Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Sculpting the space of actions. Explaining human action by integrating intentions and mechanisms.Machiel Keestra - 2014 - Dissertation, University of Amsterdam
    How can we explain the intentional nature of an expert’s actions, performed without immediate and conscious control, relying instead on automatic cognitive processes? How can we account for the differences and similarities with a novice’s performance of the same actions? Can a naturalist explanation of intentional expert action be in line with a philosophical concept of intentional action? Answering these and related questions in a positive sense, this dissertation develops a three-step argument. Part I considers different methods of explanations in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Précis of The creative mind: Myths and mechanisms.Margaret A. Boden - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):519-531.
    What is creativity? One new idea may be creative, whereas another is merely new: What's the difference? And how is creativity possible? These questions about human creativity can be answered, at least in outline, using computational concepts. There are two broad types of creativity, improbabilist and impossibilist. Improbabilist creativity involves novel combinations of familiar ideas. A deeper type involves METCS: the mapping, exploration, and transformation of conceptual spaces. It is impossibilist, in that ideas may be generated which – with respect (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • A Day in the Life of a Meme.Liane Gabora - 1996 - Philosophica 57 (1):53-90.
    Like the information patterns that evolve through. biological processes, mental representations or memes evolve through adaptive exploration and transformation of an information space through variation, selection, and transmission. However since memes do not contain instructions for their replication our brains do it for them, strategically, guided by a fitness landscape that reflects both internal drives and a worldview that forms through meme assimilation. This paper presents a tentative model for how an individual becomes a meme evolving agent via the emergence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Origins of the Qualitative Aspects of Consciousness: Evolutionary Answers to Chalmers' Hard Problem.Jonathan Y. Tsou - 2012 - In Liz Stillwaggon Swan (ed.), Origins of mind. New York: Springer. pp. 259--269.
    According to David Chalmers, the hard problem of consciousness consists of explaining how and why qualitative experience arises from physical states. Moreover, Chalmers argues that materialist and reductive explanations of mentality are incapable of addressing the hard problem. In this chapter, I suggest that Chalmers’ hard problem can be usefully distinguished into a ‘how question’ and ‘why question,’ and I argue that evolutionary biology has the resources to address the question of why qualitative experience arises from brain states. From this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A Metaphysics of Creativity.Dustin Stokes - 2008 - In Kathleen Stock & Katherine Thomson-Jones (eds.), New waves in aesthetics. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. pp. 105--124.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Self-other organization: Why early life did not evolve through natural selection.Liane Gabora - manuscript
    The improbability of a spontaneously generated self-assembling molecule has suggested that life began with a set of simpler, collectively replicating elements, such as an enclosed autocatalytic set of polymers (or autocell). Since replication occurs without a self-assembly code, acquired characteristics are inherited. Moreover, there is no strict distinction between alive and dead; one can only infer that an autocell was alive if it replicates. These features of early life render natural selection inapplicable to the description of its change-of-state because they (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Creative thought as a non-Darwinian evolutionary process.Dr Liane M. Gabora - 2005 - [Journal (Paginated)] (in Press).
    Selection theory requires multiple, distinct, simultaneously-actualized states. In cognition, each thought or cognitive state changes the 'selection pressure' against which the next is evaluated; they are not simultaneously selected amongst. Creative thought is more a matter of honing in a vague idea through redescribing successive iterations of it from different real or imagined perspectives; in other words, actualizing potential through exposure to different contexts. It has been proven that the mathematical description of contextual change of state introduces a non-Kolmogorovian probability (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophy and Cognitive Sciences: Proceedings of the 16th International Wittgenstein Symposium (Kirchberg Am Wechsel, Austria 1993).Roberto Casati & Barry Smith (eds.) - 1994 - Vienna: Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.
    Online collection of papers by Devitt, Dretske, Guarino, Hochberg, Jackson, Petitot, Searle, Tye, Varzi and other leading thinkers on philosophy and the foundations of cognitive Science. Topics dealt with include: Wittgenstein and Cognitive Science, Content and Object, Logic and Foundations, Language and Linguistics, and Ontology and Mereology.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The cognizer's innards: A psychological and philosophical perspective on the development of thought.Andy Clark & Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 1993 - Mind and Language 8 (4):487-519.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   164 citations  
  • Representation and desire: A philosophical error with consequences for theory-of-mind research.Eric Schwitzgebel - 1999 - Philosophical Psychology 12 (2):157-180.
    This paper distinguishes two conceptions of representation at work in the philosophical literature. On the first, "contentive" conception (found, for example, in Searle and Fodor), something is a representation, roughly, if it has "propositional content". On the second, "indicative" conception (found, for example, in Dretske), representations must not only have content but also have the function of indicating something about the world. Desire is representational on the first view but not on the second. This paper argues that philosophers and psychologists (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Empirical treatments of imagination and creativity.Dustin Stokes - 2024 - In Amy Kind & Julia Langkau (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Imagination and Creativity. Oxford University Press.
    This paper offers a critical survey and analysis of empirical studies on creativity, with emphasis on how imagination plays a role in the creative process. It takes as a foil the romantic view that, given features like novelty, incubation, and insight, we should be skeptical about the prospects for naturalistic explanation of creativity. It rebuts this skepticism by first distinguishing stages or operations in the creative process. It then works through various behavioral and neural studies, and corresponding philosophical theorizing, that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Naturalistic Approaches to Creativity.Dustin Stokes & Elliot Samuel Paul - 2016 - In Wesley Buckwalter & Justin Sytsma (eds.), Blackwell Companion to Experimental Philosophy. Malden, MA: Blackwell. pp. 318–333.
    This chapter offers a brief characterization of creativity, followed by a review of some of the reasons people have been skeptical about the possibility of explaining creativity. It surveys some of the recent work on creativity that is naturalistic in the sense that it presumes creativity is natural, as opposed to magical, occult, or supernatural, and is therefore amenable to scientific inquiry. The chapter divides into two categories. The broader category is empirical philosophy, which draws on empirical research while addressing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Creativity.Elliot Samuel Paul & Dustin Stokes - 2023 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    This entry provides a substantive overview of research and debates concerning creativity in philosophy and related fields. Topics covered include definitions of creativity, whether creativity can be learned, whether it can be explained, attempts to explain creativity in cognitive science, and whether computer programs or AI systems can be creative.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Drawings of Representational Images by Upper Paleolithic Humans and their Absence in Neanderthals Reflect Historical Differences in Hunting Wary Game.Richard G. Coss - 2017 - Evolutionary Studies in Imaginative Culture 1 (2):15-38.
    One characteristic of the transition from the Middle Paleolithic to the Upper Paleolithic in Europe was the emergence of representational charcoal drawings and engravings by Aurignacian and Gravettian artists. European Neanderthals never engaged in representational drawing during the Middle and Early Upper Paleolithic, a property that might reflect less developed visuomotor coordination. This article postulates a causal relationship between an evolved ability of anatomically modern humans to throw spears accurately while hunting and their ability to draw representational images from working (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Children’s reasoning about the efficiency of others’ actions: The development of rational action prediction.Gökhan Gönül & Markus Paulus - 2021 - Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 204 (105035).
    The relative efficiency of an action is a central criterion in action control and can be used to predict others’ behavior. Yet, it is unclear when the ability to predict on and reason about the efficiency of others’ actions develops. In three main and two followup studies, 3- to 6-year-old children (n = 242) were confronted with vignettes in which protagonists could take a short (efficient) path or a long path. Children predicted which path the protagonist would take and why (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Verbal and Figural Creativity in Children With Autism Spectrum Disorder and Typical Development.Anat Kasirer, Esther Adi-Japha & Nira Mashal - 2020 - Frontiers in Psychology 11.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Analogy programs and creativity.Bruce D. Burns - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):535-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computation: Part of the problem of creativity.Merlin Donald - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):537-538.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The historical basis of scientific discovery.Gerd Grasshoff - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):545-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computational creativity: What place for literature?Jörgen Pind - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):547-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity: Metarules and emergent systems.Jonathan Rowe - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):550-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can artificial intelligence explain age changes in literary creativity?Carolyn Adams-Price - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):532-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On doing the impossible.Robert L. Campbell - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):535-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • (1 other version)Common Object Representations for Visual Production and Recognition.Judith E. Fan, Daniel L. K. Yamins & Nicholas B. Turk-Browne - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (8):2670-2698.
    Production and comprehension have long been viewed as inseparable components of language. The study of vision, by contrast, has centered almost exclusively on comprehension. Here we investigate drawing—the most basic form of visual production. How do we convey concepts in visual form, and how does refining this skill, in turn, affect recognition? We developed an online platform for collecting large amounts of drawing and recognition data, and applied a deep convolutional neural network model of visual cortex trained only on natural (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Children's Mental Models of Prenatal Development.Tessa J. P. van Schijndel, Sara E. van Es, Rooske K. Franse, Bianca M. C. W. van Bers & Maartje E. J. Raijmakers - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analogy Lays the Foundation for Two Crucial Aspects of Symbolic Development: Intention and Correspondence.Lei Yuan & David H. Uttal - 2017 - Topics in Cognitive Science 9 (3):738-757.
    We argue that analogical reasoning, particularly Gentner's structure-mapping theory, provides an integrative theoretical framework through which we can better understand the development of symbol use. Analogical reasoning can contribute both to the understanding of others’ intentions and the establishment of correspondences between symbols and their referents, two crucial components of symbolic understanding. We review relevant research on the development of symbolic representations, intentionality, comparison, and similarity, and demonstrate how structure-mapping theory can shed light on several ostensibly disparate findings in the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Imitation, Inspiration, and Creation: Cognitive Process of Creative Drawing by Copying Others' Artworks.Takeshi Okada & Kentaro Ishibashi - 2017 - Cognitive Science 41 (7):1804-1837.
    To investigate the cognitive processes underlying creative inspiration, we tested the extent to which viewing or copying prior examples impacted creative output in art. In Experiment 1, undergraduates made drawings under three conditions: copying an artist's drawing, then producing an original drawing; producing an original drawing without having seen another's work; and copying another artist's work, then reproducing that artist's style independently. We discovered that through copying unfamiliar abstract drawings, participants were able to produce creative drawings qualitatively different from the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Creativity, combination, and cognition.Terry Dartnall - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):537-537.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Young children show representational flexibility when interpreting drawings.Melissa L. Allen, Erika Nurmsoo & Norman Freeman - 2016 - Cognition 147 (C):21-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The birth of an idea.Liane M. Gabora - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):543-543.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)How Language Programs the Mind.Gary Lupyan & Benjamin Bergen - 2016 - Topics in Cognitive Science 8 (1):408-424.
    Many animals can be trained to perform novel tasks. People, too, can be trained, but sometime in early childhood people transition from being trainable to something qualitatively more powerful—being programmable. We argue that such programmability constitutes a leap in the way that organisms learn, interact, and transmit knowledge, and that what facilitates or enables this programmability is the learning and use of language. We then examine how language programs the mind and argue that it does so through the manipulation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  • Imagination and Creativity.Dustin Stokes - 2016 - In Amy Kind (ed.), The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Imagination. New York: Routledge.
    This paper surveys historical and recent philosophical discussions of the relations between imagination and creativity. In the first two sections, it covers two insufficiently studied analyses of the creative imagination, that of Kant and Sartre, respectively. The next section discusses imagination and its role in scientific discovery, with particular emphasis on the writings of Michael Polanyi, and on thought experiments and experimental design. The final section offers a brief discussion of some very recent work done on conceptual relations between imagination (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Creativity: Myths? Mechanisms.Michel Treisman - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):554-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What about everyday creativity?Nick V. Flor - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):540-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Can computers be creative, or even disappointed?Robert J. Sternberg - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):553-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The time course of implicit and explicit concept learning.Eleni Ziori & Zoltán Dienes - 2012 - Consciousness and Cognition 21 (1):204-216.
    The present experiment investigated the development of implicit and explicit knowledge during concept learning. According to Cleeremans and Jiménez , the content of a representation can be conscious only when the representation is of a sufficiently good quality; on this theory, increasing explicit and decreasing implicit knowledge might be expected with training. The view that implicit knowledge arises from compilation of explicit knowledge makes the opposite prediction. The present research tested these possibilities using subjective measures based on confidence ratings. One (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Creative thinking presupposes the capacity for thought.James H. Fetzer - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Respecting the phenomenology of human creativity.Victor A. Shames & John F. Kihlstrom - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Creativity theory: Detail and testability.K. J. Gilhooly - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):544-545.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Imagery and creativity.Klaus Rehkämper - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):550-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The creative mind versus the creative computer.Robert W. Weisberg - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):555-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Review of Mohan Matthen-Seeing, Doing, and Knowing: A Philosophical Theory of Sense Perception. [REVIEW]Dustin Stokes - 2006 - British Journal of Aesthetics 46 (3):323-325.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Visualizing Thought.Barbara Tversky - 2011 - Topics in Cognitive Science 3 (3):499-535.
    Depictive expressions of thought predate written language by thousands of years. They have evolved in communities through a kind of informal user testing that has refined them. Analyzing common visual communications reveals consistencies that illuminate how people think as well as guide design; the process can be brought into the laboratory and accelerated. Like language, visual communications abstract and schematize; unlike language, they use properties of the page (e.g., proximity and place: center, horizontal/up–down, vertical/left–right) and the marks on it (e.g., (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   39 citations  
  • Machine discoverers: Transforming the spaces they explore.Jan M. Zytkow - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):557-558.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What is the difference between real creativity and mere novelty?Alan Bundy - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):533-534.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Creativity is in the mind of the creator.Ashwin Ram, Eric Domeshek, Linda Wills, Nancy Nersessian & Janet Kolodner - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):549-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The creative mind.Scott R. Turner - 1995 - Artificial Intelligence 79 (1):145-159.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Generating and Understanding Jokes by Five- And Nine-Year-Olds as an Expression of Theory of Mind.Marta Białecka-Pikul & Maria Kielar-Turska - 2009 - Polish Psychological Bulletin 40 (4):163-169.
    Generating and Understanding Jokes by Five- And Nine-Year-Olds as an Expression of Theory of Mind The main aim of the presented research is to describe children's ability to generate and understand humorous stories and pictures drawn by their peers and older or younger children. From the perspective of research on children's theories of mind, we assume that in middle childhood we will observe a transition from the basic, copy theory of mind to the interpretative one. We examined 60 five- and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)How Language Programs the Mind.Gary Lupyan & Benjamin Bergen - 2016 - Topics in Cognitive Science 8 (2):408-424.
    Many animals can be trained to perform novel tasks. People, too, can be trained, but sometime in early childhood people transition from being trainable to something qualitatively more powerful—being programmable. We argue that such programmability constitutes a leap in the way that organisms learn, interact, and transmit knowledge, and that what facilitates or enables this programmability is the learning and use of language. We then examine how language programs the mind and argue that it does so through the manipulation of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • The generative-rules definition of creativity.Joseph O'Rourke - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):547-547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark