- Induction and Confirmation Theory: An Approach based on a Paraconsistent Nonmonotonic Logic.Ricardo Sousa Silvestre - 2010 - Princípios 17 (28):71-98.details
|
|
Induction and inference to the best explanation.Ruth Weintraub - 2013 - Philosophical Studies 166 (1):203-216.details
|
|
Karl Popper, Science and Enlightenment.Nicholas Maxwell - 2017 - London: UCL Press.details
|
|
Ramsification and inductive inference.Panu Raatikainen - 2012 - Synthese 187 (2):569-577.details
|
|
Le réalisme des hypothèses et la Partial Interpretation View.Philippe Mongin - 1988 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 18 (3):281-325.details
|
|
Hempel's Raven paradox: A lacuna in the standard bayesian solution.Peter B. M. Vranas - 2004 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 55 (3):545-560.details
|
|
Explanation as a guide to induction.Roger White - 2005 - Philosophers' Imprint 5:1-29.details
|
|
Troubles with the Canberra Plan.Panu Raatikainen - 2020 - Synthese 1 (1-2).details
|
|
Relevance and Verification.Ben Blumson - 2021 - Philosophical Quarterly 71 (3):457-480.details
|
|
Evidence and the openness of knowledge.Assaf Sharon & Levi Spectre - 2017 - Philosophical Studies 174 (4):1001-1037.details
|
|
On the equivalence of Goodman’s and Hempel’s paradoxes.Kenneth Boyce - 2014 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 45:32-42.details
|
|
Inductive confirmation, counterfactual conditionals, and laws of nature.Marc Lange - 1996 - Philosophical Studies 85 (1):1-36.details
|
|
The Two Davids and Australian Materialism.A. R. J. Fisher - 2021 - In Peter R. Anstey & David Braddon-Mitchell (eds.), Armstrong's Materialist Theory of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 29-51.details
|
|
A Conciliatory Answer to the Paradox of the Ravens.William Peden - 2020 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 51 (1):45-64.details
|
|
Argumentation Theory and the Recent Philosophy of Science.William Rehg - unknowndetails
|
|
On What We Know We Don’t Know.Sylvain Bromberger - 1992 - Chicago and London / Stanford: University of Chicago Press / CSLI.details
|
|
Chalmers' Blueprint of the World.Panu Raatikainen - 2014 - International Journal of Philosophical Studies 22 (1):113-128.details
|
|
Scientific Objectivity and Framework Transpositions.Patrick A. Heelan - 1970 - Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 19:55-70.details
|
|
Scheffler Revisited on the Role of History and Philosophy of Science in Science Teacher Education.R. Michael Matthews - 1997 - Studies in Philosophy and Education 16 (1/2):159-173.details
|
|
Neo-rationalism versus neo-darwinism: Integrating development and evolution. [REVIEW]Kelly C. Smith - 1992 - Biology and Philosophy 7 (4):431-451.details
|
|
Rethinking objectivity: Nozick's neglected third option.Alison Wylie - 2000 - International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 14 (1):5 – 9.details
|
|
The species problem: A reply to Hull.Michael Ruse - 1971 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (4):369-371.details
|
|
Teaching the Philosophical and Worldview Components of Science.Michael R. Matthews - 2009 - Science & Education 18 (6-7):697-728.details
|
|
R. M. Martin’s Logic of Belief.David Parsons - 2017 - History and Philosophy of Logic 38 (1):72-86.details
|
|
Der Rabe und der Bayesianist.Mark Siebel - 2004 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 35 (2):313-329.details
|
|
A Comparative Treatment of the Paradox of Confirmation.Ram-Prasad Chakravarthi - 2002 - Journal of Indian Philosophy 30 (4):339-358.details
|
|
The compatibility of divine foreknowledge and freewill.J. Westphal - 2011 - Analysis 71 (2):246-252.details
|
|
On the independence of singular causal explanation in social science: Archaeology.Thomas Nickles - 1977 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (2):163-187.details
|
|
Metaphysics and the advancement of science.J. W. N. Watkins - 1975 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 26 (2):91-121.details
|
|
Reliabilism and induction.Michael Levin - 1993 - Synthese 97 (3):297 - 334.details
|
|
The average american has 2.3 children.Jeff Pelletier - unknowndetails
|
|
Carnap, Kuhn, and revisionism: On the publication of structure in encyclopedia. [REVIEW]J. C. Pinto de Oliveira - 2007 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 38 (1):147-157.details
|
|
Four ways of eliminating mind from teleology.Lowell Nissen - 1991 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 24 (1):27-48.details
|
|
Ryle revisited: The dispositional model fifty years after.Grazia Melilli Ramoino - 2003 - British Journal for the History of Philosophy 11 (1):89 – 119.details
|
|
Confirmation, paradoxes, and possible worlds.Shelley Stillwell - 1985 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 36 (1):19-52.details
|
|
Objectivity and rationality in epistemology and education: Scheffler's middle road.Alven Neiman & Harvey Siegel - 1993 - Synthese 94 (1):55 - 83.details
|
|
Die pragmatische vollendung Des logischen empirismus. In memoriam Carl Gustav Hempel (1905–1997).Gereon Wolters - 2000 - Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 31 (2):205-242.details
|
|
On 'what is said to be'.Robert Schwartz - 1993 - Synthese 94 (1):43 - 54.details
|
|
Explanations, desires, and inscriptions.Israel Scheffler - 1971 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (4):362-369.details
|
|
Observational Data and Scientific Progress.Friedrich Rapp - 1980 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 11 (2):153.details
|
|
Another look at the doctrine of verstehen.Jane R. Martin - 1969 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 20 (1):53-67.details
|
|
Inscriptionalism and the objects of explanation.Samuel Gorovitz - 1970 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 21 (3):247-256.details
|
|