Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Updating evolutionary epistemology.Christophe Heintz - 2018 - In Kris Rutten, Stefaan Blancke & Ronald Soetaert (eds.), Perspectives on Science and Culture. West Lafayette, Indiana: Purdue University Press. pp. 195-222.
    This chapter critically analyzes evolutionary epistemology as a theoretical framework for the study of science as a historical and cultural phenomenon. As spelled out by Campbell in the 1970s, evolutionary epistemology has an ambitious goal: it aims at understanding the complex relations between bio- logical evolution, especially the biological evolution of human cognition, and the cultural evolution of scientific knowledge. It eventually aims at forming an integrated causal theory of the evolution of science, starting with the evo- lution of human (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The essential opacity of modular systems: Why even connectionism cannot give complete formal accounts of cognition.Marten J. den Uyl - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):56-57.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The psychological appeal of connectionism.Denise Dellarosa - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):28-29.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Multidisciplinary creativity: the case of Herbert A. Simon.Subrata Dasgupta - 2003 - Cognitive Science 27 (5):683-707.
    In the twentieth century, no person epitomized more dramatically the “Renaissance mind” than Herbert A. Simon (1916–2001). In aworking life spanning over 60 years, Simon made seminal contributions to administrative theory, axiomatic foundations of physics, economics, sociology, econometrics, cognitive psychology, logic of scientific discovery, and artificial intelligence. Simon's life of the mind, thus, affords nothing less than a “laboratory” in which to observe and examine at close quarters the phenomenon ofmultidisciplinary creativity. In this paper, we attempt to shed some light (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Is attention an appropriate concept for explaining brain processes?G. J. Dalenoort - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):341-342.
    In interpreting measurements of brain processes it is necessary to make the model used explicit. A concept such as attention cannot be used in the description of brain activities without a model of the relation of mental and neural processes.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Programs in the explanation of behavior.Robert Cummins - 1977 - Philosophy of Science 44 (June):269-87.
    The purpose of this paper is to set forth a sense in which programs can and do explain behavior, and to distinguish from this a number of senses in which they do not. Once we are tolerably clear concerning the sort of explanatory strategy being employed, two rather interesting facts emerge; (1) though it is true that programs are "internally represented," this fact has no explanatory interest beyond the mere fact that the program is executed; (2) programs which are couched (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   88 citations  
  • On the artificiality of artificial intelligence.Hans F. M. Crombag - 1993 - Artificial Intelligence and Law 2 (1):39-49.
    In this article the question is raised whether artificial intelligence has any psychological relevance, i.e. contributes to our knowledge of how the mind/brain works. It is argued that the psychological relevance of artificial intelligence of the symbolic kind is questionable as yet, since there is no indication that the brain structurally resembles or operates like a digital computer. However, artificial intelligence of the connectionist kind may have psychological relevance, not because the brain is a neural network, but because connectionist networks (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Mindwatching.Rodney M. J. Cotterill - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):340-341.
    This book delivers much more than its title appears to promise; it is not merely a description of current methods for remotely monitoring brain activity. It primarily concentrates on just one such method: positron emission tomography, but it demonstrates beautifully how far that technique can now take us in the quest to discover the mechanisms underlying thought.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A systematic methodology for cognitive modelling.R. Cooper, J. Fox, J. Farringdon & T. Shallice - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 85 (1-2):3-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The reflexivity of cognitive science: the scientist as model of human nature.Jamie Cohen-Cole - 2005 - History of the Human Sciences 18 (4):107-139.
    This article examines how experimental psychology experienced a revolution as cognitive science replaced behaviorism in the mid-20th century. This transition in the scientific account of human nature involved making normal what had once been normative: borrowing ideas of democratic thinking from political culture and conceptions of good thinking from philosophy of science to describe humans as active, creatively thinking beings, rather than as organisms that simply respond to environmental conditions. Reflexive social and intellectual practices were central to this process as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Is Smolensky's treatment of connectionism on the level?Carol E. Cleland - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):27-28.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Active symbols, limited storage and the power of natural intelligence.Eric Chown & Stephen Kaplan - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):442-443.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Re-membering cognition.Susan F. Chipman - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):441-442.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Information processing abstractions: The message still counts more than the medium.B. Chandrasekaran, Ashok Goel & Dean Allemang - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):26-27.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   26 citations  
  • Ability, Breadth, and Parsimony in Computational Models of Higher‐Order Cognition.Nicholas L. Cassimatis, Paul Bello & Pat Langley - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (8):1304-1322.
    Computational models will play an important role in our understanding of human higher‐order cognition. How can a model's contribution to this goal be evaluated? This article argues that three important aspects of a model of higher‐order cognition to evaluate are (a) its ability to reason, solve problems, converse, and learn as well as people do; (b) the breadth of situations in which it can do so; and (c) the parsimony of the mechanisms it posits. This article argues that fits of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Toward unified cognitive theory: The path is well worn and the trenches are deep.John M. Carroll - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):441-441.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Reframing the problem of intelligent behavior.Stuart K. Card - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):438-439.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A unified theory for psychologists?Richard A. Carlson & Mark Detweiler - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):440-440.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Methodological suggestions from a comparative psychology of knowledge processes.Donald T. Campbell - 1959 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 2 (1-4):152 – 182.
    Introductory Abstract Philosophers of science, in the course of making a sharp distinction between the tasks of the philosopher and those of the scientist, have pointed to the possibility of an empirical science of induction. A comparative psychology of knowledge processes is offered as one aspect of this potential enterprise. From fragments of such a psychology, methodological suggestions are drawn relevant to several chronic problems in the social sciences, including the publication of negative results from novel explorations, the operational diagnosis (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Learning by imitation: A hierarchical approach.Richard W. Byrne & Anne E. Russon - 1998 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 21 (5):667-684.
    To explain social learning without invoking the cognitively complex concept of imitation, many learning mechanisms have been proposed. Borrowing an idea used routinely in cognitive psychology, we argue that most of these alternatives can be subsumed under a single process, priming, in which input increases the activation of stored internal representations. Imitation itself has generally been seen as a This has diverted much research towards the all-or-none question of whether an animal can imitate, with disappointingly inconclusive results. In the great (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   52 citations  
  • Brain imaging, ethology, and the nonhuman mind.Gordon M. Burghardt - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):339-340.
    Posner & Raichle's (1994) exciting, wonderfully illustrated book describes the past successes and future potential of the relatively noninvasive imaging of the nervous systems of living people. The focus has been on cognitive processes but there is no reason why emotional and motivational systems cannot also be tapped. Although the authors do not formally address such contentious issues as consciousness and the private experience of other species, imaging methods may hold promise for helping us to understand these phenomena, as well (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Stakeholder Theory of the Firm.Steven N. Brenner - 1992 - Business Ethics Quarterly 2 (2):99-119.
    Various authors advocate consideration of stakeholder value concerns in organizational decision making. Brenner and Cochran (1990, 1991) propose a stakeholder theory of the firm which contains several propositions and a stakeholder value matrix. In order to begin any stakeholder rnodel validation, an approach is needed to measure stakeholder value and influence weights. We propose a multicriteria decision modeling approach, utilizing the analytic hierarchy process, to estimate stakeholder value matrix weights. This approach is illustrated using a simplified example and suggestions are (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • Unified cognitive theory: You can't get there from here.Derek Bickerton - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):437-438.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Two constructive themes.Richard K. Belew - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):25-26.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism and interlevel relations.William Bechtel - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):24-25.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • La compromission numérique, nouvelle incrimination principielle?Philippe Baumard - 2017 - Archives de Philosophie du Droit 59 (1):237-248.
    L’auteur établit le concept nouveau de compromission numérique selon lequel les algorithmes, et les acteurs qui les développent, ne se situent plus dans une logique de réplication de modèles de raisonnement ou de comportement humains, mais dans l’invention de modèles qui changent profondément les environnements physiques et sociaux où ils sont implantés. Dans ce scénario, la compromission numérique affecte le fait social. Uber ou Volskwagen ont créé des algorithmes déloyaux, capables de tromper la vigilance humaine aussi bien que la vigilance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models of Herbert A. Simon.Mie Augier - 2000 - Perspectives on Science 8 (4):407-443.
    : The work of Herbert A. Simon has drawn increasing attention from modern scholars who argue that Simon's work changed during the Cold War. This is due to the fact that Simon seemingly changed the substance of his research in the 1950s. This paper argues that Simon did not change in any significant way, but was lead by his interest in decision making and rationality into areas of economics, political science, sociology, psychology, organization theory, and computer science. He used elements (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On the proper treatment of the connection between connectionism and symbolism.Louise Antony & Joseph Levine - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):23-24.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Role of Imagination in Social Scientific Discovery: Why Machine Discoverers Will Need Imagination Algorithms.Michael Stuart - 2019 - In Mark Addis, Fernand Gobet & Peter Sozou (eds.), Scientific Discovery in the Social Sciences. Springer Verlag.
    When philosophers discuss the possibility of machines making scientific discoveries, they typically focus on discoveries in physics, biology, chemistry and mathematics. Observing the rapid increase of computer-use in science, however, it becomes natural to ask whether there are any scientific domains out of reach for machine discovery. For example, could machines also make discoveries in qualitative social science? Is there something about humans that makes us uniquely suited to studying humans? Is there something about machines that would bar them from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The Enactivist Revolution.Kenneth Aizawa - 2014 - Avant: Trends in Interdisciplinary Studies (2):19-42.
    Among the many ideas that go by the name of “enactivism” there is the idea that by “cognition” we should understand what is more commonly taken to be behavior. For clarity, label such forms of enactivism “enactivismb.” This terminology requires some care in evaluating enactivistb claims. There is a genuine risk of enactivist and non-enactivist cognitive scientists talking past one another. So, for example, when enactivistsb write that “cognition does not require representations” they are not necessarily denying what cognitivists claim (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Critique of the Computational Model of Thought: The Contribution of Merleau-Ponty.Christopher M. Aanstoos - 1987 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 18 (1-2):187-200.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Computers Are Syntax All the Way Down: Reply to Bozşahin.William J. Rapaport - 2019 - Minds and Machines 29 (2):227-237.
    A response to a recent critique by Cem Bozşahin of the theory of syntactic semantics as it applies to Helen Keller, and some applications of the theory to the philosophy of computer science.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Putting together connectionism – again.Paul Smolensky - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):59-74.
    A set of hypotheses is formulated for a connectionist approach to cognitive modeling. These hypotheses are shown to be incompatible with the hypotheses underlying traditional cognitive models. The connectionist models considered are massively parallel numerical computational systems that are a kind of continuous dynamical system. The numerical variables in the system correspond semantically to fine-grained features below the level of the concepts consciously used to describe the task domain. The level of analysis is intermediate between those of symbolic cognitive models (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  • The Rise of Cognitive Science in the 20th Century.Carrie Figdor - 2018 - In Amy Kind (ed.), Philosophy of Mind in the Twentieth and Twenty-First Centuries: The History of the Philosophy of Mind, Volume 6. New York: Routledge. pp. 280-302.
    This chapter describes the conceptual foundations of cognitive science during its establishment as a science in the 20th century. It is organized around the core ideas of individual agency as its basic explanans and information-processing as its basic explanandum. The latter consists of a package of ideas that provide a mathematico-engineering framework for the philosophical theory of materialism.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Expertise in Non-Well-Defined Task Domains: The Case of Reading.Sarah Bro Trasmundi, Edward Baggs, Juan Toro & Sune Vork Steffensen - 2024 - Social Epistemology 38 (1):13-27.
    In this article, we discuss expertise by considering the activity of reading. Cognitive scientists have traditionally conceptualised reading as a single, well-defined task, namely the decoding of letter sequences into meaningful sequences of speech sounds. This definition captures a core feature of the reading activity at the computational level, but it is an overly narrow model of how reading behaviour occurs in the real world. We propose a more expansive model of expertise. In our view, expertise in general is best (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Impasse-Driven problem solving: The multidimensional nature of feeling stuck.Wendy Ross & Selene Arfini - 2024 - Cognition 246 (C):105746.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The typology of scientific research.Stefan Ziemski - 1975 - Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 6 (2):276-291.
    Summary The typology of scientific research is of considerable importance for the development of the methodology of science. Apart from the typology accepted by UNESCO, the author introduces a new typology of scientific research, distinguishing the following types of research: diagnostic and generalizing, chronological and systematic, heuristic and justificatory, universalist and specialist, theoretical and practical, explanatory and descriptive and others.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The reality of the symbolic and subsymbolic systems.Andrew Woodfield & Adam Morton - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):58-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cartesian vs. Newtonian research strategies for cognitive science.Morton E. Winston - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):463-464.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognition and simulation.N. E. Wetherick - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):462-463.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Cognitive Psychology and the Understanding of Perception.Frederick J. Wertz - 1987 - Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 18 (1-2):103-142.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Protocol analysis as a task for artificial intelligence.D. A. Waterman & A. Newell - 1971 - Artificial Intelligence 2 (3-4):285-318.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On putting the cart before the horse: Taking perception seriously in unified theories of cognition.Kim J. Vicente & Alex Kirlik - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):461-462.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A cognitive process shell.Steven A. Vere - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):460-461.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Has the case been made against the ecumenical view of connectionism?Robert Van Gulick - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):57-58.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On models and mechanisms.William R. Uttal - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):459-460.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking in action.Barbara Tversky & Angela Kessell - 2014 - Pragmatics and Cognition 22 (2):206-223.
    When thought overwhelms the mind, the mind uses the body and the world. Several studies reveal ways that people alone or together use gesture and marks on paper to structure and augment their thought for comprehension, inference, and discovery. The studies show that the mapping of thought to gesture or the page is more direct than the arbitrary mapping to language and suggest that these forms of visual/spatial/action representation are used to “translate” language into mental representations. It is argued that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Thinking in action.Barbara Tversky & Angela Kessell - 2014 - Pragmatics and Cognition 22 (2):206-223.
    When thought overwhelms the mind, the mind uses the body and the world. Several studies reveal ways that people alone or together use gesture and marks on paper to structure and augment their thought for comprehension, inference, and discovery. The studies show that the mapping of thought to gesture or the page is more direct than the arbitrary mapping to language and suggest that these forms of visual/spatial/action representation are used to “translate” language into mental representations. It is argued that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Computation, PET images, and attention.John K. Tsotsos - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (2):372-372.
    Posner & Raichle (1994) is a nice addition to the Scientific American Library and the average reader will both enjoy the book and learn a great deal. As an activeresearcher, however, I find the book disappointing in many respects. My two major disappointments are in the illusion of computation that is created throughout the volume and in the inadequate perspective of the presentation on visual attention.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unified theories and theories that mimic each other's predictions.James T. Townsend - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):458-459.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation