Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Computing as a Science: A Survey of Competing Viewpoints. [REVIEW]Matti Tedre - 2011 - Minds and Machines 21 (3):361-387.
    Since the birth of computing as an academic discipline, the disciplinary identity of computing has been debated fiercely. The most heated question has concerned the scientific status of computing. Some consider computing to be a natural science and some consider it to be an experimental science. Others argue that computing is bad science, whereas some say that computing is not a science at all. This survey article presents viewpoints for and against computing as a science. Those viewpoints are analyzed against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • What really matters.Charles Taylor - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The thinker dreams of being an emperor.M. M. Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):685-686.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The possibility of irreducible intentionality.Charles Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):626-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Minds, programs, and chinese philosophers: A chinese perspective on the chinese room.Koji Tanaka - 2004 - Sophia 43 (1):61-72.
    The paper is concerned with John Searle’s famous Chinese room argument. Despite being objected to by some, Searle’s Chinese room argument appears very appealing. This is because Searle’s argument is based on an intuition about the mind that ‘we’ all seem to share. Ironically, however, Chinese philosophers don’t seem to share this same intuition. The paper begins by first analysing Searle’s Chinee room argument. It then introduces what can be seen as the (implicit) Chinese view of the mind. Lastly, it (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Experimental philosophy within its proper bounds.John Symons - 2022 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 65 (5):586-606.
    ABSTRACT In Philosophy Within its Proper Bounds, Édouard Machery argues that the results of experimental philosophy should lead us to abandon much of traditional philosophical practice. In its place Machery defends naturalized conceptual analysis as a more modest and pragmatic alternative to standard analytic philosophy. This paper argues that Machery overstates the metaphilosophical significance of x-phi’s results. We can and should keep many of the insights and good methodological habits that come with x-phi. However, if one is not already convinced (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Don't leave the “un” off “consciousness”.Neal R. Swerdlow - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):699-700.
    Gray extrapolates from circuit models of psychopathology to propose neural substrates for the contents of consciousness. I raise three concerns: knowledge of synaptic arrangements may be inadequate to fully support his model; latent inhibition deficits in schizophrenia, a focus of this and related models, are complex and deserve replication; and this conjecture omits discussion of the neuropsychological basis for the contents of the unconscious.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Keith Devlin, goodbye, Descartes: The end of logic and the search for a new cosmology of the mind. [REVIEW]Jim Swan - 2000 - Minds and Machines 10 (3):409-416.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is PARRY paranoid?David W. Swanson - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4):548-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • How Is Meaning Grounded in the Organism?Liz Stillwaggon Swan & Louis J. Goldberg - 2010 - Biosemiotics 3 (2):131-146.
    In this paper we address the interrelated questions of why and how certain features of an organism’s environment become meaningful to it. We make the case that knowing the biology is essential to understanding the foundation of meaning-making in organisms. We employ Miguel Nicolelis et al’s seminal research on the mammalian somatosensory system to enrich our own concept of brain-objects as the neurobiological intermediary between the environment and the consequent organismic behavior. In the final section, we explain how brain-objects advance (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Kan maskiner tenke likevel? En kritikk av Einar Duenger Bøhns artikkel «Kan maskiner tenke?».Atle Ottesen Søvik - 2023 - Norsk Filosofisk Tidsskrift 58 (4):225-235.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • 深層学習の哲学的意義.Takayuki Suzuki - 2021 - Kagaku Tetsugaku 53 (2):151-167.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Probaility and information.Patrick Suppes - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (1):81-82.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • Problems of extension, representation, and computational irreducibility.Patrick Suppes - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):507-508.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Problem spaces, language and connectionism: Issues for cognition.Patrick Suppes - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):457-458.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Computational Models of Consciousness: An Evaluation.Ron Sun - 1999 - Journal of Intelligent Systems 9 (5-6):507-568.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Criteria for an effective theory of consciousness and some preliminary attempts.Ron Sun - 2004 - Consciousness and Cognition 13 (2):268-301.
    In the physical sciences a rigorous theory is a hierarchy of descriptions in which causal relationships between many general types of entity at a phenomenological level can be derived from causal relationships between smaller numbers of simpler entities at more detailed levels. The hierarchy of descriptions resembles the modular hierarchy created in electronic systems in order to be able to modify a complex functionality without excessive side effects. Such a hierarchy would make it possible to establish a rigorous scientific theory (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Artificial Forms of Life.Sebastian Sunday Grève - 2023 - Philosophies 8 (5).
    The logical problem of artificial intelligence—the question of whether the notion sometimes referred to as ‘strong’ AI is self-contradictory—is, essentially, the question of whether an artificial form of life is possible. This question has an immediately paradoxical character, which can be made explicit if we recast it (in terms that would ordinarily seem to be implied by it) as the question of whether an unnatural form of nature is possible. The present paper seeks to explain this paradoxical kind of possibility (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Effective search using Sewall Wright's shifting balance hypothesis.B. H. Sumida - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):93-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Steep Cliff Arguments.David B. Suits - 1999 - Argumentation 13 (2):127-138.
    In recent philosophical debates a number of arguments have been used which have so much in common that it is useful to study them as having a similar structure. Many arguments -- Searle's Chinese Room, for example -- make use of thought experiments in which we are told a story or given a narrative context such that we feel we are in comfortable surroundings. A new notion is then introduced which clashes with our ordinary habits and associations. As a result, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why the Method of Cases Doesn’t Work.Christopher Suhler - 2019 - Review of Philosophy and Psychology 10 (4):825-847.
    In recent years, there has been increasing discussion of whether philosophy actually makes progress. This discussion has been prompted, in no small part, by the depth and persistence of disagreement among philosophers on virtually every major theoretical issue in the field. In this paper, I examine the role that the Method of Cases – the widespread philosophical method of testing and revising theories by comparing their verdicts against our intuitions in particular cases – plays in creating and sustaining theoretical disagreements (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Why language clouds our ascription of understanding, intention and consciousness.Susan A. J. Stuart - forthcoming - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences:1-22.
    The grammatical manipulation and production of language is a great deceiver. We have become habituated to accept the use of well-constructed language to indicate intelligence, understanding and, consequently, intention, whether conscious or unconscious. But we are not always right to do so, and certainly not in the case of large language models (LLMs) like ChapGPT, GPT-4, LLaMA, and Google Bard. This is a perennial problem, but when one understands why it occurs, it ceases to be surprising that it so stubbornly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The situated processing of situated language.Susan U. Stucky - 1989 - Linguistics and Philosophy 12 (3):347 - 357.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conscious machines: Memory, melody and muscular imagination. [REVIEW]Susan A. J. Stuart - 2010 - Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 9 (1):37-51.
    A great deal of effort has been, and continues to be, devoted to developing consciousness artificially (A small selection of the many authors writing in this area includes: Cotterill (J Conscious Stud 2:290–311, 1995 , 1998 ), Haikonen ( 2003 ), Aleksander and Dunmall (J Conscious Stud 10:7–18, 2003 ), Sloman ( 2004 , 2005 ), Aleksander ( 2005 ), Holland and Knight ( 2006 ), and Chella and Manzotti ( 2007 )), and yet a similar amount of effort has (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Neo-Lamarckism, or, The rediscovery of culture.Gary W. Strong - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):92-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conversation, responsibility, and autism spectrum disorder.Nathan Stout - 2016 - Philosophical Psychology 29 (7):1-14.
    In this paper, I present a challenge for Michael McKenna’s conversational theory of moral responsibility. On his view, to be a responsible agent is to be able to engage in a type of moral conversation. I argue that individuals with autism spectrum disorder present a considerable problem for the conversational theory because empirical evidence on the disorder seems to suggest that there are individuals in the world who meet all of the conditions for responsible agency that the theory lays out (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • From data to dynamics: The use of multiple levels of analysis.Gregory O. Stone - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):54-55.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Philosophy and WEIRD intuition.Stephen Stich - 2010 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (2-3):110-111.
    From Plato to the present, philosophers have relied on intuitive judgments as evidence for or against philosophical theories. Most philosophers are WEIRD, highly educated, and male. The literature reviewed in the target article suggests that such people might have intuitions that differ from those of people in other groups. There is a growing body of evidence suggesting that they do.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • From connectionism to eliminativism.Stephen P. Stich - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (1):53-54.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Connectionism, Realism, and realism.Stephen P. Stich - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (3):531.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • What muscle variable(s) does the nervous system control in limb movements?R. B. Stein - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):535-541.
    To controlforceaccurately under a wide range of behavioral conditions, the central nervous system would either require a detailed, continuously updated representation of the state of each muscle (and the load against which each is acting) or else force feedback with sufficient gain to cope with variations in the properties of the muscles and loads. The evidence for force feedback with adequate gain or for an appropriate central representation is not sufficient to conclude that force is the major controlled variable in (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   168 citations  
  • Ultimate differences.G. Lynn Stephens & George Graham - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):698-699.
    Gray unwisely melds together two distinguishable contributions of consciousness: one to epistemology, the other to evolution. He also renders consciousness needlessly invisible behaviorally.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The representation of egocentric space in the posterior parietal cortex.J. F. Stein - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):691-700.
    The posterior parietal cortex (PPC) is the most likely site where egocentric spatial relationships are represented in the brain. PPC cells receive visual, auditory, somaesthetic, and vestibular sensory inputs; oculomotor, head, limb, and body motor signals; and strong motivational projections from the limbic system. Their discharge increases not only when an animal moves towards a sensory target, but also when it directs its attention to it. PPC lesions have the opposite effect: sensory inattention and neglect. The PPC does not seem (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   87 citations  
  • Searching for General Principles in Cognitive Performance: Reply to Commentators.Damian G. Stephen & Guy Van Orden - 2012 - Topics in Cognitive Science 4 (1):94-102.
    The commentators expressed concerns regarding the relevance and value of non-computational non-symbolic explanations of cognitive performance. But what counts as an “explanation” depends on the pre-theoretical assumptions behind the scenes of empirical science regarding the kinds of variables and relationships that are sought out in the first place, and some of the present disagreements stem from incommensurate assumptions. Traditional cognitive science presumes cognition to be a decomposable system of components interacting according to computational rules to generate cognitive performances (i.e., component-dominant (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Of cockroaches as kings.Robert J. Sternberg - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):91-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Models of memory: Wittgenstein and cognitive science.David G. Stern - 1991 - Philosophical Psychology 4 (2):203-18.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   46 citations  
  • Motor equivalence and distributed control: Evidence for nonspecific muscle commands.George E. Stelmach & Virginia A. Diggles - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):566-567.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Movement control views: From diversity to unity.R. B. Stein - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):568-577.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Learning, selection, and species.Kim Sterelny - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):90-91.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Categories, categorisation and development: Introspective knowledge is no threat to functionalism.Kim Sterelny - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):81-83.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Can computers be creative, or even disappointed?Robert J. Sternberg - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (3):553-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Good Old-Fashioned Artificial Intelligence” : Abandonment and Survival of the Computational Hypothesis of the Mind.Henri Stephanou - 2022 - Philosophia Scientiae:73-91.
    Dans cet article, nous interrogeons la désuétude du projet initial de l’intelligence artificielle, fondé conjointement avec la science cognitive, et partageant avec elle ce qu’on appela plus tard l’hypothèse computationnelle de l’esprit, c’est-à-dire l’idée que la pensée intelligente peut être décrite sous la forme de programmes informatiques. Si cette désuétude reflète en partie notre éloignement d’une période très particulière du xxe siècle, celle des années 1950 marquées par les angoisses de la guerre froide, nous souhaitons montrer qu’elle est sous-tendue par (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Artificial intelligence and its natural limits.Karl D. Stephan & Gyula Klima - 2021 - AI and Society (1):9-18.
    An argument with roots in ancient Greek philosophy claims that only humans are capable of a certain class of thought termed conceptual, as opposed to perceptual thought, which is common to humans, the higher animals, and some machines. We outline the most detailed modern version of this argument due to Mortimer Adler, who in the 1960s argued for the uniqueness of the human power of conceptual thought. He also admitted that if conceptual thought were ever manifested by machines, such an (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • The developmental history of an illusion.Keith E. Stanovich - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):80-81.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Neurological ballistic movements: Sampled data or intermittent open-loop control.Lawrence Stark - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (4):564-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • And then a miracle happens….Keith E. Stanovich - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):684-685.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Not All Computational Methods Are Effective Methods.Mark Sprevak - 2022 - Philosophies 7 (5):113.
    An effective method is a computational method that might, in principle, be executed by a human. In this paper, I argue that there are methods for computing that are not effective methods. The examples I consider are taken primarily from quantum computing, but these are only meant to be illustrative of a much wider class. Quantum inference and quantum parallelism involve steps that might be implemented in multiple physical systems, but cannot be implemented, or at least not at will, by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Kripke’s paradox and the Church–Turing thesis.Mark D. Sprevak - 2008 - Synthese 160 (2):285-295.
    Kripke (1982, Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press) presents a rule-following paradox in terms of what we meant by our past use of “plus”, but the same paradox can be applied to any other term in natural language. Many responses to the paradox concentrate on fixing determinate meaning for “plus”, or for a small class of other natural language terms. This raises a problem: how can these particular responses be generalised to the whole of natural language? (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Chinese Rooms and Program Portability.Mark D. Sprevak - 2007 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (4):755-776.
    I argue in this article that there is a mistake in Searle's Chinese room argument that has not received sufficient attention. The mistake stems from Searle's use of the Church-Turing thesis. Searle assumes that the Church-Turing thesis licences the assumption that the Chinese room can run any program. I argue that it does not, and that this assumption is false. A number of possible objections are considered and rejected. My conclusion is that it is consistent with Searle's argument to hold (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • What Are We to Think about Thought Experiments?Lawrence Souder - 2003 - Argumentation 17 (2):203-217.
    Arguments from thought experiment ask the reader to imagine some hypothetical, sometimes exotic, often fantastic, scenario for the sake of illustrating or countering some claim. Variously characterized as mental experimentation, imaginary cases, and even crazy cases, thought experiments figure into both scientific and philosophical arguments. They are often criticized for their fictive nature and for their lack of grounding. Nevertheless, they are common especially in arguments in ethics and philosophy of mind. Moreover, many thought experiments have spawned variations that attempt (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations