Switch to: References

Citations of:

Set Theory

Journal of Symbolic Logic 46 (4):876-877 (1981)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Backwards Easton forcing and 0#. [REVIEW]M. C. Stanley - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3):809 - 833.
    It is shown that if κ is an uncountable successor cardinal in L[ 0 ♯ ], then there is a normal tree T ∈ L [ 0 ♯ ] of height κ such that $0^\sharp \not\in L\lbrack\mathbf{T}\rbrack$ . Yet T is $ -distributive in L[ 0 ♯ ]. A proper class version of this theorem yields an analogous L[ 0 ♯ ]-definable tree such that distinct branches in the presence of 0 ♯ collapse the universe. A heretofore unutilized method for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Covering analytic sets by families of closed sets.Sławomir Solecki - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (3):1022-1031.
    We prove that for every family I of closed subsets of a Polish space each Σ 1 1 set can be covered by countably many members of I or else contains a nonempty Π 0 2 set which cannot be covered by countably many members of I. We prove an analogous result for κ-Souslin sets and show that if A ♯ exists for any $A \subset \omega^\omega$ , then the above result is true for Σ 1 2 sets. A theorem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The tree property and the failure of the Singular Cardinal Hypothesis at ℵω2.Dima Sinapova - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (3):934-946.
    We show that given ù many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which the tree property holds at ℵ ω²+1 and the SCH fails at ℵ ω².
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The tree property at ℵ ω+1.Dima Sinapova - 2012 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 77 (1):279-290.
    We show that given ω many supercompact cardinals, there is a generic extension in which there are no Aronszajn trees at ℵω+1. This is an improvement of the large cardinal assumptions. The previous hypothesis was a huge cardinal and ω many supercompact cardinals above it, in Magidor—Shelah [7].
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Co-critical points of elementary embeddings.Michael Sheard - 1985 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 50 (1):220-226.
    Probably the two most famous examples of elementary embeddings between inner models of set theory are the embeddings of the universe into an inner model given by a measurable cardinal and the embeddings of the constructible universeLinto itself given by 0#. In both of these examples, the “target model” is a subclass of the “ground model”. It is not hard to find examples of embeddings in which the target model is not a subclass of the ground model: ifis a generic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Meager nowhere-dense games (IV): N-tactics.Marion Scheepers - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (2):603-605.
    We consider the infinite game where player ONE chooses terms of a strictly increasing sequence of first category subsets of a space and TWO chooses nowhere dense sets. If after ω innings TWO's nowhere dense sets cover ONE's first category sets, then TWO wins. We prove a theorem which implies for the real line: If TWO has a winning strategy which depends on the most recent n moves of ONE only, then TWO has a winning strategy depending on the most (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Descriptive inner model theory.Grigor Sargsyan - 2013 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 19 (1):1-55.
    The purpose of this paper is to outline some recent progress in descriptive inner model theory, a branch of set theory which studies descriptive set theoretic and inner model theoretic objects using tools from both areas. There are several interlaced problems that lie on the border of these two areas of set theory, but one that has been rather central for almost two decades is the conjecture known as the Mouse Set Conjecture. One particular motivation for resolving MSC is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On the most open question in the history of mathematics: A discussion of Maddy.Adrian Riskin - 1994 - Philosophia Mathematica 2 (2):109-121.
    In this paper, I argue against Penelope Maddy's set-theoretic realism by arguing (1) that it is perfectly consistent with mathematical Platonism to deny that there is a fact of the matter concerning statements which are independent of the axioms of set theory, and that (2) denying this accords further that many contemporary Platonists assert that there is a fact of the matter because they are closet foundationalists, and that their brand of foundationalism is in radical conflict with actual mathematical practice.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The club principle and the distributivity number.Heike Mildenberger - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (1):34 - 46.
    We give an affirmative answer to Brendle's and Hrušák's question of whether the club principle together with h > N₁ is consistent. We work with a class of axiom A forcings with countable conditions such that q ≥ n p is determined by finitely many elements in the conditions p and q and that all strengthenings of a condition are subsets, and replace many names by actual sets. There are two types of technique: one for tree-like forcings and one for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The baire category theorem and cardinals of countable cofinality.Arnold W. Miller - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (2):275-288.
    Let κ B be the least cardinal for which the Baire category theorem fails for the real line R. Thus κ B is the least κ such that the real line can be covered by κ many nowhere dense sets. It is shown that κ B cannot have countable cofinality. On the other hand it is consistent that the corresponding cardinal for 2 ω 1 be ℵ ω . Similar questions are considered for the ideal of measure zero sets, other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • UFA fails in the bell-Kunen model.John W. L. Merrill - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (1):284-296.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural internal forcing schemata extending ZFC: Truth in the universe?Garvin Melles - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (2):461-472.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sets and supersets.Toby Meadows - 2016 - Synthese 193 (6):1875-1907.
    It is a commonplace of set theory to say that there is no set of all well-orderings nor a set of all sets. We are implored to accept this due to the threat of paradox and the ensuing descent into unintelligibility. In the absence of promising alternatives, we tend to take up a conservative stance and tow the line: there is no universe. In this paper, I am going to challenge this claim by taking seriously the idea that we can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Foundations as truths which organize mathematics.Colin Mclarty - 2013 - Review of Symbolic Logic 6 (1):76-86.
    The article looks briefly at Fefermans own foundations. Among many different senses of foundations, the one that mathematics needs in practice is a recognized body of truths adequate to organize definitions and proofs. Finding concise principles of this kind has been a huge achievement by mathematicians and logicians. We put ZFC and categorical foundations both into this context.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Logic in the Tractatus.Max Weiss - 2017 - Review of Symbolic Logic 10 (1):1-50.
    I present a reconstruction of the logical system of the Tractatus, which differs from classical logic in two ways. It includes an account of Wittgenstein’s “form-series” device, which suffices to express some effectively generated countably infinite disjunctions. And its attendant notion of structure is relativized to the fixed underlying universe of what is named. -/- There follow three results. First, the class of concepts definable in the system is closed under finitary induction. Second, if the universe of objects is countably (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Magidor function and diamond.Pierre Matet - 2011 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 76 (2):405 - 417.
    Let κ be a regular uncountable cardinal and λ be a cardinal greater than κ. We show that if 2 <κ ≤ M(κ, λ), then ◇ κ,λ holds, where M(κ, λ) equals $\lambda ^{\aleph }0$ if cf(λ) ≥ κ, and $(\lambda ^{+})^{\aleph _{0}}$ otherwise.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Partitions and filters.P. Matet - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (1):12-21.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On skinny stationary subsets of.Yo Matsubara & Toschimichi Usuba - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (2):667-680.
    We introduce the notion of skinniness for subsets of $\mathcal{P}_\kappa \lambda$ and its variants, namely skinnier and skinniest. We show that under some cardinal arithmetical assumptions, precipitousness or $2^\lambda$-saturation of $\mathrm{NS}_{\kappa\lambda}\mid X$, where $\mathrm{NS}_{\kappa\lambda}$ denotes the non-stationary ideal over $\mathcal{P}_\kappa \lambda$, implies the existence of a skinny stationary subset of $X$. We also show that if $\lambda$ is a singular cardinal, then there is no skinnier stationary subset of $\mathcal{P}_\kappa \lambda$. Furthermore, if $\lambda$ is a strong limit singular cardinal, there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reflecting stationary sets.Menachem Magidor - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):755-771.
    We prove that the statement "For every pair A, B, stationary subsets of ω 2 , composed of points of cofinality ω, there exists an ordinal α such that both A ∩ α and $B \bigcap \alpha$ are stationary subsets of α" is equiconsistent with the existence of weakly compact cardinal. (This completes results of Baumgartner and Harrington and Shelah.) We also prove, assuming the existence of infinitely many supercompact cardinals, the statement "Every stationary subset of ω ω + 1 (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • How applied mathematics became pure.Penelope Maddy - 2008 - Review of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):16-41.
    My goal here is to explore the relationship between pure and applied mathematics and then, eventually, to draw a few morals for both. In particular, I hope to show that this relationship has not been static, that the historical rise of pure mathematics has coincided with a gradual shift in our understanding of how mathematics works in application to the world. In some circles today, it is held that historical developments of this sort simply represent changes in fashion, or in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Recursively enumerable generic sets.Wolfgang Maass - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (4):809-823.
    We show that one can solve Post's Problem by constructing generic sets in the usual set theoretic framework applied to tiny universes. This method leads to a new class of recursively enumerable sets: r.e. generic sets. All r.e. generic sets are low and simple and therefore of Turing degree strictly between 0 and 0'. Further they supply the first example of a class of low recursively enumerable sets which are automorphic in the lattice E of recursively enumerable sets with inclusion. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Extending the Non-extendible: Shades of Infinity in Large Cardinals and Forcing Theories.Stathis Livadas - 2018 - Axiomathes 28 (5):565-586.
    This is an article whose intended scope is to deal with the question of infinity in formal mathematics, mainly in the context of the theory of large cardinals as it has developed over time since Cantor’s introduction of the theory of transfinite numbers in the late nineteenth century. A special focus has been given to this theory’s interrelation with the forcing theory, introduced by P. Cohen in his lectures of 1963 and further extended and deepened since then, which leads to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Ziegler spectrum of the ring of entire complex valued functions.Sonia L’Innocente, Françoise Point, Gena Puninski & Carlo Toffalori - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):160-177.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Putnam on reference and constructible sets.Michael Levin - 1997 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 48 (1):55-67.
    Putnam argues that, by ‘reinterpretation’, the Axiom of Constructibility can be saved from empirical refutation. This paper contends that this argument fails, a failure which leaves Putnam's sweeping appeal to the Lowenheim –Skolem Theorem inadequately motivated.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Modeling occurrences of objects in relations.Joop Leo - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (1):145-174.
    We study the logical structure of relations, and in particular the notion of occurrences of objects in a state. We start with formulating a number of principles for occurrences and defining corresponding mathematical models. These models are analyzed to get more insight in the formal properties of occurrences. In particular, we prove uniqueness results that tell us more about the possible logical structures relations might have.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Patching ideal families and enforcing reflection.Christopher C. Leary - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (1):26-37.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • An variation for one souslin tree.Paul Larson - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (1):81-98.
    We present a variation of the forcing S max as presented in Woodin [4]. Our forcing is a P max -style construction where each model condition selects one Souslin tree. In the extension there is a Souslin tree T G which is the direct limit of the selected Souslin trees in the models of the generic. In some sense, the generic extension is a maximal model of "there exists a minimal Souslin tree," with T G being this minimal tree. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Baire numbers, uncountable Cohen sets and perfect-set forcing.Avner Landver - 1992 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 57 (3):1086-1107.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Aronszajn trees, square principles, and stationary reflection.Chris Lambie-Hanson - 2017 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 63 (3-4):265-281.
    We investigate questions involving Aronszajn trees, square principles, and stationary reflection. We first consider two strengthenings of introduced by Brodsky and Rinot for the purpose of constructing κ‐Souslin trees. Answering a question of Rinot, we prove that the weaker of these strengthenings is compatible with stationary reflection at κ but the stronger is not. We then prove that, if μ is a singular cardinal, implies the existence of a special ‐tree with a cf(μ)‐ascent path, thus answering a question of Lücke.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The poset of all copies of the random graph has the 2-localization property.Miloš S. Kurilić & Stevo Todorčević - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (8):649-662.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Borel reductions and cub games in generalised descriptive set theory.Vadim Kulikov - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (2):439-458.
    It is shown that the power set of $\kappa$ ordered by the subset relation modulo various versions of the non-stationary ideal can be embedded into the partial order of Borel equivalence relations on $2^\kappa$ under Borel reducibility. Here $\kappa$ is an uncountable regular cardinal with $\kappa^{<\kappa}=\kappa$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • What Are Structural Properties?†.Johannes Korbmacher & Georg Schiemer - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (3):295-323.
    Informally, structural properties of mathematical objects are usually characterized in one of two ways: either as properties expressible purely in terms of the primitive relations of mathematical theories, or as the properties that hold of all structurally similar mathematical objects. We present two formal explications corresponding to these two informal characterizations of structural properties. Based on this, we discuss the relation between the two explications. As will be shown, the two characterizations do not determine the same class of mathematical properties. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   18 citations  
  • Stationary reflection for uncountable cofinality.Péter Komjáth - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (1):147-151.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The category of inner models.Peter Koepke - 2002 - Synthese 133 (1-2):275 - 303.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Regular embeddings of the stationary tower and Woodin's Σ 2 2 maximality theorem.Richard Ketchersid, Paul B. Larson & Jindřich Zapletal - 2010 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 75 (2):711-727.
    We present Woodin's proof that if there exists a measurable Woodin cardinal δ, then there is a forcing extension satisfying all $\Sigma _{2}^{2}$ sentences ϕ such that CH + ϕ holds in a forcing extension of V by a partial order in V δ . We also use some of the techniques from this proof to show that if there exists a stationary limit of stationary limits of Woodin cardinals, then in a homogeneous forcing extension there is an elementary embedding (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Bristol model: An abyss called a Cohen real.Asaf Karagila - 2018 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 18 (2):1850008.
    We construct a model [Formula: see text] of [Formula: see text] which lies between [Formula: see text] and [Formula: see text] for a Cohen real [Formula: see text] and does not have the form [Formula: see text] for any set [Formula: see text]. This is loosely based on the unwritten work done in a Bristol workshop about Woodin’s HOD Conjecture in 2011. The construction given here allows for a finer analysis of the needed assumptions on the ground models, thus taking (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Iterating symmetric extensions.Asaf Karagila - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):123-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The mathematical development of set theory from Cantor to Cohen.Akihiro Kanamori - 1996 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 2 (1):1-71.
    Set theory is an autonomous and sophisticated field of mathematics, enormously successful not only at its continuing development of its historical heritage but also at analyzing mathematical propositions cast in set-theoretic terms and gauging their consistency strength. But set theory is also distinguished by having begun intertwined with pronounced metaphysical attitudes, and these have even been regarded as crucial by some of its great developers. This has encouraged the exaggeration of crises in foundations and of metaphysical doctrines in general. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Definable minimal collapse functions at arbitrary projective levels.Vladimir Kanovei & Vassily Lyubetsky - 2019 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 84 (1):266-289.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The consistency strength of an infinitary Ramsey property.George Kafkoulis - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (4):1158-1195.
    In this paper we study the consistency strength of the theory $\mathbf\mathrm{ZFC} + (\exists\kappa \text{strong limit})(\forall\mu , and we prove the consistency of this theory relative to the consistency of the existence of a supercompact cardinal and an inaccessible above it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the existence of large p-ideals.Winfried Just, A. R. D. Mathias, Karel Prikry & Petr Simon - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (2):457-465.
    We prove the existence of p-ideals that are nonmeagre subsets of P(ω) under various set-theoretic assumptions.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Distributive ideals and partition relations.C. A. Johnson - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (3):617-625.
    It is a theorem of Rowbottom [12] that ifκis measurable andIis a normal prime ideal onκ, then for eachλ<κ,In this paper a natural structural property of ideals, distributivity, is considered and shown to be related to this and other ideal theoretic partition relations.The set theoretical terminology is standard and background results on the theory of ideals may be found in [5] and [8]. Throughoutκwill denote an uncountable regular cardinal, andIa proper, nonprincipal,κ-complete ideal onκ.NSκis the ideal of nonstationary subsets ofκ, andIκ= (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Maximality Principles in Set Theory.Luca Incurvati - 2017 - Philosophia Mathematica 25 (2):159-193.
    In set theory, a maximality principle is a principle that asserts some maximality property of the universe of sets or some part thereof. Set theorists have formulated a variety of maximality principles in order to settle statements left undecided by current standard set theory. In addition, philosophers of mathematics have explored maximality principles whilst attempting to prove categoricity theorems for set theory or providing criteria for selecting foundational theories. This article reviews recent work concerned with the formulation, investigation and justification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Souslin forcing.Jaime I. Ihoda & Saharon Shelah - 1988 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (4):1188-1207.
    We define the notion of Souslin forcing, and we prove that some properties are preserved under iteration. We define a weaker form of Martin's axiom, namely MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ), and using the results on Souslin forcing we show that MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ) is consistent with the existence of a Souslin tree and with the splitting number s = ℵ 1 . We prove that MA(Γ + ℵ 0 ) proves the additivity of measure. Also we introduce (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Constructing strongly equivalent nonisomorphic models for unsuperstable theories, Part A.Tapani Hyttinen & Saharon Shelah - 1994 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 59 (3):984-996.
    We study how equivalent nonisomorphic models an unsuperstable theory can have. We measure the equivalence by Ehrenfeucht-Fraisse games. This paper continues the work started in $[HT]$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • On Scott and Karp trees of uncountable models.Tapani Hyttinen & Jouko Väänänen - 1990 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 55 (3):897-908.
    Let U and B be two countable relational models of the same first order language. If the models are nonisomorphic, there is a unique countable ordinal α with the property that $\mathfrak{U} \equiv^\alpha_{\infty\omega} \mathfrak{B} \text{but not} \mathfrak{U} \equiv^{\alpha + 1}_{\infty\omega} \mathfrak{B},$ i.e. U and B are L ∞ω -equivalent up to quantifier-rank α but not up to α + 1. In this paper we consider models U and B of cardinality ω 1 and construct trees which have a similar relation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Forcing and Consistency Results for Recursion in3E Together with Selection Over ℵ1.M. R. R. Hoole - 1986 - Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 32 (7-9):107-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On ℵ1 many minimal models.Greg Hjorth - 1996 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 61 (3):906 - 919.
    The existence of a countable complete theory with exactly ℵ 1 many minimal models is independent of ZFC + ¬CH.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Universal sets for pointsets properly on the n th level of the projective hierarchy.Greg Hjorth, Leigh Humphries & Arnold W. Miller - 2013 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 78 (1):237-244.
    The Axiom of Projective Determinacy implies the existence of a universal $\utilde{\Pi}^{1}_{n}\setminus\utilde{\Delta}^{1}_{n}$ set for every $n \geq 1$. Assuming $\text{\upshape MA}(\aleph_{1})+\aleph_{1}=\aleph_{1}^{\mathbb{L}}$ there exists a universal $\utilde{\Pi}^{1}_{1}\setminus\utilde{\Delta}^{1}_{1}$ set. In ZFC there is a universal $\utilde{\Pi}^{0}_{\alpha}\setminus\utilde{\Delta}^{0}_{\alpha}$ set for every $\alpha$.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Properties of subtle cardinals.Claudia Henrion - 1987 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 52 (4):1005-1019.
    Subtle cardinals were first introduced in a paper by Jensen and Kunen [JK]. They show that ifκis subtle then ◇κholds. Subtle cardinals also play an important role in [B1], where Baumgartner proposed that certain large cardinal properties should be considered as properties of their associated normal ideals. He shows that in the case of ineffables, the ideals are particularly useful, as can be seen by the following theorem,κis ineffable if and only ifκis subtle andΠ½-indescribableandthe subtle andΠ½-indescribable ideals cohere, i.e. they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation