Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The Mill-Whewell Debate: Much Ado about Induction.Laura J. Snyder - 1997 - Perspectives on Science 5 (2):159-198.
    This article examines the nineteenth-century debate about scientific method between John Stuart Mill and William Whewell. Contrary to standard interpretations (given, for example, by Achinstein, Buchdahl, Butts, and Laudan), I argue that their debate was not over whether to endorse an inductive methodology but rather over the nature of inductive reasoning in science and the types of conclusions yielded by it. Whewell endorses, while Mill rejects, a type of inductive reasoning in which inference is employed to find a property or (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Scientific realism and the stratagema de divide et impera.Timothy D. Lyons - 2006 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57 (3):537-560.
    In response to historical challenges, advocates of a sophisticated variant of scientific realism emphasize that theoretical systems can be divided into numerous constituents. Setting aside any epistemic commitment to the systems themselves, they maintain that we can justifiably believe those specific constituents that are deployed in key successful predictions. Stathis Psillos articulates an explicit criterion for discerning exactly which theoretical constituents qualify. I critique Psillos's criterion in detail. I then test the more general deployment realist intuition against a set of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   77 citations  
  • Rationality in the discovery of empirical laws.Erik Weber - 1999 - Foundations of Science 4 (3):357-370.
    In this paper I argue against the traditional viewthat in discovery processes there is no place forrational decisions. First I argue that some historicalprocesses in which an empirical law was developed,were rational. Second, I identify some of themethodological rules that we can follow in order to berational when constructing an empirical law. Finally,I argue that people who deny that scientific discoverycan be rational do not understand the nature ofmethodological rules.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Discoverers' induction.Laura J. Snyder - 1997 - Philosophy of Science 64 (4):580-604.
    In this paper I demonstrate that, contrary to the standard interpretations, William Whewell's view of scientific method is neither that of the hypothetico-deductivist nor that of the retroductivist. Rather, he offers a unique inductive methodology, which he calls "discoverers' induction." After explicating this methodology, I show that Kepler's discovery of his first law of planetary motion conforms to it, as Whewell claims it does. In explaining Whewell's famous phrase about "happy guesses" in science, I suggest that Whewell intended a distinction (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Kepler Then and Now.Owen Gingerich - 2002 - Perspectives on Science 10 (2):228-240.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Steering Problem Solving between Cliff Incoherence and Cliff Solitude.Joke Meheus & Diderik Batens - 1996 - Philosophica 58 (2).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Putting presuppositions on the table: Why the foundations matter.Paul R. Boehlke, Laurie M. Knapp & Rachel L. Kolander - 2006 - Zygon 41 (2):415-426.
    Abstract. Over time scientists have developed an effective investigative process that includes the acceptance of particular basic presuppositions, methods, content, and theories. T he deeply held presuppositions are the philosophical foundation of scientific thought and do much to define the field’s worldview. These fundamental assumptions can be esoteric for many and can become a source of conflict when they are not commonly shared with other points of view. Such presuppositions affect the observations, the conclusions drawn, and the positions taken. Furthermore, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Early Numerical Analysis in Kepler's New Astronomy.Steinar Thorvaldsen - 2010 - Science in Context 23 (1):39-63.
    ArgumentJohannes Kepler published hisAstronomia novain 1609, based upon a huge amount of computations. The aim of this paper is to show that Kepler's new astronomy was grounded on methods from numerical analysis. In his research he applied and improved methods that required iterative calculations, and he developed precompiled mathematical tables to solve the problems, including a transcendental equation. Kepler was aware of the shortcomings of his novel methods, and called for a new Apollonius to offer a formal mathematical deduction. He (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Kepler's Optical Part of Astronomy (1604): Introducing the Ecliptic Instrument.Giora Hon & Yaakov Zik - 2009 - Perspectives on Science 17 (3):307-345.
    The year 2009 marks the 400th anniversary of the publication of one of the most revolutionary scientific texts ever written. In this book, appropriately entitled, Astronomia nova, Johannes Kepler developed an astronomical theory which departs fundamentally from the systems of Ptolemy and Copernicus. One of the great innovations of this theory is its dependence on the science of optics. The declared goal of Kepler in his earlier publication, Paralipomena to Witelo whereby The Optical Part of Astronomy is Treated , was (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Carl Prantl y la historia de la lógica de la investigación científica.Daniel Antonio Di Liscia & Javier Legris - 2016 - Scientiae Studia 14 (2):527.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark