Switch to: References

Citations of:

Plato's „Sophist”. The Drama of Original and Image

[author unknown]
Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 48 (1):121-121 (1983)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Apariencia e imagen: Examen a partir de algunos diálogos platónicos.Delgado Carolina - 2016 - Estudios de Filosofía (Universidad de Antioquia) 53.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Plato and Peirce on Likeness and Semblance.Han-Liang Chang - 2012 - Biosemiotics 5 (3):301-312.
    In his well-known essay, ‘What Is a Sign?’ (CP 2.281, 285) Peirce uses ‘likeness’ and ‘resemblance’ interchangeably in his definition of icon. The synonymity of the two words has rarely, if ever, been questioned. Curiously, a locus classicus of the pair, at least in F. M. Cornford’s English translation, can be found in a late dialogue of Plato, namely, the Sophist. In this dialogue on the myth and truth of the sophists’ profession, the mysterious ‘stranger’, who is most likely Socrates’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Heidegger’s ontic relatedness: Pros ti and Mitsein.Laura Candiotto - 2016 - Revista de Filosofia Aurora 28 (43):313.
    Relational structure is a primitive notion of Heidegger’s Dasein. By analyzing the concept of pros-ti as it emerges from the Heidegger’s 1924 course dedicated to Plato’s Sophist, I outline the Platonic and Aristotelic roots of Heideggerian Mitsein. Arguably the Mitsein makes explicit the instances of the pros ti — in other words, the instances of Aristotle’s concept of relatedness/intentionality that Heidegger ascribes to Plato’s heteron — but giving them an existential value, having Heidegger pursued the shift from realism to phenomenologyexistentialism. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Commentary on Dixsaut.Klaus Brinkmann - 1997 - Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 13 (1):28-34.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • No-existing beings: phantasmata in Plato.Barbara Botter - 2016 - Archai: Revista de Estudos Sobre as Origens Do Pensamento Ocidental 18:113-149.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Phainomena e explicação na Ética Eudêmia de Aristóteles.Raphael Zillig - 2014 - In Zillig Raphael (ed.), Conocimiento, ética y estética en la Filosofía Antigua: Actas del II Simposio Nacional de Filosofía Antigua. Asociación Argentina de Filosofía Antigua. pp. 330-336.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philebus.Verity Harte - 2012 - In Associate Editors: Francisco Gonzalez Gerald A. Press (ed.), The Continuum Companion to Plato. Continuum International Publishing Group. pp. 81-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Do We Recognise Problems?Audrey Wasser - 2017 - Deleuze and Guatarri Studies 11 (1):48-67.
    This article approaches Gilles Deleuze's notion of problems through a series of thinkers Deleuze draws on in developing this notion: Heidegger, Plato, Kant, Bergson and Nietzsche. Taking these thinkers as its guide, it sketches six broad characteristics that accompany an investment in problems, ultimately arguing that problems are attained through the activity of critique. It echoes Deleuze's essay ‘How Do We Recognise Structuralism?’ by asking: for whom do problems exist? What does Deleuze recognise in those who recognise problems? And what (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • The Groundwork for Dialectic in Statesman 277a-287b.Colin C. Smith - 2018 - International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 12 (2):132-150.
    In Plato’s Statesman, the Eleatic Stranger leads Socrates the Younger and their audience through an analysis of the statesman in the service of the interlocutors’ becoming “more capable in dialectic regarding all things”. In this way, the dialectical exercise in the text is both intrinsically and instrumentally valuable, as it yields a philosophically rigorous account of statesmanship and exhibits a method of dialectical inquiry. After the series of bifurcatory divisions in the Sophist and early Statesman, the Stranger changes to a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sophist 237-239.George Rudebusch - 1991 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 29 (4):521-531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Science of Philosophy: Discourse and Deception in Plato’s Sophist.Pettersson Olof - 2018 - Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (2):221-237.
    At 252e1 to 253c9 in Plato’s Sophist, the Eleatic Visitor explains why philosophy is a science. Like the art of grammar, philosophical knowledge corresponds to a generic structure of discrete kinds and is acquired by systematic analysis of how these kinds intermingle. In the literature, the Visitor’s science is either understood as an expression of a mature and authentic platonic metaphysics, or as a sophisticated illusion staged to illustrate the seductive lure of sophistic deception. By showing how the Visitor’s account (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wandering philosophers in Classical Greece.Silvia Montiglio - 2000 - Journal of Hellenic Studies 120:86-105.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • La symphonie de l'être dans le Sophiste de Platon.Jean-François Mattéi - 1985 - Dialogue 24 (2):237-256.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Dynamic Association of Being and Non-Being: Heidegger’s Thoughts on Plato’s Sophist Beyond Platonism.SangWon Lee - 2016 - Human Studies 39 (3):385-403.
    This article examines Heidegger’s interpretation of Plato’s Sophist, focusing on his attempts to grasp Plato’s original thinking of being and non-being. Some contemporary thinkers and commentators argue that Heidegger’s view of Plato is simply based on his criticism against the traditional metaphysics of Platonism and its language. But a close reading of his lecture on the Sophist reveals that his view of Plato is grounded in Plato’s questioning struggle with the ambiguous nature of human speech or language. For Heidegger, Plato’s (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Europe and the Stranger.Rodolphe Gasché - 2016 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 47 (3):292-305.
    ABSTRACTWith few exceptions, the prominent role of the Stranger in Plato’s late dialogue on the Sophist has drawn little attention in Plato scholarship. Yet, in this dialogue Plato charges the expatriated Stranger, who, furthermore, lacks a patronym and thus is not identifiable, remaining a stranger to the end, with the task not only of rejecting all philosophy hitherto as nothing more than a kind of storytelling about Being, but also of committing the parricide of Parmenides, the father of Greek philosophy (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘The Ordinary’ in Stanley Cavell and Jacques Derrida.Judith Wolfe - 2013 - Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 17 (1).
    This paper analyses the opposing accounts of ‘the ordinary’ given by Jacques Derrida and Stanley Cavell, beginning with their competing interpretations of J. L. Austin¹s thought on ordinary language. These accounts are presented as mutually critiquing: Derrida¹s deconstructive method poses an effective challenge to Cavell¹s claim that the ordinary is irreducible by further philosophical analysis, while, conversely, Cavell¹s valorisation of the human draws attention to a residual humanity in Derrida¹s text which Derrida cannot account for. The two philosophers’ approaches are, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation