Switch to: References

Citations of:

The Unheeded Cry: Animal Consciousness, Animal Pain, and Science

Oxford University Press (1989)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. The suffering of invertebrates: An approach from animal ethics.Alejandro Villamor-Iglesias - 2021 - Tópicos: Revista de Filosofía 61:403-420.
    Invertebrate animals are usually seen as a kind of “aliens” which do not deserve any moral consideration. However, there is a growing amount of evidenceindicating that many of them do have the capacity to experience pain. The samecriteria that are usually applied in order to infer that vertebrates are sentient beings (behavioral response, learning capacity, memory, a certain specific neurophysiological structure…) lead to the idea that many invertebrates aresentient as well. Therefore, under the skeptical premise that we have no directevidence (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethical Debate on Animal Research.Abu Sadat Mohammad Nurunnabi, Rokhsana Dil Afroz & Salman Nur Alam - 2013 - Bangladesh Journal of Bioethics 4 (3):11-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Health and Welfare in Animals and Humans.Lennart Nordenfelt - 2011 - Acta Biotheoretica 59 (2):139-152.
    This paper contains a brief comparative analysis of some philosophical and scientific discourses on human and animal health and welfare, focusing mainly on the welfare of sentient animals. The paper sets forth two kinds of proposals for the analysis of animal welfare which do not appear in the contemporary philosophical discussion of human welfare, viz. the coping theory of welfare and the theory of welfare in terms of natural behaviour. These proposals are scrutinized in the light of some similar theories (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Robots should be slaves.Joanna J. Bryson - 2010 - In Yorick Wilks (ed.), Close Engagements with Artificial Companions: Key social, psychological, ethical and design issues. John Benjamins Publishing. pp. 63-74.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   74 citations  
  • Role of Joy in Farm Animal Welfare Legislation.Philipp von Gall & Mickey Gjerris - 2017 - Society and Animals 25 (2):163-179.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ethics, animals and the environment: A review of recent books. [REVIEW]Wim J. van der Steen - 1992 - Acta Biotheoretica 40 (4):339-347.
    Animal liberation ethics and environmental ethics have recently come of age. Concerning concrete moral rules considered by researchers in these areas there is much consensus. Highly general theories formulated to justify the rules are more problematic. However, the search for such theories may well be misguided.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A plea to implement robustness into a breeding goal: poultry as an example.L. Star, E. D. Ellen, K. Uitdehaag & F. W. A. Brom - 2008 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 21 (2):109-125.
    The combination of breeding for increased production and the intensification of housing conditions have resulted in increased occurrence of behavioral, physiological, and immunological disorders. These disorders affect health and welfare of production animals negatively. For future livestock systems, it is important to consider how to manage and breed production animals. In this paper, we will focus on selective breeding of laying hens. Selective breeding should not only be defined in terms of production, but should also include traits related to animal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • The pervasiveness of species bias.Peter Singer - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):759-761.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How to argue with egg producers.Peter Singer - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):749-750.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness might matter very much.Adam Shriver & Colin Allen - 2005 - Philosophical Psychology 18 (1):113-22.
    Peter Carruthers argues that phenomenal consciousness might not matter very much either for the purpose of determining which nonhuman animals are appropriate objects of moral sympathy, or for the purpose of explaining for the similarities in behavior of humans and nonhumans. Carruthers bases these claims on his version of a dispositionalist higher-order thought (DHOT) theory of consciousness which allows that much of human behavior is the result of first-order beliefs that need not be conscious, and that prima facie judgments about (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The burdensome enterprise of animal research.Kenneth J. Shapiro - 1997 - Ethics and Behavior 7 (2):188 – 192.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Transforming animal species: The case of 'oncomouse'.Maurizio Salvi - 2001 - Science and Engineering Ethics 7 (1):15-28.
    In this paper I deal with ethical implications arising from animal biotechnology. I analyse some general questions surrounding the production of transgenic animals through a specific case study: the oncomouse. In particular, I explore ethical factors involved in the production of oncomice. This is because biologists genetically modify animals’ germ cells and refuse to modify human germ cells. I will underline how the international community has thus far justified this ‘ethical difference’.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Assessing animal welfare: Design versus Performance criteria.Jeffrey Rushen - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):758-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Send in the clones ... Don't bother, they 're here'.B. Rollin - 1997 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 10 (1):25-40.
    The creation of a cloned sheep from mammary tissue has raisedmajor social concern, and much talk about major ethical issuesoccasioned by this technology. It is necessary to separategenuine from spurious ethical issues here, a task made failureto initiate ethical discussion and explanation of new technologyas well as by fear reactions in society. As in geneticengineering of animals, issues about cloning fall into threecategories – suggestions that the technology is inherently wrong,risk emerging from the technology and harm to the creatureengendered. The (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Animal Pain: What It is and Why It Matters. [REVIEW]Bernard E. Rollin - 2011 - The Journal of Ethics 15 (4):425-437.
    The basis of having a direct moral obligation to an entity is that what we do to that entity matters to it. The ability to experience pain is a sufficient condition for a being to be morally considerable. But the ability to feel pain is not a necessary condition for moral considerability. Organisms could have possibly evolved so as to be motivated to flee danger or injury or to eat or drink not by pain, but by “pangs of pleasure” that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Utilitarian killing, replacement, and rights.Evelyn Pluhar - 1990 - Journal of Agricultural Ethics 3 (2):147-171.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Utilitarian killing, replacement, and rights.Evelyn Pluhar - 1990 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 3 (2):147-171.
    The ethical theory underlying much of our treatment of animals in agriculture and research is the moral agency view. It is assumed that only moral agents, or persons, are worthy of maximal moral significance, and that farm and laboratory animals are not moral agents. However, this view also excludes human non-persons from the moral community. Utilitarianism, which bids us maximize the amount of good in the world, is an alternative ethical theory. Although it has many merits, including impartiality and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • The concept of learning from the study of the Holocaust.Nigel Pleasants - 2004 - History of the Human Sciences 17 (2-3):187-210.
    In his much-discussed Hitler’s Willing Executioners, Daniel Goldhagen claims to bring ‘the critical eye of the anthropologist’ to the task of understanding the motivational state of Holocaust perpetrators. This aspect of his methodology has not received much critical attention. In this article I seek to fill that gap. I do so through consideration of Peter Winch’s reflections on the concept of learning from anthropological study of an alien social and cultural world. Goldhagen tells us that perpetrators acted as they did (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Dying Animal.Jessica Pierce - 2013 - Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 10 (4):469-478.
    The study of animal death is poised to blossom into an exciting new interdisciplinary field—and one with profound relevance for bioethics. Areas of interest include the biology and evolution of death-related behavior in nonhuman animals, as well as human social, psychological, cultural, and moral attitudes toward and practices related to animal death. In this paper, I offer a brief overview of what we know about death-related behavior in animals. I will then sketch some of the bioethical implications of this emerging (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Affective consciousness: Core emotional feelings in animals and humans.Jaak Panksepp - 2005 - Consciousness and Cognition 14 (1):30-80.
    The position advanced in this paper is that the bedrock of emotional feelings is contained within the evolved emotional action apparatus of mammalian brains. This dual-aspect monism approach to brain–mind functions, which asserts that emotional feelings may reflect the neurodynamics of brain systems that generate instinctual emotional behaviors, saves us from various conceptual conundrums. In coarse form, primary process affective consciousness seems to be fundamentally an unconditional “gift of nature” rather than an acquired skill, even though those systems facilitate skill (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   126 citations  
  • Towards welfare biology: Evolutionary economics of animal consciousness and suffering. [REVIEW]Yew-Kwang Ng - 1995 - Biology and Philosophy 10 (3):255-285.
    Welfare biology is the study of living things and their environment with respect to their welfare. Despite difficulties of ascertaining and measuring welfare and relevancy to normative issues, welfare biology is a positive science. Evolutionary economics and population dynamics are used to help answer basic questions in welfare biology : Which species are affective sentients capable of welfare? Do they enjoy positive or negative welfare? Can their welfare be dramatically increased? Under plausible axioms, all conscious species are plastic and all (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   47 citations  
  • The Use of Animals in New Zealand: Regulation and Practice.Michael C. Morris - 2011 - Society and Animals 19 (4):368-382.
    On the statute books, New Zealand has a strong regulatory system that protects nonhuman animals on farms. Animals are guaranteed the “Five Freedoms,” including freedom to express normal patterns of behavior. This theoretically strong protection is weakened considerably, however, through institutional structures and practices. A loophole in the law allowing practices that violate the Five Freedoms in “exceptional circumstances” is used frequently. The Ministry of Agriculture and Forestry is the government agency that administers animal welfare regulation. This agency is also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Human Rights of Users of Humanlike Care Automata.Lantz Fleming Miller - 2020 - Human Rights Review 21 (2):181-205.
    Care is more than dispensing pills or cleaning beds. It is about responding to the entire patient. What is called “bedside manner” in medical personnel is a quality of treating the patient not as a mechanism but as a being—much like the caregiver—with desires, ideas, dreams, aspirations, and the gamut of mental and emotional character. As automata, answering an increasing functional need in care, are designed to enact care, the pressure is on their becoming more humanlike to carry out the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Filling the gaps in the risks vs. benefits of mammalian adult-cell cloning: Taking Bernard Rollin's philosophy its next step.Lantz Miller - 1998 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 11 (1):1-16.
    A critique is made of Bernard Rollin''s examination of the ethics of cloning adult mammalian cells. The primary concern is less to propound an anticloning or procloning position than to call for full exploration of the ethical complexities before a rush to judgment is made. Indeed, the ethical examination in question rushes toward an ethical position in such a way that does not appear consistent with Rollin''s usual methodology. By extending this methodology – which entails full weighing of benefits and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Fish and microchips: on fish pain and multiple realization.Matthias Michel - 2019 - Philosophical Studies 176 (9):2411-2428.
    Opponents to consciousness in fish argue that fish do not feel pain because they do not have a neocortex, which is a necessary condition for feeling pain. A common counter-argument appeals to the multiple realizability of pain: while a neocortex might be necessary for feeling pain in humans, pain might be realized differently in fish. This paper argues, first, that it is impossible to find a criterion allowing us to demarcate between plausible and implausible cases of multiple realization of pain (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  • “Würde der kreatur” and the common morality.Ben Mepham - 2000 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 13 (1):65-78.
    If respect for the dignity ofnon-human creatures is to be an element of publicpolicy it needs, as a first step, to be assimilatedinto the common morality. It is suggested that suchrespect may be based on several philosophicalpremises. Limiting the discussion to sentient animals,the paper reviews three of these: the concept ofanimal telos; the application of Rawlsiancontractarianism to the case of non-human animals asmoral patients; and human attitudes to animals in thelight of virtue theory. Consideration is then given tothe extent to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • “Würde der kreatur” and the common morality.Ben Mepham - 2000 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 13 (1-2):65-78.
    If respect for the dignity of non-human creatures is to be an element of public policy it needs, as a first step, to be assimilated into the common morality. It is suggested that such respect may be based on several philosophical premises. Limiting the discussion to sentient animals, the paper reviews three of these: the concept of animal telos; the application of Rawlsian contractarianism to the case of non-human animals as moral patients; and human attitudes to animals in the light (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The three rs: A restrictive and refutable rigmarole.H. Lansdell - 1993 - Ethics and Behavior 3 (2):177 – 185.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Behavioural restriction, animal welfare, and choice experiments.M. Kiley-Worthington - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):748-749.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Consciousness reduced: The role of the ‘idiot’ in early evolutionary psychology.Simon Jarrett - 2020 - History of the Human Sciences 33 (5):110-137.
    A conception of the idiotic mind was used to substantiate late 19th-century theories of mental evolution. A new school of animal/comparative psychologists attempted from the 1870s to demonstrate that evolution was a mental as well as a physical process. This intellectual enterprise necessitated the closure, or narrowing, of the ‘consciousness gap’ between human and animal species. A concept of a quasi-non-conscious human mind, set against conscious intention and ability in higher animals, provided an explanatory framework for the human–animal continuum and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Moral Considerability and the Argument from Relevance.Oscar Horta - 2018 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 31 (3):369-388.
    The argument from relevance expresses an intuition that, although shared by many applied ethicists, has not been analyzed and systematized in the form of a clear argument thus far. This paper does this by introducing the concept of value relevance, which has been used before in economy but not in the philosophical literature. The paper explains how value relevance is different from moral relevance, and distinguishes between direct and indirect ways in which the latter can depend on the former. These (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Toward positive animal welfare.Clive Hollands - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):757-758.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book Review. [REVIEW]Richard P. Haynes - 2007 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 21 (1):99-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Book review. [REVIEW]Richard P. Haynes - 2007 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 21 (1):533-542.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Telos and the Ethics of Animal Farming.Jes Lynning Harfeld - 2013 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 26 (3):691-709.
    The concept of animal welfare in confinement agriculture—and an ethical theory based upon this concept—necessitates an idea of what kind of being it is that fares well and what “well” is for this being. This double-question is at the heart of understanding and adequately defining welfare as qualitatively embedded in the experiencing subject. The notion of telos derives (philosophically) from Aristotle and is a way of accounting for the good life of an animal from the unique speciesness of the animal (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Philosophical Ethology: On the Extents of What It Is to Be a Pig.Jes Harfeld - 2011 - Society and Animals 19 (1):83-101.
    Answers to the question, “What is a farm animal?” often revolve around genetics, physical attributes, and the animals’ functions in agricultural production. The essential and defining characteristics of farm animals transcend these limited models, however, and require an answer that avoids reductionism and encompasses a de-atomizing point of view. Such an answer should promote recognition of animals as beings with extensive mental and social capabilities that outline the extent of each individual animal’s existence and—at the same time—define the animals as (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Liberty and Valuing Sentient Life.John Hadley - 2013 - Ethics and the Environment 18 (1):87-103.
    In “Do Animals have an Interest in Liberty?” Alasdair Cochrane brings some much needed attention to the ethics of animal confinement (2009a). Of particular significance is the question of whether confinement in itself is bad for nonhuman animal (hereafter, animal) well-being. If confinement conditions cause animals to suffer or frustrate their preferences it is safe to assume that liberty or freedom (following Cochrane, I use the terms interchangeably) would be instrumentally good for them. But, what about seemingly benign conditions of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • On strangerism and speciesism.J. A. Gray - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):756-757.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Steps in the ethical analysis of learned helplessness.John P. Gluck - 1997 - Ethics and Behavior 7 (2):186 – 188.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Harry F. Harlow and animal research: Reflection on the ethical paradox.John P. Gluck - 1997 - Ethics and Behavior 7 (2):149 – 161.
    With respect to the ethical debate about the treatment of animals in biomedical and behavioral research, Harry F. Harlow represents a paradox. On the one hand, his work on monkey cognition and social development fostered a view of the animals as having rich subjective lives filled with intention and emotion. On the other, he has been criticized for the conduct of research that seemed to ignore the ethical implications of his own discoveries. The basis of this contradiction is discussed and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Animals, thoughts and concepts.Hans-Johann Glock - 2000 - Synthese 123 (1):35-104.
    There are three main positions on animalthought: lingualism denies that non-linguistic animalshave any thoughts; mentalism maintains that theirthoughts differ from ours only in degree, due totheir different perceptual inputs; an intermediateposition, occupied by common sense and Wittgenstein,maintains that animals can have thoughts of a simplekind. This paper argues in favor of an intermediateposition. It considers the most important arguments infavor of lingualism, namely those inspired byDavidson: the argument from the intensional nature ofthought (Section 1); the idea that thoughts involveconcepts (Sections (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Use and abuse revisited: Response to Pluhar and Varner. [REVIEW]Kathryn Paxton George - 1994 - Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 7 (1):41-76.
    In her recent Counter-Reply to my views, Evelyn Pluhar defends her use of literature on nutrition and restates her argument for moral vegetarianism. In his Vegan Ideal article, Gary Varner claims that the nutrition literature does not show sufficient differences among women, men, and children to warrant concern about discrimination. In this response I show how Professor Pluhar continues to draw fallacious inferences: she begs the question on equality, avoids the main issue in my ethical arguments, argues from irrelevancies, misquotes (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Sustainability and the moral community.Kathryn Paxton George - 1992 - Agriculture and Human Values 9 (4):48-57.
    Three views of sustainability are juxtaposed with four views about who the members of the moral community are. These provide points of contact for understanding the moral issues in sustainability. Attention is drawn to the preferred epistemic methods of the differing factions arguing for sustainability. Criteria for defining membership in the moral community are explored; rationality and capacity for pain are rejected as consistent criteria. The criterion of having interests is shown to be most coherent for explaining why all living (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Moral and nonmoral innate constraints.Kathryn Paxton George - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (2):189-202.
    Charles J. Lumsden and E.O. Wilson, in their writings together and individually, have proposed that human behaviors, whether moral or nonmoral, are governed by innate constraints (which they have termed epigenetic rules). I propose that if a genetic component of moral behavior is to be discovered, some sorting out of specifically moral from nonmoral innate constraints will be necessary. That some specifically moral innate constraits exist is evidenced by virtuous behaviors exhibited in nonhuman mammals, whose behavior is usually granted to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Commentary: The Concept of a Bewusstseinskultur.Sascha Benjamin Fink - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Thomas Metzinger has diagnosed the need for a Bewusstseinskultur, a ‘consciousness culture’: a culturally implemented way in which a society as a whole engages with the dawning natural science of consciousness, with phenomenal experiences themselves, and with our increasing capability to manipulate them. A Bewusstseinskultur is an achievement, built by a society-wide orientation on empirical evidence, thorough scientific theorizing and rational deliberation. It affects a broad range of issues from animal ethics, drug policy, end-of-life-care, and robo-ethics to post-humanism. However, this (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Humans' use of animals: On the horns of a moral dilemma.Brian Everill - 1991 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 14 (4):756-756.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Integral ecology: The what, who, and how of environmental phenomena.Sean Esbjörn-Hargens - 2005 - World Futures 61 (1 & 2):5 – 49.
    Providing an overview of Integral Ecology, this article defines and explains some of the key terms and concepts that underlie an approach to the environment that is inspired by and makes use of Ken Wilber's Integral Theory. First Integral Ecology is distinguished from other environmental approaches. Then Wilber's Integral Theory is introduced, which provides a foundation for a participatory approach to ecology. Next, the ontology, epistemology, and methodology of environmental phenomena is examined in light of Wilber's framework and illustrated with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Scientific Autonomy and the 3Rs.Bernard E. Rollin - 2009 - American Journal of Bioethics 9 (12):62-64.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Fish Pain Debate: Broadening Humanity’s Moral Horizon.Maximilian Padden Elder - 2014 - Journal of Animal Ethics 4 (2):16-29,.
    This article explores the moral complexities and inconsistencies in the perception of fish welfare; mainly, that fish lack the ability to suffer and, therefore, exist outside of humanity’s moral horizon. The science behind fish sentience has advanced to the point where a serious discussion on the human-fish relationship is warranted. It is argued that enough scientific evidence exists to provide evidence for fish sentience and suffering. However, for those unconvinced in light of the lack of both scientific and popular consensus, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What to Think of Canine Obesity? Emerging Challenges to Our Understanding of Human–Animal Health Relationships.Chris Degeling, Ian Kerridge & Melanie Rock - 2013 - Social Epistemology 27 (1):90 - 104.
    (2013). What to Think of Canine Obesity? Emerging Challenges to Our Understanding of Human–Animal Health Relationships. Social Epistemology: Vol. 27, No. 1, pp. 90-104. doi: 10.1080/02691728.2012.760662.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation