Switch to: References

Citations of:

Autobiography

Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia 15 (4):436-437 (1959)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Social Evolution, Progress and Teleology in Spencer's Synthetic Philosophy and Freudian Psychoanalysis.L. Nascimento - forthcoming - History of the Human Sciences.
    This article aims to compare notions of progress and evolution in the social theories of Freud and Spencer. It argues 1) that the two authors had similarly complex theories that contained mixed elements of positivism and teleology; 2) In its positivist elements, both authors made use of unified natural laws and, in its teleological aspect, they made use of notions of final cause in that progress and the evolution of civilization was understood as a linear path of progressive development with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Harm Principle and Recognition Theory: On the Complementarity between Linklater, Honneth and the Project of Emancipation.Shannon Brincat - 2013 - Critical Horizons 14 (2):225--256.
    This paper explores potential points of synthesis between two leading theorists in Critical Theory and Critical International Relations Theory, Axel Honneth and Andrew Linklater. Whereas Linklater's recent work on the harm principle has turned away from the critical social theory of the Frankfurt School in favour of Norbert Elias and process sociology, the paper observes a fundamental complementarity between harm and the precepts of recognition theory that can bridge these otherwise disparate approaches to emancipation. The paper begins with a brief (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The importance of ideals in education.Doret J. De Ruyter - 2003 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 37 (3):467–482.
    The article argues that it is important to offer children ideals. Ideals are defined as imagined excellences, which are so desirable that people will try to actualise them. These characteristics show the importance of ideals for people: ideals give direction and meaning to their lives. The motivating power of ideals can, however, also lead to fanaticism. Education should therefore involve several worthy ideals that children can commit themselves to as well as critical reflection on the ways in which people are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Higher and Lower Pleasures Revisited: Evidence from Neuroscience.Roger Crisp & Morten Kringelbach - 2017 - Neuroethics 11 (2):211-215.
    This paper discusses J.S. Mill’s distinction between higher and lower pleasures, and suggests that recent neuroscientific evidence counts against it.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Between Autonomy and State Regulation: J.S. Mill's Elastic Paternalism.Raphael Cohen-Almagor - 2012 - Philosophy 87 (4):557-582.
    This paper analyses J.S. Mill's theory on the relationships between individual autonomy and State powers. It will be argued that there is a significant discrepancy between Mill's general liberal statements aimed to secure individual largest possible autonomy and the specific examples which provide the government with quite wide latitude for interference in the public and private spheres. The paper outlines the boundaries of government interference in the Millian theory. Subsequently it describes Mill's elastic paternalism designed to prevent people from inflicting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Utilitarianism in media ethics and its discontents.Clifford G. Christians - 2007 - Journal of Mass Media Ethics 22 (2-3):113 – 131.
    Utilitarianism has dominated media ethics for a century. For Mill, individual autonomy and neutrality are the foundations of his On Liberty and System of Logic, as well as his Utilitarianism. These concepts fit naturally with media ethics theory and professional practice in a democratic society. However, the weaknesses in utilitarianism articulated by Ross and others direct us at this stage to a dialogic ethics of duty instead. Habermas's discourse ethics, feminist ethics, and communitarian ethics are examples of duty ethics rooted (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • AI chatbots and liberal education.William Chan - forthcoming - AI and Society:1-3.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Decision making in compromise situations: guidelines based on J. S. Mill's doctrine of political half‐measures.Rafael Cejudo - 2014 - Business Ethics: A European Review 23 (4):364-374.
    The purpose of this article is to offer guidelines to deal with hard choices, specifically in situations where some compromise among opposing values is inescapable. The guidelines are intended to help ethicists and practitioners to delineate different alternatives and to dismiss some of them as morally unacceptable. This article explores the view that compromises arise from negotiations but from ethical predicaments as well. For this reason, I distinguish between strategic and moral compromises. Both managers and employees are individual moral agents (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The creation of equals.Stephen Burwood - 2009 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 43 (4):485-506.
    Karl Jaspers argued that academics must be prepared to accept, perhaps even to welcome, the fact that most students 'will learn next to nothing' from a university education. In this paper I shall argue that, while Jaspers' model is unpersuasive as an ideal and inaccurate as a description, there is an uncomfortable truth lurking behind his forthright but gloomy conclusion; viz., that university teaching pays little direct attention to the needs of the student in the wider world (i.e. to the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The Church, the State, and Vaccine Policy.Saad B. Omer, Douglas J. Opel, Tyler Tate & Robert A. Bednarczyk - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (4):50-52.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Philosophical autobiography.Julian Baggini - 2002 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 45 (3):295 – 312.
    An examination of the genre of philosophical autobiography sheds light on the role of personal judgment alongside objective rationality in philosophy. Building on Monk's conception of philosophical biography, philosophical autobiography can be seen as any autobiography that reveals some interplay between life and thought. It is argued that almost all autobiographies by philosophers are philosophical because the recounting of one's own life is almost invariably a form of extended speech act of self-revelation. When a philosopher is the autobiographer, this self-revelation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Mill's Poet–Philosopher, and the Instrumental-Social Importance of Poetry for Moral Sentiments.Andrew Gustafson - 2009 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 17 (4):821-847.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Ethics of Conceptualization: A Needs-Based Approach.Matthieu Queloz - forthcoming - Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Philosophy strives to give us a firmer hold on our concepts. But what about their hold on us? Why place ourselves under the sway of a concept and grant it the authority to shape our thought and conduct? Another conceptualization would carry different implications. What makes one way of thinking better than another? This book develops a framework for concept appraisal. Its guiding idea is that to question the authority of concepts is to ask for reasons of a special kind: (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Hedonism.Chris Heathwood - 2013 - In Hugh LaFollette (ed.), The International Encyclopedia of Ethics. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell.
    An encyclopedia entry on hedonistic theories of value and welfare -- the view, roughly, that pleasure is the good.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Eclipse of Value-Free Economics. The concept of multiple self versus homo economicus.Aleksander Ostapiuk - 2020 - Wrocław, Polska: Publishing House of Wroclaw University of Economics and Business.
    The books’ goal is to answer the question: Do the weaknesses of value-free economics imply the need for a paradigm shift? The author synthesizes criticisms from different perspectives (descriptive and methodological). Special attention is paid to choices over time, because in this area value-free economics has the most problems. In that context, the enriched concept of multiple self is proposed and investigated. However, it is not enough to present the criticisms towards value-free economics. For scientists, a bad paradigm is better (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Thinking About Contradictions: The Imaginary Logic of Nikolai Aleksandrovich Vasil’Ev.Venanzio Raspa - 2017 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    This volume examines the entire logical and philosophical production of Nikolai A. Vasil’ev, studying his life and activities as a historian and man of letters. Readers will gain a comprehensive understanding of this influential Russian logician, philosopher, psychologist, and poet. The author frames Vasil’ev’s work within its historical and cultural context. He takes into consideration both the situation of logic in Russia and the state of logic in Western Europe, from the end of the 19th century to the beginning of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • John Stuart Mill and the practice of colonial rule in India.David Williams - 2021 - Journal of International Political Theory 17 (3):412-428.
    John Stuart Mill’s justification for British rule in India is well known. Less well known and discussed are Mill’s extensive writings on the practice of British rule in India. A close engagement with Mill’s writings on this issue shows Mill was a much more uncertain and anxious imperialist than he is often presented to be. Mill was acutely aware of the difficulties presented by the imperial context in India, he identified a number of very demanding conditions that would have to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Liberty of the Liberty Principle.Robert Westmoreland - 2020 - Res Publica 26 (3):337-355.
    Mill’s Liberty Principle aims to protect ‘social’ freedom, which is traditionally understood as negative freedom. I argue that Mill’s conception of social freedom does not comfortably fit even a moralized conception of negative freedom, and that individuality, an ideal fundamental to On Liberty, is a robustly positive type of freedom. This raises the question of whether protecting social freedom involves an egalitarian, progressive state that ambitiously strives to create the social conditions of individuality. I consider the case for an affirmative (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Cultivating Virtue.Jonathan Webber - 2013 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 72:239-259.
    Ought you to cultivate your own virtue? Various philosophers have argued that there is something suspect about directing one's ethical attention towards oneself in this way. These arguments can be divided between those that deem aiming at virtue for its own sake to be narcissistic and those that consider aiming at virtue for the sake of good behaviour to involve a kind of doublethink. Underlying them all is the assumption that epistemic access to one's own character requires an external point (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Autobiography: St Augustine and John Stuart Mill.Martin Warner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 16:189-210.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophical Autobiography: St Augustine and John Stuart Mill.Martin Warner - 1983 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 16:189-210.
    Many classic philosophical debates converge on the twin questions ‘What is man?’ and ‘What is his place in nature?’, in the sense that taking up a position in those debates normally commits one to a certain range of answers to these questions. Such answers typically lie near the centre of one's web of belief, deeply entrenched in the structure of one's concepts, and thus remain remarkably resistant to the standard techniques of confirmation and refutation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • French radicalism through the eyes of John Stuart Mill.Georgios Varouxakis - 2004 - History of European Ideas 30 (4):433-461.
    The paper attempts to highlight some under-researched aspects of the interaction between British and French radical political thinkers and activists during the period between the July Revolution of 1830 in France and the early years of the Third Republic. It focuses in particular on the decisive impact that the aftermath of the July Revolution of 1830 had for the perception of French politics by the most Francophile British radical, John Stuart Mill. In this context, Mill's astonishingly dense coverage of French (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The absolutism problem in On Liberty.Piers Norris Turner - 2013 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43 (3):322-340.
    Mill argues that, apart from the principle of utility, his utilitarianism is incompatible with absolutes. Yet in On Liberty he introduces an exceptionless anti-paternalism principle—his liberty principle. In this paper I address ‘the absolutism problem,’ that is, whether Mill's utilitarianism can accommodate an exceptionless principle. Mill's absolute claim is not a mere bit of rhetoric. But the four main solutions to the absolutism problem are also not supported by the relevant texts. I defend a fifth solution—the competence view—that turns on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Meaning and morality in boxing.Michael-John Turp - forthcoming - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy:1-15.
    While sport is often pursued more for reasons of meaning than morality, philosophers have had far less to say about the former. How are the ends of sport related to meaning and morality? I address the question through the case study of boxing. One reason for this approach is that the moral status of boxing is contested, which makes it an interesting candidate for immoral, meaningful activity. Drawing on Wolf’s hybrid account of meaning in life, I argue that boxing can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Perfection of the Teacher Through the Pursuit of Happiness: Cavell’s Reading of J. S. Mill.Mitsutoshi Takayanagi - 2015 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 35 (1):17-28.
    Drawing upon Nel Noddings’ contention that, if children are to be happy in schools, their teachers should also be happy, this paper tries to explore a way in which the obviously intimate but seemingly conflicting connections between students’ and teachers’ happiness can be understood from the viewpoint of Stanley Cavell’s reading of J. S. Mill. Mill’s conceptions of desire and pleasure are examined as a means of liberating the above connection from existing prioritization: that is, teachers’ or students’ happiness comes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The subversion of Mill and the ultimate aim of nursing.Paul C. Snelling - 2018 - Nursing Philosophy 19 (1):e12201.
    This is lightly edited and referenced version of a presentation given at the 20th International Philosophy of Nursing conference in Quebec on 23rd August 2016. Philosophical texts are not given the same prominence in nurse education as their more valued younger sibling, primary research evidence, but they can influence practice through guidelines, codes and espoused values. John Stuart Mill’s harm principle, found in On Liberty, is not a universal law, and only a thoroughgoing libertarian would defend it as such, though (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The long slide to happiness.Richard Smith - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 42 (3-4):559-573.
    The recent wave of interest in 'teaching happiness' is beset by problems. It consists of many different emphases and approaches, many of which are inconsistent with each other. If happiness is understood as essentially a matter of 'feeling good', then it is difficult to account for the fact that we want and value all sorts of things that do not make us particularly happy. In education and in life more broadly we value a wider diversity of goods. Such criticisms are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Long Slide to Happiness.Richard Smith - 2008 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 42 (3-4):559-573.
    The recent wave of interest in ‘teaching happiness’ is beset by problems. It consists of many different emphases and approaches, many of which are inconsistent with each other. If happiness is understood as essentially a matter of ‘feeling good’, then it is difficult to account for the fact that we want and value all sorts of things that do not make us particularly happy. In education and in life more broadly we value a wider diversity of goods. Such criticisms are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Special cases, composition of causes, and the complexity of nature.Sheldon Smith - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (1):80-96.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • ‘Lost, Enfeebled, and Deprived of Its Vital Effect’: Mill’s Exaggerated View of the Relation Between Conflict and Vitality.Robert Mark Simpson - 2021 - Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 95 (1):97-114.
    Mill thinks our attitudes should be held in a way that’s active and ‘alive’. He believes attitudes that lack these qualities—those held dogmatically, or in unreflective conformity—are inimical to our well-being. This claim then serves as a premiss in his argument for overarching principles of liberty. He argues that attitudinal vitality, in the relevant sense, relies upon people experiencing attitudinal conflict, and that this necessitates a prioritization of personal liberties. I argue that, pace Mill, contestation isn’t required for attitudinal vitality. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Altruism as a thick concept.Michael Schefczyk & Mark Peacock - 2010 - Economics and Philosophy 26 (2):165-187.
    In this paper, we examine different forms of altruism. We commence by analysing the definition and, after clarifying its conditions for altruism, we argue that it is not in with everyday linguistic usage of the term. We therefore consider a definition, which we likewise refine, and argue that it better reflects ordinary language use. Both behavioural and psychological approaches define altruism descriptively and thus fail to capture an important aspect of altruism, namely its normative component. Altruism, we argue, is a, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Malthus and Utilitarianism with Special Reference to the Essay on Population.Samuel Hollander - 1989 - Utilitas 1 (2):170.
    Was Malthus a ‘Utilitarian’? This apparently simple-minded question is justified by on-going debate in the secondary literature. For example, in his study, The Classical Economists, D. P. O'Brien maintains that ‘only the two Mills, apart from Bentham himself, were really Utilitarians’. Against this we have the view of Lord Robbins that ‘We get the picture badly out of focus if we conceive that reliance on the principle of utility was confined to Bentham and his immediate circle.’ In this paper we (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Positive Psychology: Looking Back and Looking Forward.Carol D. Ryff - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Envisioning the future of positive psychology requires looking at its past. To that end, I first review prior critiques of PP to underscore that certain early problems have persisted over time. I then selectively examine recent research to illustrate progress in certain areas as well as draw attention to recurrent problems. Key among them is promulgation of poorly constructed measures of well-being and reliance on homogeneous, privileged research samples. Another concern is the commercialization of PP, which points to the need (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Early J.S. Mill on Marriage and Divorce.Janelle Pötzsch - 2021 - Symposion. Theoretical and Applied Inquiries in Philosophy and Social Sciences 8 (2):175-185.
    Janelle Pötzsch ABSTRACT: This paper discusses Mill’s early essay on marriage and divorce and gives two possible sources of influence for it: Plato’s arguments on the appropriate scope of the law in book IV of his Republic and Unitarian ideas on motherhood. It demonstrates that Plato’s Republic and Mill’s essay both emphasize the crucial ….
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conflicto y libertad en la teoría política de Nicolás Maquiavelo y John Stuart Mill.María Pollitzer - 2015 - Foro Interno. Anuario de Teoría Política 15:69-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Stuart Mills liberaler Marktsozialismus: bisheriges Scheitern und bleibende Relevanz.Christian Neuhäuser - 2018 - Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 66 (3):295-320.
    John Stuart Mill had strong sympathies with a liberal form of market socialism based on worker-owned and worker-managed firms. He thought that only very few government interventions were needed to trigger a peaceful and spontaneous transition to such an economic system. This article recapitulates his thesis and argument by focusing on his major workPrinciples of Political Economy, which is rather neglected by philosophers, especially in the German-speaking world. I will argue that Mill was too optimistic in his hope for a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Fleeming Jenkin and The Origin of Species: a reassessment.Susan W. Morris - 1994 - British Journal for the History of Science 27 (3):313-343.
    Early in June of 1867, Charles Darwin turned back the cover of his copy of the respected quarterlyNorth British Review, to find on its opening pages a lengthy essay attacking his theory of natural selection. As with the vast majority of articles in the Victorian periodicals, the review was anonymous, prompting immediate speculation in Darwin's circle as to the author's identity. It was to be about a year-and-a-half before Darwin would learn that the engineer Fleeming Jenkin had written the essay. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Genetic intervention and the parent-child relationship.Terrance McConnell - 2010 - Genomics, Society and Policy 6 (3):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Importance of Trust in the Vaccine Safety Enterprise.Thomas May - 2017 - American Journal of Bioethics 17 (4):48-50.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Return of James Mill.Mariangela Ripoli - 1998 - Utilitas 10 (1):105-.
    This paper argues that James Mill is worthy of greater study than he now receives. It outlines the course of scholarship on James Mill, and considers various hypotheses to explain the decline of interest in his writings. Two examples, in education and penal theory, are presented of cases in which James Mill's views differed significantly from Bentham's, and anticipated those of John Stuart Mill.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The paradox of philosophy for children and how to resolve it.Maria Kasmirli - 2020 - Childhood and Philosophy 16 (36):01-24.
    There is a paradox in the idea of philosophy for children. Good teaching starts from the concrete and particular, and it engages with each student’s individual interests, beliefs, and experiences. Preadolescents find this approach more natural than a more impersonal one and respond better to it. But doing philosophy involves focusing on the abstract and general and disengaging oneself from one’s personal interests and beliefs. It involves critiquing one’s attitudes, seeing abstract relations, and applying general principles. So, if good teaching (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Contesting patrilineal descent in political theory: James mill and nineteenth-century feminism.Jim Jose - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (1):151-174.
    : Liberal philosopher James Mill has been understood as being unambiguously antifeminist. However, Terence Ball, supposedly informed by a feminist perspective, has argued for a new interpretation. Ball has reconceptualized Mill as a feminist and the sole source of the feminism of his son (J. S. Mill), suggesting a revision of the received wisdom about their relationship to the development of nineteenth century feminist thought. This paper takes issue with Ball's "new interpretation" and its presumed feminist basis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Contesting Patrilineal Descent in Political Theory: James Mill and Nineteenth-Century Feminism.Jim Jose - 2000 - Hypatia 15 (1):151-174.
    Liberal philosopher James Mill has been understood as being unambiguously antifeminist. However, Terence Ball, supposedly informed by a feminist perspective, has argued for a new interpretation. Ball has reconceptualized Mill as a feminist and the sole source of the feminism of his son, suggesting a revision of the received wisdom about their relationship to the development of nineteenth century feminist thought. This paper takes issue with Ball's “new interpretation” and its presumed feminist basis.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Why can’t what is true be valuable?Jim Hutchinson - 2019 - Synthese (7):1-20.
    In recent discussions of the so-called “value of truth,” it is assumed that what is valuable in the relevant way is not the things that are true, but only various states and activities associated with those things: knowing them, investigating them, etc. I consider all the arguments I know of for this assumption, and argue that none provide good reason to accept it. By examining these arguments, we gain a better appreciation of what the value of the things that are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • John Stuart mill's philosophy of economics.Daniel M. Hausman - 1981 - Philosophy of Science 48 (3):363-385.
    John Stuart Mill regards economics as an inexact and separate science which employs a deductive method. This paper analyzes and restates Mill's views and considers whether they help one to understand philosophical peculiarities of contemporary microeconomic theory. The author concludes that it is philosophically enlightening to interpret microeconomics as an inexact and separate science, but that Mill's notion of a deductive method has only a little to contribute.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Actions and Decisions: Pragmatism Gateway to Artful Analytic Management Philosophizing.Pierre Guillet de Monthoux - 2017 - Philosophy of Management 16 (3):279-290.
    How management philosophy is conceived depends on if pragmatism is acknowledged or not! After having been under the main domination of management science both research and education has until recently widened its scope from a decision-making to an action-perspective. It seems to be a recent reconnection to pragmatism that makes the 2011 Carnegie report propose to rethink management in liberal arts terms, whilst the vastly influential 1959 Carnegie Pierson report distanced itself from American pragmatism thus focusing on decisions and forgetting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Sympathy and Self-Interest: The Crisis in Mill's Mental History*: Michele Green.Michele Green - 1989 - Utilitas 1 (2):259-277.
    John Stuart Mill's crisis of 1826 has received a great deal of attention from scholars. This attention results from reflection on the importance of the crisis to Mill's mature thought. Did the crisis signal rejection or revision of Benthamism? Or did it have little or no effect on Mill's view of his intellectual inheritance? Ultimately, an interpretation of the cause and resolution of the crisis is integral to an understanding of the nature of Mill's moral and social philosophy. Scholars, in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Melancholic epistemology.George Graham - 1990 - Synthese 82 (3):399-422.
    Too little attention has been paid by philosophers to the cognitive and epistemic dimensions of emotional disturbances such as depression, grief, and anxiety and to the possibility of justification or warrant for such conditions. The chief aim of the present paper is to help to remedy that deficiency with respect to depression. Taxonomy of depression reveals two distinct forms: depression (1) with intentionality and (2) without intentionality. Depression with intentionality can be justified or unjustified, warranted or unwarranted. I argue that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Loss of Affect in Intellectual Activity.Peter Goldie - 2012 - Emotion Review 4 (2):122-126.
    In this article I will consider how loss of affect in our intellectual lives, through depression for example, can be as debilitating as loss of affect elsewhere in our lives. This will involve showing that there are such things as intellectual emotions, that their role in intellectual activity is not merely as an aid to the intellect, and that loss of affect changes not only one’s motivations, but also one’s overall evaluative take on the world.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • John Stuart Mill on suicide.Iñigo Álvarez Gálvez - 2017 - Otrosiglo 1 (1):74-89.
    John Stuart Mill didn’t take his life; but he could have done it. Had he done it when he was twenty, we would have never known what he thought about it. But he didn’t. And many years later he wrote about nature, God, religion and autonomy. My aim in this article is to show how his thoughts about nature and theism affect in fact his stance about autonomy to commit suicide.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark