Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A finitization of Littlewood's Tauberian theorem and an application in Tauberian remainder theory.Thomas Powell - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (4):103231.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On Extracting Variable Herbrand Disjunctions.Andrei Sipoş - 2022 - Studia Logica 110 (4):1115-1134.
    Some quantitative results obtained by proof mining take the form of Herbrand disjunctions that may depend on additional parameters. We attempt to elucidate this fact through an extension to first-order arithmetic of the proof of Herbrand’s theorem due to Gerhardy and Kohlenbach which uses the functional interpretation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The collapse of the Hilbert program: A variation on the gödelian theme.Saul A. Kripke - 2022 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 28 (3):413-426.
    The Hilbert program was actually a specific approach for proving consistency, a kind of constructive model theory. Quantifiers were supposed to be replaced by ε-terms. εxA(x) was supposed to denote a witness to ∃xA(x), or something arbitrary if there is none. The Hilbertians claimed that in any proof in a number-theoretic system S, each ε-term can be replaced by a numeral, making each line provable and true. This implies that S must not only be consistent, but also 1-consistent. Here we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mathematical Incompleteness Results in First-Order Peano Arithmetic: A Revisionist View of the Early History.Saul A. Kripke - 2021 - History and Philosophy of Logic 43 (2):175-182.
    In the Handbook of Mathematical Logic, the Paris-Harrington variant of Ramsey's theorem is celebrated as the first result of a long ‘search’ for a purely mathematical incompleteness result in first-order Peano arithmetic. This paper questions the existence of any such search and the status of the Paris-Harrington result as the first mathematical incompleteness result. In fact, I argue that Gentzen gave the first such result, and that it was restated by Goodstein in a number-theoretic form.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reading Gentzen's Three Consistency Proofs Uniformly.Ryota Akiyoshi & Yuta Takahashi - 2013 - Journal of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science 41 (1):1-22.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Hilbert’s Program.Richard Zach - 2014 - In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, CA: The Metaphysics Research Lab.
    In the early 1920s, the German mathematician David Hilbert (1862–1943) put forward a new proposal for the foundation of classical mathematics which has come to be known as Hilbert's Program. It calls for a formalization of all of mathematics in axiomatic form, together with a proof that this axiomatization of mathematics is consistent. The consistency proof itself was to be carried out using only what Hilbert called “finitary” methods. The special epistemological character of finitary reasoning then yields the required justification (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   28 citations  
  • Herbrand analyses.Wilfried Sieg - 1991 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 30 (5-6):409-441.
    Herbrand's Theorem, in the form of $$\underset{\raise0.3em\hbox{$\smash{\scriptscriptstyle-}$}}{\exists } $$ -inversion lemmata for finitary and infinitary sequent calculi, is the crucial tool for the determination of the provably total function(al)s of a variety of theories. The theories are (second order extensions of) fragments of classical arithmetic; the classes of provably total functions include the elements of the Polynomial Hierarchy, the Grzegorczyk Hierarchy, and the extended Grzegorczyk Hierarchy $\mathfrak{E}^\alpha $ , α < ε0. A subsidiary aim of the paper is to show (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • The Gödelian Inferences.Curtis Franks - 2009 - History and Philosophy of Logic 30 (3):241-256.
    I attribute an 'intensional reading' of the second incompleteness theorem to its author, Kurt G del. My argument builds partially on an analysis of intensional and extensional conceptions of meta-mathematics and partially on the context in which G del drew two familiar inferences from his theorem. Those inferences, and in particular the way that they appear in G del's writing, are so dubious on the extensional conception that one must doubt that G del could have understood his theorem extensionally. However, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gödel's functional interpretation and its use in current mathematics.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (2):223–267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A most artistic package of a jumble of ideas.Fernando Ferreira - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (2):205–222.
    In the course of ten short sections, we comment on Gödel's seminal dialectica paper of fifty years ago and its aftermath. We start by suggesting that Gödel's use of functionals of finite type is yet another instance of the realistic attitude of Gödel towards mathematics, in tune with his defense of the postulation of ever increasing higher types in foundational studies. We also make some observations concerning Gödel's recasting of intuitionistic arithmetic via the dialectica interpretation, discuss the extra principles that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Godel's unpublished papers on foundations of mathematics.W. W. Tatt - 2001 - Philosophia Mathematica 9 (1):87-126.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Gödel's reformulation of Gentzen's first consistency proof for arithmetic: The no-counterexample interpretation.W. W. Tait - 2005 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2):225-238.
    The last section of “Lecture at Zilsel’s” [9, §4] contains an interesting but quite condensed discussion of Gentzen’s first version of his consistency proof for P A [8], reformulating it as what has come to be called the no-counterexample interpretation. I will describe Gentzen’s result (in game-theoretic terms), fill in the details (with some corrections) of Godel's reformulation, and discuss the relation between the two proofs.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Platonism and mathematical intuition in Kurt gödel's thought.Charles Parsons - 1995 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 1 (1):44-74.
    The best known and most widely discussed aspect of Kurt Gödel's philosophy of mathematics is undoubtedly his robust realism or platonism about mathematical objects and mathematical knowledge. This has scandalized many philosophers but probably has done so less in recent years than earlier. Bertrand Russell's report in his autobiography of one or more encounters with Gödel is well known:Gödel turned out to be an unadulterated Platonist, and apparently believed that an eternal “not” was laid up in heaven, where virtuous logicians (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Hao Wang as philosopher and interpreter of gödel.Charles Parsons - 1998 - Philosophia Mathematica 6 (1):3-24.
    The paper undertakes to characterize Hao Wang's style, convictions, and method as a philosopher, centering on his most important philosophical work From Mathematics to Philosophy, 1974. The descriptive character of Wang's characteristic method is emphasized. Some specific achievements are discussed: his analyses of the concept of set, his discussion, in connection with setting forth Gödel's views, of minds and machines, and his concept of ‘analytic empiricism’ used to criticize Carnap and Quine. Wang's work as interpreter of Gödel's thought and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Number theory and elementary arithmetic.Jeremy Avigad - 2003 - Philosophia Mathematica 11 (3):257-284.
    is a fragment of first-order aritlimetic so weak that it cannot prove the totality of an iterated exponential fimction. Surprisingly, however, the theory is remarkably robust. I will discuss formal results that show that many theorems of number theory and combinatorics are derivable in elementary arithmetic, and try to place these results in a broader philosophical context.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Alternating (In)Dependence-Friendly Logic.Dylan Bellier, Massimo Benerecetti, Dario Della Monica & Fabio Mogavero - 2023 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 174 (10):103315.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Hilbert's 'Verunglückter Beweis', the first epsilon theorem, and consistency proofs.Richard Zach - 2004 - History and Philosophy of Logic 25 (2):79-94.
    In the 1920s, Ackermann and von Neumann, in pursuit of Hilbert's programme, were working on consistency proofs for arithmetical systems. One proposed method of giving such proofs is Hilbert's epsilon-substitution method. There was, however, a second approach which was not reflected in the publications of the Hilbert school in the 1920s, and which is a direct precursor of Hilbert's first epsilon theorem and a certain "general consistency result" due to Bernays. An analysis of the form of this so-called "failed proof" (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Predicative functionals and an interpretation of ⌢ID.Jeremy Avigad - 1998 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 92 (1):1-34.
    In 1958 Gödel published his Dialectica interpretation, which reduces classical arithmetic to a quantifier-free theory T axiomatizing the primitive recursive functionals of finite type. Here we extend Gödel's T to theories Pn of “predicative” functionals, which are defined using Martin-Löf's universes of transfinite types. We then extend Gödel's interpretation to the theories of arithmetic inductive definitions IDn, so that each IDn is interpreted in the corresponding Pn. Since the strengths of the theories IDn are cofinal in the ordinal Γ0, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Odel's dialectica interpretation and its two-way stretch.Solomon Feferman - manuscript
    In 1958, G¨ odel published in the journal Dialectica an interpretation of intuitionistic number theory in a quantifier-free theory of functionals of finite type; this subsequently came to be known as G¨ odel’s functional or Dialectica interpretation. The article itself was written in German for an issue of that journal in honor of Paul Bernays’ 70th birthday. In 1965, Bernays told G¨.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The metamathematics of ergodic theory.Jeremy Avigad - 2009 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 (2-3):64-76.
    The metamathematical tradition, tracing back to Hilbert, employs syntactic modeling to study the methods of contemporary mathematics. A central goal has been, in particular, to explore the extent to which infinitary methods can be understood in computational or otherwise explicit terms. Ergodic theory provides rich opportunities for such analysis. Although the field has its origins in seventeenth century dynamics and nineteenth century statistical mechanics, it employs infinitary, nonconstructive, and structural methods that are characteristically modern. At the same time, computational concerns (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • A Most Artistic Package of a Jumble of Ideas.Fernando Ferreira - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (2):205-222.
    In the course of ten short sections, we comment on Gödel's seminal dialectica paper of fifty years ago and its aftermath. We start by suggesting that Gödel's use of functionals of finite type is yet another instance of the realistic attitude of Gödel towards mathematics, in tune with his defense of the postulation of ever increasing higher types in foundational studies. We also make some observations concerning Gödel's recasting of intuitionistic arithmetic via the dialectica interpretation, discuss the extra principles that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Critical study of Michael Potter’s Reason’s Nearest Kin. [REVIEW]Richard Zach - 2005 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (4):503-513.
    Critical study of Michael Potter, Reason's Nearest Kin. Philosophies of Arithmetic from Kant to Carnap. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2000. x + 305 pages.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • William Tait. The provenance of pure reason. Essays on the philosophy of mathematics and on its history.Charles Parsons - 2009 - Philosophia Mathematica 17 (2):220-247.
    William Tait's standing in the philosophy of mathematics hardly needs to be argued for; for this reason the appearance of this collection is especially welcome. As noted in his Preface, the essays in this book ‘span the years 1981–2002’. The years given are evidently those of publication. One essay was not previously published in its present form, but it is a reworking of papers published during that period. The Introduction, one appendix, and some notes are new. Many of the essays (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Second thoughts around some of göde's writings:.G. Kreisel - 1998 - Synthese 114 (1):99-160.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Gödel's Functional Interpretation and its Use in Current Mathematics.Ulrich Kohlenbach - 2008 - Dialectica 62 (2):223-267.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Informal versus formal mathematics.Francisco Antonio Doria - 2007 - Synthese 154 (3):401-415.
    We discuss Kunen’s algorithmic implementation of a proof for the Paris–Harrington theorem, and the author’s and da Costa’s proposed “exotic” formulation for the P = NP hypothesis. Out of those two examples we ponder the relation between mathematics within an axiomatic framework, and intuitive or informal mathematics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark