristina Sernadas - forthcoming - Studia Logica:1-35.
    We show how to obtain a probabilistic semantics and calculus for a logic presented by a valuation specification. By identifying general forms of valuation constraints we are able to accommodate a wide class of propositional based logics encompassing multi-valued logics like Łukasiewicz 3-valued logic and the Belnap–Dunn four-valued logic as well as paraconsistent logics like $${\textsf{mbC}}$$ and $${\textsf{LFI1}}$$. The probabilistic calculus is automatically generated from the valuation specification. Although not having explicit probability constructors in the language, the rules of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Notion of Interpretation and Nonelementary Languages.Michal Krynicki - 1988 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 34 (6):541-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Modal Logic.James W. Garson - 2009 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   50 citations  
  • The Link Between Probability Functions and Logical Consequence.Peter Roeper - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (1):15-.
    RésuméOn défend ici l'idée que la définition des notions sémantiques à l'aide des fonctions de probabilité devrait être vue non pas comme une généralisation de la sémantique standard en termes d'assignations de valeurs de vérité, mais plutôt comme une généralisation aux degrés de conséquence logique, de la caractérisation de la relation de conséquence que l'on retrouve dans le calcul des séquents de Gentzen.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle'S natural deduction reconsidered.John M. Martin - 1997 - History and Philosophy of Logic 18 (1):1-15.
    John Corcoran’s natural deduction system for Aristotle’s syllogistic is reconsidered.Though Corcoran is no doubt right in interpreting Aristotle as viewing syllogisms as arguments and in rejecting Lukasiewicz’s treatment in terms of conditional sentences, it is argued that Corcoran is wrong in thinking that the only alternative is to construe Barbara and Celarent as deduction rules in a natural deduction system.An alternative is presented that is technically more elegant and equally compatible with the texts.The abstract role assigned by tradition and Lukasiewicz (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Probability functions and their assumption sets — the binary case.Hugues Leblanc & Charles G. Morgan - 1984 - Synthese 60 (1):91 - 106.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Validity Measurement in Some Propositional Logics.Branislav Boričić - 1997 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 43 (4):550-558.
    The language of the propositional calculus is extended by two families of propositional probability operators, inductively applicable to the formulae, and the set of all formulae provable in an arbitrary superintuitionistic propositional logic is extended by the probability measure axioms concerning those probability operators. A logical system obtained in such a way, similar to a kind of polymodal logic, makes possible to express a probability measure of truthfulness of any formula. The paper contains a description of the Kripke-type possible worlds (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Seeing to it that: a canonical form for agentives.Nuel Belnap & Michael Perloff - 1988 - Theoria 54 (3):175-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   91 citations  
  • Les fonctions de probabilité: la question de leur définissabilité récursive.Hugues Leblanc & Peter Roeper - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (4):643-.
    Pensons aux divers énoncés qui peuvent être composés à partir d'un ensemble fini ou dénombrable d'énoncés atomiques à l'aide de, disons, ‘˜’ et ‘&’; soit A n'importe lequel de ces énoncés; et soit l'ensemble SA des composantes atomiques de A. La valeur de vérité de A dépend évidemment des valeurs de vérité de certains membres de SA. En effet, si aux valeurs de vérité Vrai et Faux sont substitués les entiers 1 et 0, respectivement; la valeur de vérité VVV d'une (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic, ontology, mathematical practice.Stewart Shapiro - 1989 - Synthese 79 (1):13 - 50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • De A et B, de leur indépendance logique, et de ce qu'ils n'ont aucun contenu factuel commun.Peter Roeper & Hugues Leblanc - 1997 - Dialogue 36 (1):137-.
    The logical independence of two statements is tantamount to their probabilistic independence, the latter understood in a sense that derives from stochastic independence. And analogous logical and probabilistic senses of having the same factual content similarly coincide. These results are extended to notions of non-symmetrical independence and independence among more than two statements.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Are Uniqueness and Deducibility of Identicals the Same?Alberto Naibo & Mattia Petrolo - 2014 - Theoria 81 (2):143-181.
    A comparison is given between two conditions used to define logical constants: Belnap's uniqueness and Hacking's deducibility of identicals. It is shown that, in spite of some surface similarities, there is a deep difference between them. On the one hand, deducibility of identicals turns out to be a weaker and less demanding condition than uniqueness. On the other hand, deducibility of identicals is shown to be more faithful to the inferentialist perspective, permitting definition of genuinely proof-theoretical concepts. This kind of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Some Uses of Logic in Rigorous Philosophy.Guillermo E. Rosado Haddock - 2010 - Axiomathes 20 (2-3):385-398.
    This paper is concerned with the use of logic to solve philosophical problems. Such use of logic goes counter to the prevailing empiricist tradition in analytic circles. Specifically, model-theoretic tools are applied to three fundamental issues in the philosophy of logic and mathematics, namely, to the issue of the existence of mathematical entities, to the dispute between first- and second-order logic and to the definition of analyticity.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Elementary categorial logic, predicates of variable degree, and theory of quantity.Brent Mundy - 1989 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 18 (2):115 - 140.
    Developing some suggestions of Ramsey (1925), elementary logic is formulated with respect to an arbitrary categorial system rather than the categorial system of Logical Atomism which is retained in standard elementary logic. Among the many types of non-standard categorial systems allowed by this formalism, it is argued that elementary logic with predicates of variable degree occupies a distinguished position, both for formal reasons and because of its potential value for application of formal logic to natural language and natural science. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • More triviality.Richard Bradley - 1999 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (2):129-139.
    This paper uses the framework of Popper and Miller's work on axiom systems for conditional probabilities to explore Adams' thesis concerning the probabilities of conditionals. It is shown that even very weak axiom systems have only a very restricted set of models satisfying a natural generalisation of Adams' thesis, thereby casting severe doubt on the possibility of developing a non-Boolean semantics for conditionals consistent with it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Probability functions and their assumption sets — the singulary case.Hugues Leblanc - 1983 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 12 (4):379 - 402.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations