Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. What Might a Theory of Causation Do for Sport?Evan Thomas Knott - 2019 - Philosophies 4 (2):34-0.
    The purpose of this research is to articulate how a theory of causation might be serviceable to a theory of sport. This article makes conceptual links between Bernard Suits’ theory of game-playing, causation, and theories of causation. It justifies theories of causation while drawing on connections between sport and counterfactuals. It articulates the value of theories of causation while emphasizing possible limitations. A singularist theory of causation is found to be more broadly serviceable with particular regard to its analysis of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Playing with Art in Suits’ Utopia.Nathan Wildman & Alfred Archer - 2019 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (3-4):456-470.
    ABSTRACTAccording to Bernard Suits, people in Utopia would spend their time playing games and would not spend any time creating or engaging with artworks. Here, we argue against this claim. We do s...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Paradoxes of Utopian Game-Playing.Deborah P. Vossen - 2017 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 44 (3):315-328.
    In The Grasshopper: Games, Life, and Utopia, Suits maintains the following two theses: game-playing is defined as ‘activity directed towards bringing about a specific state of affairs, using only means permitted by rules, where the rules prohibit more efficient in favour of less efficient means, and where such rules are accepted just because they make possible such activity’ and ‘game playing is what makes Utopia intelligible.’ Observing that these two theses cannot be jointly maintained absent paradox, this essay explores the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Good Grasshopping and the Avoidance of Game-Spoiling.Deborah P. Vossen - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35 (2):175-192.
    Traditionally, acts of sportsmanship have been upheld as worthy of praise. The purpose of this paper is to discern whether Bernard Suits’ Grasshopper -- in "The Grasshopper: Games, Life and Utopia" -- would share this approval. The paper begins with a conceptual analysis of good sportspersonship. From this, four action categories are identified including good sportspersonship in the forms of game desertion, changing the game, not trying, and lusory self-handicapping. A strategy for evaluation is derived from the Grasshopper’s theory. Game-playing (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • What Counts As Part of a Game? A Look at Skills.Cesar R. Torres - 2000 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 27 (1):81-92.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   54 citations  
  • Games and Their Institutions in The Grasshopper.Bernard Suits - 2006 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 33 (1):1-8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Fruits, Apples, and Category Mistakes: On Sport, Games, and Play.Angela J. Schneider - 2001 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 28 (2):151-159.
    (2001). Fruits, Apples, and Category Mistakes: On Sport, Games, and Play. Journal of the Philosophy of Sport: Vol. 28, No. 2, pp. 151-159. doi: 10.1080/00948705.2001.9714610.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • An Epistemic Condition for Playing a Game.Lukas Schwengerer - 2018 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (3-4):293-306.
    In 'The Grasshopper' Suits proposes that ‘playing a game’ can be captured as an attempt to achieve a specific state of affairs (prelusory goal), using only means permitted by rules (lusory means). These rules prohibit more efficient means, and are accepted because they make the activity possible (lusory attitude). I argue these conditions are not jointly sufficient. The starting point for the argument is the idea that goals, means and attitudes can pick out their content in different ways. They can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Suits, Autotelicity, Temporal Reallocations, Game Resources and Defining 'play'.Richard Royce - 2011 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 5 (2):93 - 109.
    Bernard Suits bequeathed a rich legacy of philosophical insights contributing to our developing a deeper understanding of sport-related issues, and his work has attracted much attention and stimulated valuable controversy over many years. However, the interest it has stimulated appears uneven. In this context and with reference to the former claims above, I focus on a part of his work that has received relatively less commentary, in the hope that it too will yield work of value. Given the imaginative quality (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Physical Activity is not Necessary: The Notion of Sport as Unproductive Officialised Competitive Game.Felix Lebed - 2021 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 16 (1):111-129.
    Every cultural phenomenon is multifaceted and only with great difficulty can it fit into the framework of one general concept. The term ‘sport’ is such a broad concept, because the great wealth of...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Gaming Up Life: Considerations for Game Expansions.Scott Kretchmar - 2008 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 35 (2):142-155.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • A Revised Definition of Games: An Analysis of Grasshopper Errors, Omissions, and Ambiguities.Scott Kretchmar - 2019 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 13 (3-4):277-292.
    ABSTRACTIn this essay, I review Suits’ classic description of games and cite three kinds of problems—mischaracterizations, omissions, and ambiguities. I build on previous criticisms by myself and others leveled at his definition. However, in contrast to much of this previous work, I will present what I hope is an improved description. The latter part of the essay is devoted to defending this alternate characterization. I conclude by arguing that my revisionist work paradoxically both supports and undermines the merits of Suits’ (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • A Functionalist Analysis of Game Acts: Revisiting Searle.R. Scott Kretchmar - 2001 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 28 (2):160-172.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • A critique of Suits’s (alleged) counterexample to Wittgenstein’s position on the definability of ‘game’.Ralph H. Johnson & Dennis Hudecki - 2019 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 47 (1):89-104.
    A central theme in the philosophy of sport literature is the definability of games. According to Thomas Hurka, and others, the argument presented by Bernard Suits in The Grasshopper refutes...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Not everything is a contest: sport, nature sport, and friluftsliv.Leslie A. Howe - 2019 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 46 (3):437-453.
    Two prevalent assumptions in the philosophy of sport literature are that all sports are games and that all games are contests, meant to determine who is the better at the skills definitive of the sport. If these are correct, it would follow that all sports are contests and that a range of sporting activities, including nature sports, are not in fact sports at all. This paper first confronts the notion that sport and games must seek to resolve skill superiority through (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Illusory checkmates: why chess is not a game.Michael Hickson - 2022 - Synthese 200 (5):1-21.
    In this essay I argue that chess is not a game.?I begin by arguing the narrower point that chess is not a game in the sense of 'game' developed by Bernard Suits.?Chess is not a Suitsian game because chess lacks a prelusory goal.?Chess lacks a prelusory goal, which is a goal that is identifiable before a game is played, because no checkmate position is knowably achievable before chess is played.?Checkmate is a postlusory discovery about chess, not a prelusory goal of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Games and ideal playgrounds.Colleen English - 2019 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 46 (3):401-415.
    ABSTRACTEven though many sport philosophers have worked to delineate clear definitions of play and games, typical language usage often conflates the two phenomena and even provides an undue normati...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aristotle and Cricket: Drama in Retrospect.Anthony D. Buckley - 2006 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 33 (1):21-36.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Sprints, Sports, and Suits.Mitchell N. Berman - 2013 - Journal of the Philosophy of Sport 40 (1):163-176.
    Philosophy of sport orthodoxy maintains the following three theses: (1) all sports (or all refereed sports) are games; (2) games are as Suits defined them; and (3) sprints are sports. This article argues that these three theses cannot be jointly maintained and offers exploratory thoughts regarding what might follow.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations