Switch to: References

Citations of:

[Omnibus Review]

Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (1):261-262 (1992)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Countable Additivity, Idealization, and Conceptual Realism.Yang Liu - 2020 - Economics and Philosophy 36 (1):127-147.
    This paper addresses the issue of finite versus countable additivity in Bayesian probability and decision theory -- in particular, Savage's theory of subjective expected utility and personal probability. I show that Savage's reason for not requiring countable additivity in his theory is inconclusive. The assessment leads to an analysis of various highly idealised assumptions commonly adopted in Bayesian theory, where I argue that a healthy dose of, what I call, conceptual realism is often helpful in understanding the interpretational value of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A special class of almost disjoint families.Thomas E. Leathrum - 1995 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (3):879-891.
    The collection of branches (maximal linearly ordered sets of nodes) of the tree $^{ (ordered by inclusion) forms an almost disjoint family (of sets of nodes). This family is not maximal--for example, any level of the tree is almost disjoint from all of the branches. How many sets must be added to the family of branches to make it maximal? This question leads to a series of definitions and results: a set of nodes is off-branch if it is almost disjoint (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The size of $\tilde{T}$.Paul Larson - 2000 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 39 (7):541-568.
    Given a stationary subset T of $\omega_{1}$ , let $\tilde{T}$ be the set of ordinals in the interval $(\omega_{1}, \omega_{2})$ which are necessarily in the image of T by any embedding derived from the nonstationary ideal. We consider the question of the size of $\tilde{T}$ , givenT, and use Martin's Maximum and $\mathbb{P}_{max}$ to give some answers.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Splitting stationary sets from weak forms of Choice.Paul Larson & Saharon Shelah - 2009 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 55 (3):299-306.
    Working in the context of restricted forms of the Axiom of Choice, we consider the problem of splitting the ordinals below λ of cofinality θ into λ many stationary sets, where θ < λ are regular cardinals. This is a continuation of [4].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • In memoriam: James Earl Baumgartner (1943–2011).J. A. Larson - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (7):877-909.
    James Earl Baumgartner (March 23, 1943–December 28, 2011) came of age mathematically during the emergence of forcing as a fundamental technique of set theory, and his seminal research changed the way set theory is done. He made fundamental contributions to the development of forcing, to our understanding of uncountable orders, to the partition calculus, and to large cardinals and their ideals. He promulgated the use of logic such as absoluteness and elementary submodels to solve problems in set theory, he applied (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bounding by canonical functions, with ch.Paul Larson & Saharon Shelah - 2003 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 3 (02):193-215.
    We show that the members of a certain class of semi-proper iterations do not add countable sets of ordinals. As a result, starting from suitable large cardinals one can obtain a model in which the Continuum Hypothesis holds and every function from ω1 to ω1 is bounded on a club by a canonical function for an ordinal less than ω2.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Nonconstructive Properties of Well-Ordered T 2 topological Spaces.Kyriakos Keremedis & Eleftherios Tachtsis - 1999 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 40 (4):548-553.
    We show that none of the following statements is provable in Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (ZF) answering the corresponding open questions from Brunner in ``The axiom of choice in topology'':(i) For every T2 topological space (X, T) if X is well-ordered, then X has a well-ordered base,(ii) For every T2 topological space (X, T), if X is well-ordered, then there exists a function f : X × W T such that W is a well-ordered set and f ({x} × W) is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Mad families, forcing and the Suslin Hypothesis.Miloš S. Kurilić - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (4):499-512.
    Let κ be a regular cardinal and P a partial ordering preserving the regularity of κ. If P is (κ-Baire and) of density κ, then there is a mad family on κ killed in all generic extensions (if and) only if below each p∈P there exists a κ-sized antichain. In this case a mad family on κ is killed (if and) only if there exists an injection from κ onto a dense subset of Ult(P) mapping the elements of onto nowhere (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Different similarities.Miloš S. Kurilić - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (7-8):839-859.
    We establish the hierarchy among twelve equivalence relations on the class of relational structures: the equality, the isomorphism, the equimorphism, the full relation, four similarities of structures induced by similarities of their self-embedding monoids and intersections of these equivalence relations. In particular, fixing a language L and a cardinal κ, we consider the interplay between the restrictions of these similarities to the class ModL of all L-structures of size κ. It turns out that, concerning the number of different similarities and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Radin forcing and its iterations.John Krueger - 2007 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (3-4):223-252.
    We provide an exposition of supercompact Radin forcing and present several methods for iterating Radin forcing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Fat sets and saturated ideals.John Krueger - 2003 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 68 (3):837-845.
    We strengthen a theorem of Gitik and Shelah [6] by showing that if κ is either weakly inaccessible or the successor of a singular cardinal and S is a stationary subset of κ such that $NS_{\kappa} \upharpoonright S$ is saturated then $\kappa \S$ is fat. Using this theorem we derive some results about the existence of fat stationary sets. We then strengthen some results due to Baumgartner and Taylor [2], showing in particular that if I is a $\lambda^{+++}-saturated$ normal ideal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Quantum Mechanics, Formalization and the Cosmological Constant Problem.Jerzy Król & Torsten Asselmeyer-Maluga - 2020 - Foundations of Science 25 (4):879-904.
    Based on formal arguments from Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory we develop the environment for explaining and resolving certain fundamental problems in physics. By these formal tools we show that any quantum system defined by an infinite dimensional Hilbert space of states interferes with the spacetime structure M. M and the quantum system both gain additional degrees of freedom, given by models of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. In particular, M develops the ground state where classical gravity vanishes. Quantum mechanics distinguishes set-theoretic random forcing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Random World and Quantum Mechanics.Jerzy Król, Krzysztof Bielas & Torsten Asselmeyer-Maluga - 2023 - Foundations of Science 28 (2):575-625.
    Quantum mechanics (QM) predicts probabilities on the fundamental level which are, via Born probability law, connected to the formal randomness of infinite sequences of QM outcomes. Recently it has been shown that QM is algorithmic 1-random in the sense of Martin–Löf. We extend this result and demonstrate that QM is algorithmic $$\omega$$ -random and generic, precisely as described by the ’miniaturisation’ of the Solovay forcing to arithmetic. This is extended further to the result that QM becomes Zermelo–Fraenkel Solovay random on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Model for Spacetime II. The Emergence of Higher Dimensions and Field Theory/Strings Dualities.Jerzy Król - 2006 - Foundations of Physics 36 (12):1778-1800.
    We show that in 4-spacetime modified at very short distances due to the weakening of classical logic, the higher dimensions emerge. We analyse the case of some smooth topoi, and the case of some class of pointless topoi. The pointless topoi raise the dimensionality due to the forcing adding “string” objects and thus replacing classical points in spacetime. Turning to strings would be something fundamental and connected with set theoretical forcing. The field theory/strings dualities originate at the set theoretical level (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Typed lambda-calculus in classical Zermelo-Frænkel set theory.Jean-Louis Krivine - 2001 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 40 (3):189-205.
    , which uses the intuitionistic propositional calculus, with the only connective →. It is very important, because the well known Curry-Howard correspondence between proofs and programs was originally discovered with it, and because it enjoys the normalization property: every typed term is strongly normalizable. It was extended to second order intuitionistic logic, in 1970, by J.-Y. Girard [4], under the name of system F, still with the normalization property.More recently, in 1990, the Curry-Howard correspondence was extended to classical logic, following (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Identity, indiscernibility, and philosophical claims.Décio Krause & Antonio Mariano Nogueira Coelho - 2005 - Axiomathes 15 (2):191-210.
    The concept of indiscernibility in a structure is analysed with the aim of emphasizing that in asserting that two objects are indiscernible, it is useful to consider these objects as members of (the domain of) a structure. A case for this usefulness is presented by examining the consequences of this view to the philosophical discussion on identity and indiscernibility in quantum theory.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • On constructions with 2-cardinals.Piotr Koszmider - 2017 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 56 (7-8):849-876.
    We propose developing the theory of consequences of morasses relevant in mathematical applications in the language alternative to the usual one, replacing commonly used structures by families of sets originating with Velleman’s neat simplified morasses called 2-cardinals. The theory of related trees, gaps, colorings of pairs and forcing notions is reformulated and sketched from a unifying point of view with the focus on the applicability to constructions of mathematical structures like Boolean algebras, Banach spaces or compact spaces. The paper is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What Are Structural Properties?†.Johannes Korbmacher & Georg Schiemer - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (3):295-323.
    Informally, structural properties of mathematical objects are usually characterized in one of two ways: either as properties expressible purely in terms of the primitive relations of mathematical theories, or as the properties that hold of all structurally similar mathematical objects. We present two formal explications corresponding to these two informal characterizations of structural properties. Based on this, we discuss the relation between the two explications. As will be shown, the two characterizations do not determine the same class of mathematical properties. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Axiomatic Theories of Partial Ground II: Partial Ground and Hierarchies of Typed Truth.Johannes Korbmacher - 2018 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 47 (2):193-226.
    This is part two of a two-part paper in which we develop an axiomatic theory of the relation of partial ground. The main novelty of the paper is the of use of a binary ground predicate rather than an operator to formalize ground. In this part of the paper, we extend the base theory of the first part of the paper with hierarchically typed truth-predicates and principles about the interaction of partial ground and truth. We show that our theory is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The category of inner models.Peter Koepke - 2002 - Synthese 133 (1-2):275 - 303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A minimal Prikry-type forcing for singularizing a measurable cardinal.Peter Koepke, Karen Räsch & Philipp Schlicht - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):85-100.
    Recently, Gitik, Kanovei and the first author proved that for a classical Prikry forcing extension the family of the intermediate models can be parametrized by $\mathscr{P}(\omega)/\mathrm{finite}$. By modifying the standard Prikry tree forcing we define a Prikry-type forcing which also singularizes a measurable cardinal but which is minimal, i.e., there are \emph{no} intermediate models properly between the ground model and the generic extension. The proof relies on combining the rigidity of the tree structure with indiscernibility arguments resulting from the normality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Kurepa trees and Namba forcing.Bernhard König & Yasuo Yoshinobu - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (4):1281-1290.
    We show that strongly compact cardinals and MM are sensitive to $\lambda$-closed forcings for arbitrarily large $\lambda$. This is done by adding ‘regressive' $\lambda$-Kurepa trees in either case. We argue that the destruction of regressive Kurepa trees requires a non-standard application of MM. As a corollary, we find a consistent example of an $\omega_2$-closed poset that is not forcing equivalent to any $\omega_2$-directed-closed poset.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Regular embeddings of the stationary tower and Woodin's Σ 2 2 maximality theorem.Richard Ketchersid, Paul B. Larson & Jindřich Zapletal - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (2):711-727.
    We present Woodin's proof that if there exists a measurable Woodin cardinal δ, then there is a forcing extension satisfying all $\Sigma _{2}^{2}$ sentences ϕ such that CH + ϕ holds in a forcing extension of V by a partial order in V δ . We also use some of the techniques from this proof to show that if there exists a stationary limit of stationary limits of Woodin cardinals, then in a homogeneous forcing extension there is an elementary embedding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Bristol model: An abyss called a Cohen real.Asaf Karagila - 2018 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 18 (2):1850008.
    We construct a model [Formula: see text] of [Formula: see text] which lies between [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text] for a Cohen real [Formula: see text] and does not have the form [Formula: see text] for any set [Formula: see text]. This is loosely based on the unwritten work done in a Bristol workshop about Woodin’s HOD Conjecture in 2011. The construction given here allows for a finer analysis of the needed assumptions on the ground models, thus taking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Ulm Classification of Analytic Equivalence Relations in Generic Universes.Vladimir Kanovei - 1998 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 44 (3):287-303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The mathematical development of set theory from Cantor to Cohen.Akihiro Kanamori - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):1-71.
    Set theory is an autonomous and sophisticated field of mathematics, enormously successful not only at its continuing development of its historical heritage but also at analyzing mathematical propositions cast in set-theoretic terms and gauging their consistency strength. But set theory is also distinguished by having begun intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes, and these have even been regarded as crucial by some of its great developers. This has encouraged the exaggeration of crises in foundations and of metaphysical doctrines in general. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Counterexamples to countable-section Π 2 1 uniformization and Π 3 1 separation.Vladimir Kanovei & Vassily Lyubetsky - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (3):262-283.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A definable E 0 class containing no definable elements.Vladimir Kanovei & Vassily Lyubetsky - 2015 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 54 (5-6):711-723.
    A generic extension L[x]\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathbf{L}[x]}$$\end{document} by a real x is defined, in which the E0\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${\mathsf{E}_0}$$\end{document}-class of x is a lightface Π21\documentclass[12pt]{minimal} \usepackage{amsmath} \usepackage{wasysym} \usepackage{amsfonts} \usepackage{amssymb} \usepackage{amsbsy} \usepackage{mathrsfs} \usepackage{upgreek} \setlength{\oddsidemargin}{-69pt} \begin{document}$${{\it \Pi}^1_2}$$\end{document} set containing no ordinal-definable reals.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Algebraic Structures of Mathematical Foundations.Robert Murray Jones - 2018 - Open Journal of Philosophy 8 (4):401-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Stacking mice.Ronald Jensen, Ernest Schimmerling, Ralf Schindler & John Steel - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (1):315-335.
    We show that either of the following hypotheses imply that there is an inner model with a proper class of strong cardinals and a proper class of Woodin cardinals. 1) There is a countably closed cardinal k ≥ N₃ such that □k and □(k) fail. 2) There is a cardinal k such that k is weakly compact in the generic extension by Col(k, k⁺). Of special interest is 1) with k = N₃ since it follows from PFA by theorems of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Full reflection at a measurable cardinal.Thomas Jech & Jiří Witzany - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (2):615-630.
    A stationary subset S of a regular uncountable cardinal κ reflects fully at regular cardinals if for every stationary set $T \subseteq \kappa$ of higher order consisting of regular cardinals there exists an α ∈ T such that S ∩ α is a stationary subset of α. Full Reflection states that every stationary set reflects fully at regular cardinals. We will prove that under a slightly weaker assumption than κ having the Mitchell order κ++ it is consistent that Full Reflection (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Forcing with quotients.Michael Hrušák & Jindřich Zapletal - 2008 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 47 (7-8):719-739.
    We study an extensive connection between quotient forcings of Borel subsets of Polish spaces modulo a σ-ideal and quotient forcings of subsets of countable sets modulo an ideal.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Von Rimscha's Transitivity Conditions.Paul Howard, Jean E. Rubin & Adrienne Stanley - 2000 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 46 (4):549-554.
    In Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice every set has the same cardinal number as some ordinal. Von Rimscha has weakened this condition to “Every set has the same cardinal number as some transitive set”. In set theory without the axiom of choice, we study the deductive strength of this and similar statements introduced by von Rimscha.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem Plus Countable Choice Do Not Imply Dependent Choice.Paul Howard & Jean E. Rubin - 1996 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 42 (1):410-420.
    Two Fraenkel-Mostowski models are constructed in which the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem is true. In both models, AC for countable sets is true, but AC for sets of cardinality 2math image and the 2m = m principle are both false. The Principle of Dependent Choices is true in the first model, but false in the second.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Representation of Functions and Total Antisymmetric Relations in Monadic Third Order Logic.M. Randall Holmes - 2019 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 48 (2):263-278.
    We analyze the representation of binary relations in general, and in particular of functions and of total antisymmetric relations, in monadic third order logic, that is, the simple typed theory of sets with three types. We show that there is no general representation of functions or of total antisymmetric relations in this theory. We present partial representations of functions and of total antisymmetric relations which work for large classes of these relations, and show that there is an adequate representation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Restricted versions of the Tukey-Teichmüller theorem that are equivalent to the Boolean prime ideal theorem.R. E. Hodel - 2005 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (4):459-472.
    We formulate a restricted version of the Tukey-Teichmüller Theorem that we denote by (rTT). We then prove that (rTT) and (BPI) are equivalent in ZF and that (rTT) applies rather naturally to several equivalent forms of (BPI): Alexander Subbase Theorem, Stone Representation Theorem, Model Existence and Compactness Theorems for propositional and first-order logic. We also give two variations of (rTT) that we denote by (rTT)+ and (rTT)++; each is equivalent to (rTT) in ZF. The variation (rTT)++ applies rather naturally to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Glimm-Effros for coanalytic equivalence relations.Greg Hjorth - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (2):402-422.
    Assuming every real has a sharp, we prove that for any $\mathop \prod \limits_\~ _1^1 $ equivalence relation either Borel reduces E₀ or in a $\mathop \Delta \limits_\~ _3^1 $ manner allows the assignment of bounded subsets of ω₁ as complete invariants.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Does category theory provide a framework for mathematical structuralism?Geoffrey Hellman - 2003 - Philosophia Mathematica 11 (2):129-157.
    Category theory and topos theory have been seen as providing a structuralist framework for mathematics autonomous vis-a-vis set theory. It is argued here that these theories require a background logic of relations and substantive assumptions addressing mathematical existence of categories themselves. We propose a synthesis of Bell's many-topoi view and modal-structuralism. Surprisingly, a combination of mereology and plural quantification suffices to describe hypothetical large domains, recovering the Grothendieck method of universes. Both topos theory and set theory can be carried out (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   57 citations  
  • Antichains of perfect and splitting trees.Paul Hein & Otmar Spinas - 2020 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (3-4):367-388.
    We investigate uncountable maximal antichains of perfect trees and of splitting trees. We show that in the case of perfect trees they must have size of at least the dominating number, whereas for splitting trees they are of size at least \\), i.e. the covering coefficient of the meager ideal. Finally, we show that uncountable maximal antichains of superperfect trees are at least of size the bounding number; moreover we show that this is best possible.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Pointwise definable models of set theory.Joel David Hamkins, David Linetsky & Jonas Reitz - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):139-156.
    A pointwise definable model is one in which every object is \loos definable without parameters. In a model of set theory, this property strengthens $V=\HOD$, but is not first-order expressible. Nevertheless, if \ZFC\ is consistent, then there are continuum many pointwise definable models of \ZFC. If there is a transitive model of \ZFC, then there are continuum many pointwise definable transitive models of \ZFC. What is more, every countable model of \ZFC\ has a class forcing extension that is pointwise definable. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Generalizations of the Kunen inconsistency.Joel David Hamkins, Greg Kirmayer & Norman Lewis Perlmutter - 2012 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 163 (12):1872-1890.
    We present several generalizations of the well-known Kunen inconsistency that there is no nontrivial elementary embedding from the set-theoretic universe V to itself. For example, there is no elementary embedding from the universe V to a set-forcing extension V[G], or conversely from V[G] to V, or more generally from one set-forcing ground model of the universe to another, or between any two models that are eventually stationary correct, or from V to HOD, or conversely from HOD to V, or indeed (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • Relations between some cardinals in the absence of the axiom of choice.Lorenz Halbeisen & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 7 (2):237-261.
    If we assume the axiom of choice, then every two cardinal numbers are comparable, In the absence of the axiom of choice, this is no longer so. For a few cardinalities related to an arbitrary infinite set, we will give all the possible relationships between them, where possible means that the relationship is consistent with the axioms of set theory. Further we investigate the relationships between some other cardinal numbers in specific permutation models and give some results provable without using (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A generalization of the Dual Ellentuck Theorem.Lorenz Halbeisen & Pierre Matet - 2003 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 42 (2):103-128.
    We prove versions of the Dual Ramsey Theorem and the Dual Ellentuck Theorem for families of partitions which are defined in terms of games.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Determinacy separations for class games.Sherwood Hachtman - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (5-6):635-648.
    We show, assuming weak large cardinals, that in the context of games of length \ with moves coming from a proper class, clopen determinacy is strictly weaker than open determinacy. The proof amounts to an analysis of a certain level of L that exists under large cardinal assumptions weaker than an inaccessible. Our argument is sufficiently general to give a family of determinacy separation results applying in any setting where the universal class is sufficiently closed; e.g., in third, seventh, or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The equality S1 = D = R.Rami Grossberg, Alexei Kolesnikov, Ivan Tomašić & Monica Van Dieren - 2003 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 49 (2):115-128.
    The new result of this paper is that for θ-stable we have S1[θ] = D[θ, L, ∞]. S1 is Hrushovski's rank. This is an improvement of a result of Kim and Pillay, who for simple theories under the assumption that either of the ranks be finite obtained the same identity. Only the first equality is new, the second equality is a result of Shelah from the seventies. We derive it by studying localizations of several rank functions, we get the followingMain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A basis theorem for perfect sets.Marcia J. Groszek & Theodore A. Slaman - 1998 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 4 (2):204-209.
    We show that if there is a nonconstructible real, then every perfect set has a nonconstructible element, answering a question of K. Prikry. This is a specific instance of a more general theorem giving a sufficient condition on a pair $M\subset N$ of models of set theory implying that every perfect set in N has an element in N which is not in M.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Measures: Back and forth between point sets and large sets.Noa Goldring - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (2):170-188.
    It was questions about points on the real line that initiated the study of set theory. Points paved the way to point sets and these to ever more abstract sets. And there was more: Reflection on structural properties of point sets not only initiated the study of ordinary sets; it also supplied blueprints for defining extra-ordinary, “large” sets, transcending those provided by standard set theory. In return, the existence of such large sets turned out critical to settling open conjectures about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Groszek‐Laver pair of undistinguishable ‐classes.Mohammad Golshani, Vladimir Kanovei & Vassily Lyubetsky - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (1-2):19-31.
    A generic extension of the constructible universe by reals is defined, in which the union of ‐classes of x and y is a lightface set, but neither of these two ‐classes is separately ordinal‐definable.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What is the theory without power set?Victoria Gitman, Joel David Hamkins & Thomas A. Johnstone - 2016 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 62 (4-5):391-406.
    We show that the theory, consisting of the usual axioms of but with the power set axiom removed—specifically axiomatized by extensionality, foundation, pairing, union, infinity, separation, replacement and the assertion that every set can be well‐ordered—is weaker than commonly supposed and is inadequate to establish several basic facts often desired in its context. For example, there are models of in which ω1 is singular, in which every set of reals is countable, yet ω1 exists, in which there are sets of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Strange ultrafilters.Moti Gitik - 2019 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 58 (1-2):35-52.
    We deal with some natural properties of ultrafilters which trivially fail for normal ultrafilters.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark