Switch to: References

Citations of:

Aristotle on Thinking

In Martha Craven Nussbaum & Amélie Rorty (eds.), Essays on Aristotle's De anima. New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 359-80 (1995 [1992])

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Highest Good in the Nicomachean Ethics and the Bhagavad Gita: Knowledge, Happiness, and Freedom.Roopen Majithia - 2024 - London: Bloomsbury Academic.
    This open access book presents a comparative study of two classics of world literature, offering the first sustained study of what unites and divides the Nicomachean Ethics and the Bhagavad Gita. -/- Asking what the texts think is the nature of moral action and how it relates to the highest good, Roopen Majithia shows how the Gita stresses the objectivity of knowledge and freedom from being a subject, while the Ethics emphasizes the knower, working out Aristotle’s central commitment to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle's Theory of Abstraction.Allan Bäck - 2014 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer.
    This book investigates Aristotle’s views on abstraction and explores how he uses it. In this work, the author follows Aristotle in focusing on the scientific detail first and then approaches the metaphysical claims, and so creates a reconstructed theory that explains many puzzles of Aristotle’s thought. Understanding the details of his theory of relations and abstraction further illuminates his theory of universals. Some of the features of Aristotle’s theory of abstraction developed in this book include: abstraction is a relation; perception (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Aristotle's Empiricism.Marc Gasser-Wingate - 2021 - Oxford University Press.
    Aristotle is famous for thinking that all our knowledge comes from perception. But it's not immediately clear what this view is meant to entail. It's not clear, for instance, what perception is supposed to contribute to the more advanced forms of knowledge that derive from it. Nor is it clear how we should understand the nature of its contribution—what it might mean to say that these more advanced forms of knowledge are "derived from" or "based on" what we perceive. Aristotle (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle on the Beginning of Animal Life and Soul Activities.Anna Schriefl & Mor Segev - 2023 - Apeiron 56 (3):587-619.
    For Aristotle, animals, by contrast to plants, possess a perceptual soul. However, there is disagreement concerning the point at which the perceptual soul is acquired, for him. On one influential interpretation, Aristotle thinks that the perceptual soul is acquired not during the initial formation of the embryo, but at some later stage of its development. On such interpretations of Aristotle’s view, the newly formed embryo is not yet an actual animal, but a plant-like living being or even inanimate matter. We (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristóteles: entre aisthesis y phantasía.Diego Antonio Pineda Rivera - 2016 - Universitas Philosophica 33 (67):131-164.
    El presente artículo examina el tránsito que, desde la percepción sensible hacia la imaginación, se hace en la psicología aristotélica, específicamente en el capítulo 3 del Libro III del De Anima y en el tratado Acerca de los ensueños. Tras un primer examen del uso que hace Aristóteles de los términos aisthesis y phantasía, y de examinar las razones por las cuales adscribe esta última a la facultad perceptiva del alma, se pone de presente la ampliación que del campo de (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-knowledge in Aristotle.Frank A. Lewis - 1996 - Topoi 15 (1):39-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • La philía politiké como amor mundi: La recepción de Hannah Arendt de la amistad política de Aristóteles.Elisa Goyenechea - 2021 - Isegoría 65:03-03.
    This paper examines Hannah Arendt’s reception of the Aristotelian philía. First, we expose the notes of the philía in his Nicomachean Ethics and the political projection of friendship as synaísthesis. Secondly, we argue that in a relevant fragment of “Truth and Politics” and in Lectures on Kant’s Political Philosophy, Arendt finishes clarifying her notion of friendship as a political and worldly bond. There she does not allude to Aristotle, but to Kant and his reflections on the sense of taste.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Unity of Intellect in Aristotle's De Anima.Lloyd Gerson - 2004 - Phronesis 49 (4):348-373.
    Desperately difficult texts inevitably elicit desperate hermeneutical measures. Aristotle's De Anima, book three, chapter five, is evidently one such text. At least since the time of Alexander of Aphrodisias, scholars have felt compelled to draw some remarkable conclusions regarding Aristotle's brief remarks in this passage regarding intellect. One such claim is that in chapter five, Aristotle introduces a second intellect, the so-called 'agent intellect', an intellect distinct from the 'passive intellect', the supposed focus of discussion up until this passage.1 This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Platonism and the invention of the problem of universals.Lloyd P. Gerson - 2004 - Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 86 (3):233-256.
    In this paper, I explore the origins of the ‘problem of universals’. I argue that the problem has come to be badly formulated and that consideration of it has been impeded by falsely supposing that Platonic Forms were ever intended as an alternative to Aristotelian universals. In fact, the role that Forms are supposed by Plato to fulfill is independent of the function of a universal. I briefly consider the gradual mutation of the problem in the Academy, in Alexander of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Perception of Universals.Marc Gasser-Wingate - 2019 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 27 (3):446-467.
    Aristotle claims that "although we perceive particulars, perception is of universals; for instance of human being, not of Callias-the-human-being" (APo II.19 100a16-b1). I offer an interpretation of this claim and examine its significance in Aristotle's epistemology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intuition, discursive thought, and truth in Aristotle.Paolo Crivelli - 2022 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 31 (4):597-613.
    Chapter Θ10 of Aristotle's Metaphysics is traditionally taken to be about the truth of intuitions, namely episodes of an immediate and sub-propositional grasp of entities. This exegesis however saddles Aristotle with a broken-backed theory of truth because in other passages of his works he claims that truth and falsehood apply only to items of a propositional nature and denies that sub-propositional items can be true or false. An alternative exegesis is preferable which takes Θ10 to be about the truth of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why the Intellect Cannot Have a Bodily Organ: De Anima 3.4.Caleb Cohoe - 2013 - Phronesis 58 (4):347-377.
    I reconstruct Aristotle’s reasons for thinking that the intellect cannot have a bodily organ. I present Aristotle’s account of the aboutness or intentionality of cognitive states, both perceptual and intellectual. On my interpretation, Aristotle’s account is based around the notion of cognitive powers taking on forms in a special preservative way. Based on this account, Aristotle argues that no physical structure could enable a bodily part or combination of bodily parts to produce or determine the full range of forms that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Nous in Aristotle's De Anima.Caleb Murray Cohoe - 2014 - Philosophy Compass 9 (9):594-604.
    I lay out and examine two sharply conflicting interpretations of Aristotle's claims about nous in the De Anima (DA). On the human separability approach, Aristotle is taken to have identified reasons for thinking that the intellect can, in some way, exist on its own. On the naturalist approach, the soul, including intellectual soul, is inseparable from the body of which it is the form. I discuss how proponents of each approach deal with the key texts from the DA, focusing on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Self and self-consciousness: Aristotelian ontology and cartesian duality.Andrea Christofidou - 2009 - Philosophical Investigations 32 (2):134-162.
    The relationship between self-consciousness, Aristotelian ontology, and Cartesian duality is far closer than it has been thought to be. There is no valid inference either from considerations of Aristotle's hylomorphism or from the phenomenological distinction between body and living body, to the undermining of Cartesian dualism. Descartes' conception of the self as both a reasoning and willing being informs his conception of personhood; a person for Descartes is an unanalysable, integrated, self-conscious and autonomous human being. The claims that Descartes introspectively (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Commentary on Miller.Victor Caston - 1999 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 15 (1):214-230.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Aristotle on the Relation of the Intellect to the Body: Commentary on Broadie.Victor Caston - 1996 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 12 (1):177-192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Does the Soul Weave? Reconsidering De Anima 1.4, 408a29-b18.Jason W. Carter - 2018 - Phronesis 63 (1):25-63.
    In De Anima 1.4, Aristotle asks whether the soul can be moved by its own affections. His conclusion—that to say the soul grows angry is like saying that it weaves and builds—has traditionally been read on the assumption that it is false to credit the soul with weaving and building; I argue that Aristotle’s analysis of psychological motions implies his belief that the soul does in fact weave and build.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle on pre-Platonic theories of sense-perception and knowledge.Luis Andrés Bredlow - 2010 - Filosofia Unisinos 11 (3):204-224.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Aristotle's Case for Perceptual Knowledge.Robert Howton - 2017 - Dissertation, University of Toronto
    Sense experience, naïvely conceived, is a way of knowing perceptible properties: the colors, sounds, smells, flavors, and textures in our perceptual environment. So conceived, ordinary experience presents the perceiver with the essential nature of a property like Sky Blue or Middle C, such that how the property appears in experience is identical to how it essentially is. In antiquity, as today, it was controversial whether sense experience could meet the conditions for knowledge implicit in this naïve conception. Aristotle was a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-Consciousness.Joel Smith - 2017 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    -/- Human beings are conscious not only of the world around them but also of themselves: their activities, their bodies, and their mental lives. They are, that is, self-conscious (or, equivalently, self-aware). Self-consciousness can be understood as an awareness of oneself. But a self-conscious subject is not just aware of something that merely happens to be themselves, as one is if one sees an old photograph without realising that it is of oneself. Rather a self-conscious subject is aware of themselves (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Attending to Presence: A Study of John Duns Scotus' Account of Sense Cognition.Amy F. Whitworth - unknown
    This project is guided and motivated by the question concerning the nature of the phantasm as that which mediates between sensation and intellection in John Duns Scotus' account of cognition. Scotus embraces Aristotle's claim that the intellect cannot think without the phantasm. The phantasm is in a corporeal organ, yet the immaterial intellect must act with it to produce an intelligible species. In this project I examine the critical elements of Scotus' cognitive theory in order to understand the nature of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Object of Aristotle’s God’s Νόησις in Metaphysics Λ.9.Sean M. Costello - 2018 - Journal of Greco-Roman Studies 57 (3):49-66.
    In this paper I attempt to discover the object of Aristotle’s God’s νόησις in Metαphysics Λ.9. In Section I, I catalogue existing interpretations and mention the two key concepts of (i) God’s substancehood and (ii) his metaphysical simplicity. In Section II, I explore the first two aporiae of Λ.9 – namely (1) what God’s οὐσία is and (2) what God intelligizes. In Section III, I show how Aristotle solves these aporiae by contending that God’s οὐσία is actually intelligizing, and being (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A noesis como intelecção dos indivisíveis em Aristóteles.Juliana Peixoto - 2010 - Dissertation, Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O nous no "Tratado da alma" de Aristóteles.Juliana Peixoto - 2005 - Dissertation, Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Themistius as a Commentator on Aristotle: Understanding and Appreciating his Conception of Nous Pathetikos and Phantasia.Myrna Gabbe - 2008 - Dionysius 26:73-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations