Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. A description theory of singular reference.Francesco Orilia - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (1):7–40.
    According to the received view, descriptivism is a dead end in an attempt to account for singular reference by proper names, indexicals and possibly even incomplete descriptions, for they require referentialism. In contrast to this, I argue for an application of the former to all kinds of singular terms, indexicals in particular, by relying on a view of incomplete descriptions as elliptical in a pragmatic sense. I thus provide a general analysis of singular reference. The proposed approach is in line (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The genome might as well store the entire language in the environment.Anat Ninio - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):746-747.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Natural selection and the autonomy of syntax.Frederick J. Newmeyer - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):745-746.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • A relational formulation of the theory of types.Reinhard Muskens - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (3):325 - 346.
    This paper developes a relational---as opposed to a functional---theory of types. The theory is based on Hilbert and Bernays' eta operator plus the identity symbol, from which Church's lambda and the other usual operators are then defined. The logic is intended for use in the semantics of natural language.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • On Walter Dubislav.Nikolay Milkov - 2015 - History and Philosophy of Logic 36 (2):147-161.
    This paper outlines the intellectual biography of Walter Dubislav. Besides being a leading member of the Berlin Group headed by Hans Reichenbach, Dubislav played a defining role as well in the Society for Empirical/Scientific Philosophy in Berlin. A student of David Hilbert, Dubislav applied the method of axiomatic to produce original work in logic and formalist philosophy of mathematics. He also introduced the elements of a formalist philosophy of science and addressed more general problems concerning the substantiation of human knowledge. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Temporal semantics in a superficially tenseless language.Lisa Matthewson - 2006 - Linguistics and Philosophy 29 (6):673 - 713.
    This paper contributes to the debate about ‘tenseless languages’ by defending a tensed analysis of a superficially tenseless language. The language investigated is St’át’imcets (Lillooet Salish). I argue that although St’át’imcets lacks overt tense morphology, every finite clause in the language possesses a phonologically covert tense morpheme; this tense morpheme restricts the reference time to being non-future. Future interpretations, as well as ‘past future’ would-readings, are obtained by the combination of covert tense with an operator analogous to Abusch’s (1985) WOLL. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   24 citations  
  • Middle position on language, cognition, and evolution.Michael Maratsos - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):744-745.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The mathematics of McTaggart's paradox.Domenico Mancuso - 2012 - Manuscrito 35 (2):233-67.
    Mc Taggart's celebrated proof of the unreality of time is a chain of implications whose final step asserts that the A-series (i.e. the classification of events as past, present or future) is intrinsically contradictory. This is widely believed to be the heart of the argument, and it is where most attempted refutations have been addressed; yet, it is also the only part of the proof which may be generalised to other contexts, since none of the notions involved in it is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Causal stories.David Magnus - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):744-744.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • As time goes by.Michael Lockwood - 1997 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 11 (1):35 – 51.
    The concept of temporal flow has been attacked both on the grounds that it is logically incoherent, and on the grounds that it conflicts with the theory of relativity. I argue that the charge of incoherence cannot be made to stick: McTaggart's argument commits the fallacy of equivocation, and arguments deployed by Smart and others turn out to be question-begging. But objections arising from relativity, so I claim, have considerably more force than Lucas acknowledges. Moreover, the idea of equating the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Adaptive complexity in sound patterns.Björn Lindblom - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):743-744.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Language evolved – So what's new?John Limber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):742-743.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Not invented here.Philip Lieberman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):741-742.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How much did the brain have to change for speech?R. C. Lewontin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):740-741.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Causality and tense--two temporal structure builders.Oversteegen Leonoor - 2005 - Journal of Semantics 22 (3):307-337.
    By force of _causes precede effects_, causality contributes to the temporal meaning of discourse. In case of semantic causal relations, this contribution is straightforward, but in case of epistemic causal relations, it is not. In order to gain insight into the semantics of epistemic causal relations, paradoxical cases are analyzed of text fragments in which temporal and causal meaning seem to be irreconcilable. A solution is proposed consisting of several parts: First, an analysis of epistemic causal coherence relations, in which (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aspect and interval tense logic.Miguel Leith & Jim Cunningham - 2001 - Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (3):331-381.
    Linguistic phenomena of tense and aspect have been investigated in a great deal of theoretical work in linguistics, philosophy and computer science. Modern tense logics, established by Prior, are part of this effort. Point tense logics offer an intuitive representation of tense but lack the expressiveness to represent many aspectual structures. Interval tense logics offer more expressiveness but in the general case can be computationally intractable. From a linguistic perspective there is the problem of precisely how to formalise the aspectual (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Temporal interpretation, discourse relations and commonsense entailment.Alex Lascarides & Nicholas Asher - 1993 - Linguistics and Philosophy 16 (5):437 - 493.
    This paper presents a formal account of how to determine the discourse relations between propositions introduced in a text, and the relations between the events they describe. The distinct natural interpretations of texts with similar syntax are explained in terms of defeasible rules. These characterise the effects of causal knowledge and knowledge of language use on interpretation. Patterns of defeasible entailment that are supported by the logic in which the theory is expressed are shown to underly temporal interpretation.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   67 citations  
  • The apparent superiority of prediction to accommodation as a side effect: A reply to Maher.Marc Lange - 2001 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (3):575-588.
    has offered a lovely example to motivate the intuition that a successful prediction has a kind of confirmatory significance that an accommodation lacks. This paper scrutinizes Maher's example. It argues that once the example is tweaked, the intuitive difference there between prediction and accommodation disappears. This suggests that the apparent superiority of prediction to accommodation is actually a side effect of an important difference between the hypotheses that tend to arise in each case.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Laws, counterfactuals, stability, and degrees of lawhood.Marc Lange - 1999 - Philosophy of Science 66 (2):243-267.
    I identify the special sort of stability (invariance, resilience, etc.) that distinguishes laws from accidental truths. Although an accident can have a certain invariance under counterfactual suppositions, there is no continuum between laws and accidents here; a law's invariance is different in kind, not in degree, from an accident's. (In particular, a law's range of invariance is not "broader"--at least in the most straightforward sense.) The stability distinctive of the laws is used to explicate what it would mean for there (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  • La notion de problème moteur principal en contexte de recherche.Normand Lacharité - 1982 - Dialogue 21 (3):449.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • La notion de problème moteur principal en contexte de recherche.Normand Lacharité - 1982 - Dialogue 21 (2):195-222.
    Un problème est dit ici «mouvoir» la recherche, quand c'est sur lui que se concentre l'énergie du chercheur et que c'est son traitement qui fait «avancer» la recherche.Une entreprise de recherche, une « e-r »,commej'écrirai souvent, est considérée ici comme une unité individuée et je postule qu'il y a toujours au moins un « niveau » où l'on peut se placer pour qu'il soit légitime de considérer une e-r comme une unité individuée.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Lessons from the study of speech perception.Keith R. Kluender - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):739-740.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Five exaptations in speech: Reducing the arbitrariness of the constraints on language.John Kingston - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):738-739.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Backtracking Counterfactuals Revisited.Justin Khoo - 2017 - Mind 126 (503):841-910.
    I discuss three observations about backtracking counterfactuals not predicted by existing theories, and then motivate a theory of counterfactuals that does predict them. On my theory, counterfactuals quantify over a suitably restricted set of historical possibilities from some contextually relevant past time. I motivate each feature of the theory relevant to predicting our three observations about backtracking counterfactuals. The paper concludes with replies to three potential objections.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Reichenbach's theory of reasonable assertion. [REVIEW]Evan K. Jobe - 1980 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31 (4):375-384.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • What would a theory of language evolution have to look like?Ray Jackendoff - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):737-738.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Needlessness of Adverbialism, Attributeism and its Compatibilty with Cognitive Science.Hilla Jacobson & Hilary Putnam - 2014 - Philosophia 42 (3):555-570.
    Although adverbialism is not given much attention in current discussions of phenomenal states, it remains of interest to philosophers who reject the representationalist view of such states, in suggesting an alternative to a problematic ‘act-property’ conception. We discuss adverbialism and the formalization Tye once offered for it, and criticize the semantics he proposed for this formalization. Our central claim is that Tye’s ontological purposes could have been met by a more minimal view, which we dub “attributeism”. We then show that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Aesthetic values in science.Milena Ivanova - 2017 - Philosophy Compass 12 (10):e12433.
    Scientists often use aesthetic values in the evaluation and choice of theories. Aesthetic values are not only regarded as leading to practically more useful theories but are often taken to stand in a special epistemic relation to the truth of a theory such that the aesthetic merit of a theory is evidence of its truth. This paper explores what aesthetic considerations influence scientists' reasoning, how such aesthetic values relate to the utility of a scientific theory, and how one can justify (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • Beyond the roadblock in linguistic evolution studies.James R. Hurford - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):736-737.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The meaning of “I” in “I”‐thought.Minyao Huang - 2018 - Mind and Language 33 (5):480-501.
    “I”‐thought is often taken to have a special cognitive significance, with “I” symbolising a subjective way of thinking about oneself that is inapt for communication. In this paper I argue that the way one thinks of oneself in “I”‐thought is immaterial to the meaning of “I,” for in general the psychological role associated with a referential expression is separable from its meaning. With respect to “I,” I suggest that its meaning consists in an interpersonal way of fixing its reference in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Self-knowledge and self-reference.Robert J. Howell - 2006 - Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 72 (1):44-70.
    Self-Knowledge and Self-Reference is a defense and reconciliation of the two apparently conflicting theses that the self is peculiarly elusive and that our basic, cogito-judgments are certain. On the one hand, Descartes seems to be correct that nothing is more certain than basic statements of self-knowledge, such as "I am thinking." On the other hand, there is the compelling Humean observation that when we introspect, nothing is found except for various "impressions." The problem, then, is that the Humean and Cartesian (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • Selecting grammars.Norbert Hornstein - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):735-736.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Tense and the psychology of relief.Christoph Hoerl - 2015 - Topoi 34 (1):217-231.
    At the centre of Arthur Prior’s ‘Thank goodness’ argument for the A-theory of time is a particular form of relief. Time must objectively pass, Prior argues, or else the relief felt when a painful experience has ended is not intelligible. In this paper, I offer a detailed analysis of the type of relief at issue in this argument, which I call temporal relief, and distinguish it from another form of relief, which I refer to as counterfactual relief. I also argue (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Self-reflexive thoughts.Gilbert Harman - 2006 - Philosophical Issues 16 (1):334-345.
    Alice has insomnia. She has trouble falling asleep and part of the problem is that she worries about it and realizes that her worrying about it tends to keep from falling asleep. It occurs to her that thinking that she will not be able to fall asleep may be a kind of self-fulfilling prophecy. Perhaps she even has a thought that might be expressed like this: I am not going to fall asleep because of my having this very thought. This (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Thinking of oneself as the thinker: the concept of self and the phenomenology of intellection.Marie Guillot - 2016 - Philosophical Explorations 19 (2):138-160.
    The indexical word “I” has traditionally been assumed to be an overt analogue to the concept of self, and the best model for understanding it. This approach, I argue, overlooks the essential role of cognitive phenomenology in the mastery of the concept of self. I suggest that a better model is to be found in a different kind of representation: phenomenal concepts or more generally phenomenally grounded concepts. I start with what I take to be the defining feature of the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Temporal connectives and verbal tenses as processing instructions.Cristina Grisot & Joanna Blochowiak - 2017 - Pragmatics and Cognition 24 (3):404-440.
    In this paper, we aim to enhance our understanding about the processing of implicit and explicit temporal chronological relations by investigating the roles of temporal connectives and verbal tenses, separately and in interaction. In particular, we investigate how two temporal connectives (ensuiteandpuis, both meaning ‘then’) and two verbal tenses expressing past time (the simple and compound past) act as processing instructions for chronological relations in French. Theoretical studies have suggested that the simple past encodes the instruction to relate events sequentially, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A New–old Characterisation of Logical Knowledge.Ivor Grattan-Guinness - 2012 - History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (3):245 - 290.
    We seek means of distinguishing logical knowledge from other kinds of knowledge, especially mathematics. The attempt is restricted to classical two-valued logic and assumes that the basic notion in logic is the proposition. First, we explain the distinction between the parts and the moments of a whole, and theories of ?sortal terms?, two theories that will feature prominently. Second, we propose that logic comprises four ?momental sectors?: the propositional and the functional calculi, the calculus of asserted propositions, and rules for (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Rube Goldberg machine par excellence.Myrna Gopnik - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):734-735.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Indexicals as token-reflexives.Manuel Garc'ıa-Carpintero - 1998 - Mind 107 (427):529-564.
    Reichenbachian approaches to indexicality contend that indexicals are "token-reflexives": semantic rules associated with any given indexical-type determine the truth-conditional import of properly produced tokens of that type relative to certain relational properties of those tokens. Such a view may be understood as sharing the main tenets of Kaplan's well-known theory regarding content, or truth-conditions, but differs from it regarding the nature of the linguistic meaning of indexicals and also regarding the bearers of truth-conditional import and truth-conditions. Kaplan has criticized these (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • What Experience Cannot Teach Us About Time.Akiko M. Frischhut - 2015 - Topoi 34 (1):143-155.
    Does the A-theory have an intuitive advantage over the B-theory? Many A-theorists have claimed so, arguing that their theory has a much better explanation for the fact that we all experience the passage of time: we experience time as passing because time really does pass. In this paper I expose and reject the argument behind the A-theorist’s claim. I argue that all parties have conceded far too easily that there is an experience that needs explaining in the first place. For (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Natural selection or shareability?Jennifer J. Freyd - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):732-734.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Seeing language evolution in the eye: Adaptive complexity or visual illusion?Lyn Frazier - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):731-732.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The intentionality of memory.Jordi Fernández - 2006 - Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (1):39-57.
    The purpose of this essay is to determine how we should construe the content of memories or, in other words, to determine what the intentional objects of memory are.1 The issue that will concern us is, then, analogous to the traditional philosophical question of whether perception directly puts us in cognitive contact with entities in the world or with entities in our own minds. As we shall see, there are some interesting aspects of the phenomenology and the epistemology of memory, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   44 citations  
  • Constructing Situations and Time.Tim Fernando - 2011 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 40 (3):371 - 396.
    Situations serving as partial worlds as well as events in natural language semantics are constructed from a type-theoretic interpretation of firstorder formulae and (after a type reduction) temporal formulae. Limitations of the Russell-Wiener-Kamp derivation of time from events are discussed and overcome to give a more widely applicable account of temporal granularity. Finite situations are formulated as strings of observations, conceptualized to persist inertially (in the absence of forces).
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The view from nowhen: The Mctaggart-Dummett argument for the unreality of time.Kevin Falvey - 2010 - Philosophia 38 (2):297-312.
    Years ago, Michael Dummett defended McTaggart’s argument for the unreality of time, arguing that it cannot be dismissed as guilty of an “indexical fallacy.” Recently, E. J. Lowe has disputed Dummett’s claims for the cogency of the argument. I offer an elaboration and defense of Dummett’s interpretation of the argument (though not of its soundness). I bring to bear some work on tense from the philosophy of language, and some recent work on the concept of the past as it occurs (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Hybrid Logic as extension of Modal and Temporal Logic.Daniel Álvarez Domínguez - 2019 - Revista de Humanidades de Valparaíso 13:34-67.
    Developed by Arthur Prior, Temporal Logic allows to represent temporal information on a logical system using modal operators such as P, F, H or G, whose intuitive meaning is “it was sometime in the Past...”, “it will be sometime in the Future...”, “it Has always been in the past...” and “it will always Going to be in the future...” respectively. Valuation of formulae built from these operators are carried out on Kripke semantics, so Modal Logic and Temporal Logic are consequently (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Existential disclosure.Paul Dekker - 1993 - Linguistics and Philosophy 16 (6):561 - 587.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • A pragmatic interpretation of intuitionistic propositional logic.Carlo Dalla Pozza & Claudio Garola - 1995 - Erkenntnis 43 (1):81-109.
    We construct an extension P of the standard language of classical propositional logic by adjoining to the alphabet of a new category of logical-pragmatic signs. The well formed formulas of are calledradical formulas (rfs) of P;rfs preceded by theassertion sign constituteelementary assertive formulas of P, which can be connected together by means of thepragmatic connectives N, K, A, C, E, so as to obtain the set of all theassertive formulas (afs). Everyrf of P is endowed with atruth value defined classically, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • Causal Slingshots.Michael Baumgartner - 2010 - Erkenntnis 72 (1):111-133.
    Causal slingshots are formal arguments advanced by proponents of an event ontology of token-level causation which, in the end, are intended to show two things: (i) The logical form of statements expressing causal dependencies on token level features a binary predicate ‘‘... causes ...’’ and (ii) that predicate takes events as arguments. Even though formalisms are only revealing with respect to the logical form of natural language statements, if the latter are shown to be adequately captured within a corresponding formalism, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Same‐Saying, Pluri‐Propositionalism, and Implicatures.Eros Corazza - 2012 - Mind and Language 27 (5):546-569.
    In combining a pluri‐propositionalist framework (Bach‐style) concerning alleged conventional implicatures, and a pluri‐propositionalist framework (Perry‐style) distinguishing various levels of content associated with a single utterance, I defend a Grice‐inspired model of communication. In so doing, I rely on the distinction between what is said, i.e. what is semantically encoded, and what is pragmatically implicated. I show how the notion of same‐saying plays a central role in dealing with problems pertaining to communication insofar as it permits us to posit a stability (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations