Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Wilhelm Windelband: The History of Philosophy as Organon and as Integral part of Philosophy.Sergii Secundant - 2018 - Sententiae 37 (2):62-92.
    The article analyzes Wilhelm Windelband’s views on the problem of the relation of philosophy to its history. Windelband’s essay “History of philosophy” (1905) is put as a starting point. The main motive for this research is the idea that the history of philosophy is an organon and a component of philosophy. The article critically examines Windelband’s interpretation of (1) Hegel’s conception of the history of philosophy, (2) the question about the grounds of philosophers’ interest in the history of philosophy, (3) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Protestantism and progress in the year XII: Charles villers's essay on the spirit and influence of Luther's reformation (1804).Michael Printy - 2012 - Modern Intellectual History 9 (2):303-329.
    This article examines Charles Villers's Essay on the Spirit and Influence of Luther's Reformation (1804) in its intellectual and historical context. Exiled from France after 1792, Villers intervened in important French and German debates about the relationship of religion, history, and philosophy. The article shows how he took up a German Protestant discussion on the meaning of the Reformation that had been underway from the 1770s through the end of the century, including efforts by Kantians to seize the mantle of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Consciousness and Personal Identity.Owen Ware & Donald C. Ainslie - 2014 - In Aaron Garrett (ed.), The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy. New York: Routledge. pp. 245-264.
    This paper offers an overview of consciousness and personal identity in eighteenth-century philosophy. Locke introduces the concept of persons as subjects of consciousness who also simultaneously recognize themselves as such subjects. Hume, however, argues that minds are nothing but bundles of perceptions, lacking intrinsic unity at a time or across time. Yet Hume thinks our emotional responses to one another mean that persons in everyday life are defined by their virtues, vices, bodily qualities, property, riches, and the like. Rousseau also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The Explanatory Structure of the Transcendental Deduction and a Cognitive Interpretation of the First Critique.Scott Edgar - 2010 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (2):285-314.
    Consider two competing interpretations of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason: the epistemic and cognitive interpretations. The epistemic interpretation presents the first Critique as a work of epistemology, but what is more, it sees Kant as an early proponent of anti-psychologism—the view that descriptions of how the mind works are irrelevant for epistemology.2 Even if Kant does not always manage to purge certain psychological-sounding idioms from his writing, the epistemic interpretation has it, he is perfectly clear that he means his evaluation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kant’s Deductions of Morality and Freedom.Owen Ware - 2017 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 47 (1):116-147.
    It is commonly held that Kant ventured to derive morality from freedom in Groundwork III. It is also believed that he reversed this strategy in the second Critique, attempting to derive freedom from morality instead. In this paper, I set out to challenge these familiar assumptions: Kant’s argument in Groundwork III rests on a moral conception of the intelligible world, one that plays a similar role as the ‘fact of reason’ in the second Critique. Accordingly, I argue, there is no (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Reinhold's "letters on kantian philosophy": their significance for Kant and german philosophy.Sergii Sekundant - 2024 - Filosofska Dumka (Philosophical Thought) 2:56-77.
    The article is devoted primarily to the analysis of Reinhold’s Letters on Kantian Philosophy, published in the “Der Teutsche Merkur” (German Mercury) 1786-1787. The purpose of this analysis is to reveal the peculiarities of Reinhold’s interpretation of Kant’s philosophy, as well as the possibility of the influence of these letters on Kant's practical philosophy and the further development of German idealism in general. To more clearly define Reinhold's own position, the article turns to Reinhold's early works, written before Letters, as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • O problema do mal na Religião nos limites da simples razão.Jorge Vanderlei Costa da Conceição - 2018 - Con-Textos Kantianos 7:252-274.
    O presente artigo objetiva demonstrar que a proposição "o homem é mau por natureza" é sintética a priori prática, uma vez que, o terceiro grau de propensão, a malignidade, trata de uma caraterística antropológica do caráter inteligível do ser racional finito. Para validar a nossa hipótese interpretativa, afirmaremos que os dois primeiros graus de propensão, a fragilidade e a impureza, se ocupam do caráter sensível do ser humano, pois ele é sobredeterminado tanto pela inclinação quanto pela lei moral, mas isso (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • (1 other version)Transcendental philosophy and atheism.Wayne M. Martin - 2007 - European Journal of Philosophy 16 (1):109–130.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Between Determinism and Indeterminism: The Freedom of Choice in Fichte's Das System Der Sittenlehre.Kien-How Goh - 2015 - European Journal of Philosophy 23 (3):439-455.
    This paper examines Fichte's conception of the freedom of choice in Das System der Sittenlehre of 1798 as a solution to the dilemma posed by determinism and indeterminism. It show that Fichte does not simply affirm an indifferent power of voluntary choice, but demonstrates how such a power might co-exist with the measure of regularity and lawfulness we normally admit of human choices. Particular choices do not occur at random, but are based on general reasons. These reasons are in turn (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations