Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Prospects of enactivist approaches to intentionality and cognition.Tobias Schlicht & Tobias Starzak - 2019 - Synthese 198 (Suppl 1):89-113.
    We discuss various implications of some radical anti-representationalist views of cognition and what they have to offer with regard to the naturalization of intentionality and the explanation of cognitive phenomena. Our focus is on recent arguments from proponents of enactive views of cognition to the effect that basic cognition is intentional but not representational and that cognition is co-extensive with life. We focus on lower rather than higher forms of cognition, namely the question regarding the intentional and representational nature of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Psychoneural isomorphism: Historical background and current relevance.Eckart Scheerer - 1994 - Philosophical Psychology 7 (2):183-210.
    The relevance of Wolfgang K hler's psychoneural isomorphism principle to contemporary cognitive neuroscience is explored. K hler's approach to the mind—body problem is interpreted as a response to the foundational crisis of psychology at the beginning of the twentieth century. Some aspects of his isomorphism doctrine are discussed, with a view to reaching an interpretation that is both historically accurate and pertinent to issues currently debated in the philosophy of psychology. The principle was meant to be empirically verifiable. Accordingly, some (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • LOT, CTM, and the Elephant in the Room.Susan Schneider - 2009 - Synthese 170 (2):235 - 250.
    According to the language of thought (LOT) approach and the related computational theory of mind (CTM), thinking is the processing of symbols in an inner mental language that is distinct from any public language. Herein, I explore a deep problem at the heart of the LOT/CTM program—it has yet to provide a plausible conception of a mental symbol.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Judging machines: philosophical aspects of deep learning.Arno Schubbach - 2019 - Synthese 198 (2):1807-1827.
    Although machine learning has been successful in recent years and is increasingly being deployed in the sciences, enterprises or administrations, it has rarely been discussed in philosophy beyond the philosophy of mathematics and machine learning. The present contribution addresses the resulting lack of conceptual tools for an epistemological discussion of machine learning by conceiving of deep learning networks as ‘judging machines’ and using the Kantian analysis of judgments for specifying the type of judgment they are capable of. At the center (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  • Does the evolutionary perspective offer more than constraints?Wolfgang Schleidt - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):456-456.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does Separating Intentionality From Mental Representation Imply Radical Enactivism?Tobias Schlicht - 2018 - Frontiers in Psychology 9.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Do Emotions Represent Values?Laura Schroeter, François Schroeter & Karen Jones - 2015 - Dialectica 69 (3):357-380.
    This paper articulates what it would take to defend representationalism in the case of emotions – i.e. the claim that emotions attribute evaluative properties to target objects or events. We argue that representationalism faces a significant explanatory challenge that has not yet been adequately recognized. Proponents must establish that a representation relation linking emotions and value is explanatorily necessary. We use the case of perception to bring out the difficulties in meeting this explanatory challenge.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Are species intelligent?: Not a yes or no question.Jonathan Schull - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):94-108.
    Plant and animal species are information-processing entities of such complexity, integration, and adaptive competence that it may be scientifically fruitful to consider them intelligent. The possibility arises from the analogy between learning and evolution, and from recent developments in evolutionary science, psychology and cognitive science. Species are now described as spatiotemporally localized individuals in an expanded hierarchy of biological entities. Intentional and cognitive abilities are now ascribed to animal, human, and artificial intelligence systems that process information adaptively, and that manifest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Are species intelligent?: Not a yes or no question.Jonathan Schull - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):63-75.
    Plant and animal species are information-processing entities of such complexity, integration, and adaptive competence that it may be scientifically fruitful to consider them intelligent. The possibility arises from the analogy between learning and evolution, and from recent developments in evolutionary science, psychology and cognitive science. Species are now described as spatiotemporally localized individuals in an expanded hierarchy of biological entities. Intentional and cognitive abilities are now ascribed to animal, human, and artificial intelligence systems that process information adaptively, and that manifest (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   43 citations  
  • A Modular Neural Network Model of Concept Acquisition.Philippe G. Schyns - 1991 - Cognitive Science 15 (4):461-508.
    Previous neural network models of concept learning were mainly implemented with supervised learning schemes. However, studies of human conceptual memory have shown that concepts may be learned without a teacher who provides the category name to associate with exemplars. A modular neural network architecture that realizes concept acquisition through two functionally distinct operations, categorizing and naming, is proposed as an alternative. An unsupervised algorithm realizes the categorizing module by constructing representations of categories compatible with prototype theory. The naming module associates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • A Modular Neural Network Model of Concept Acquisition.Philippe G. Schyns - 1991 - Cognitive Science 15 (4):461-508.
    Previous neural network models of concept learning were mainly implemented with supervised learning schemes. However, studies of human conceptual memory have shown that concepts may be learned without a teacher who provides the category name to associate with exemplars. A modular neural network architecture that realizes concept acquisition through two functionally distinct operations, categorizing and naming, is proposed as an alternative. An unsupervised algorithm realizes the categorizing module by constructing representations of categories compatible with prototype theory. The naming module associates (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  • An attentional hierarchy.Peter A. Sandon - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (3):414-415.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Thinking without global generalisations: A cognitive defence of moral particularism.Nancy Salay - 2008 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 51 (4):390 – 411.
    In their article entitled “Ethical Particularism and Patterns”, Frank Jackson, Philip Pettit, and Michael Smith (JPS henceforth) argue that moral particularism is a cognitively implausible theory since it appears to entail the view that one might have a skill that is not grounded in an ability to recognise and represent natural patterns in the world. This charge echoes the complaints of computational theorists of cognition against their embodied cognition counterparts, namely that, theories of cognition that eschew talk of mental representation (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Misplaced predicates and misconstrued intelligence.Stanley N. Salthe - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):86-87.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Situating representational redescriptionin infants' pragmatic knowledge.Julie C. Rutkowska - 1994 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (4):726-727.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • “Intelligence” as description and as explanation.P. A. Russell - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):86-86.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Theory of Localist Representation and of a Purely Abstract Cognitive System: The Evidence from Cortical Columns, Category Cells, and Multisensory Neurons.Asim Roy - 2017 - Frontiers in Psychology 8.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Connectionism and the language of thought.Mark Rowlands - 1994 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45 (2):485-503.
    In an influential critique, Jerry Fodor and Zenon Pylyshyn point to the existence of a potentially devastating dilemma for connectionism (Fodor and Pylyshyn [1988]). Either connectionist models consist in mere associations of unstructured representations, or they consist in processes involving complex representations. If the former, connectionism is mere associationism, and will not be capable of accounting for very much of cognition. If the latter, then connectionist models concern only the implementation of cognitive processes, and are, therefore, not informative at the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Weak versus strong claims about the algorithmic level.Paul S. Rosenbloom - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):490-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Seeing truth or just seeming true?Adina Roskies - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):682-683.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Comments on Bechtel, levels of description and explanation in cognitive science.Jay F. Rosenberg - 1994 - Minds and Machines 4 (1):27-37.
    I begin by tracing some of the confusions regarding levels and reduction to a failure to distinguish two different principles according to which theories can be viewed as hierarchically arranged — epistemic authority and ontological constitution. I then argue that the notion of levels relevant to the debate between symbolic and connectionist paradigms of mental activity answers to neither of these models, but is rather correlative to the hierarchy of functional decompositions of cognitive tasks characteristic of homuncular functionalism. Finally, I (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A non‐representational approach to imagined action.Iris Rooij, Raoul M. Bongers & F. G. Haselager - 2002 - Cognitive Science 26 (3):345-375.
    This study addresses the dynamical nature of a “representation‐hungry” cognitive task involving an imagined action. In our experiment, participants were handed rods that systematically increased or decreased in length on subsequent trials. Participants were asked to judge whether or not they thought they could reach for a distant object with the hand‐held rod. The results are in agreement with a dynamical model, extended from Tuller, Case, Ding, and Kelso (1994). The dynamical effects observed in this study suggest that predictive judgments (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Useful ideas for exploiting time to engineer representations.Richard Rohwer - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (3):471-471.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A simple model from a powerful framework that spans levels of analysis.Timothy T. Rogers & James L. McClelland - 2008 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6):729-749.
    The commentaries reflect three core themes that pertain not just to our theory, but to the enterprise of connectionist modeling more generally. The first concerns the relationship between a cognitive theory and an implemented computer model. Specifically, how does one determine, when a model departs from the theory it exemplifies, whether the departure is a useful simplification or a critical flaw? We argue that the answer to this question depends partially upon the model's intended function, and we suggest that connectionist (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Systematic, unconscious thought is the place to anchor quantum mechanics in the mind.Thomas Roeper - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):681-682.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Implications of neural networks for how we think about brain function.David A. Robinson - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (4):644-655.
    Engineers use neural networks to control systems too complex for conventional engineering solutions. To examine the behavior of individual hidden units would defeat the purpose of this approach because it would be largely uninterpretable. Yet neurophysiologists spend their careers doing just that! Hidden units contain bits and scraps of signals that yield only arcane hints about network function and no information about how its individual units process signals. Most literature on single-unit recordings attests to this grim fact. On the other (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • It's a far cry from speech to language.Maritza Rivera-Gaxiola & Annette Karmiloff-Smith - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (4):645-646.
    We agree with Müller's epigenetic view of evolution and ontogeny and applaud his multilevel perspective. With him, we stress the importance in ontogeny of progressive specialisation rather than prewired structures. However, we argue that he slips from “speech” to “language” and that, in seeking homologies, these two levels need to be kept separate in the analysis of evolution and ontogeny.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Why this makes me think of that.Thierry Ripoll - 1998 - Thinking and Reasoning 4 (1):15 – 43.
    This study was aimed at explaining how and under what conditions surface similarity leads to the retrieval of an analogous base problem in LTM. Some elements of a theory of the organisation of knowledge in memory are proposed. Two levels of representation are distinguished. The first level represents directly accessible, local surface properties. The second level represents more abstract information pertaining to the category with which each analogous problem can be associated. Some results will be described showing that access to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Feedback from moral philosophy to cognitive science.Regina A. Rini - 2015 - Philosophical Psychology 28 (4):569-588.
    A popular argument form uses general theories of cognitive architecture to motivate conclusions about the nature of moral cognition. This paper highlights the possibility for modus tollens reversal of this argument form. If theories of cognitive architecture generate predictions for moral cognition, then tests of moral thinking provide feedback to cognitive science. In certain circumstances, philosophers' introspective attention to their own moral deliberations can provide unique data for these tests. Recognizing the possibility for this sort of feedback helps to illuminate (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • How human is SOAR?Roger W. Remington, Michael G. Shafto & Colleen M. Seifert - 1992 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 15 (3):455-455.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Is there more than one type of mental algorithm?Ronan G. Reilly - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):489-490.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Level of analysis is not a central issue.James A. Reggia - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (2):406-407.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Ways and means.Adam V. Reed - 1987 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10 (3):488-489.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The society of mind.George N. Reeke - 1991 - Artificial Intelligence 48 (3):341-348.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   32 citations  
  • The computational brain.George N. Reeke - 1996 - Artificial Intelligence 82 (1-2):381-391.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Editorial: Consciousness and Cognition: New Approaches.Michael Wright & Colette Ray - 1999 - Journal of Intelligent Systems 9 (5-6):297-306.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reverberations of Hebbian thinking.Josef P. Rauschecker - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):642-643.
    Cortical reverberations may induce synaptic changes that underlie developmental plasticity as well as long-term memory. They may be especially important for the consolidation of synaptic changes. Reverberations in cortical networks should have particular significance during development, when large numbers of new representations are formed. This includes the formation of representations across different sensory modalities.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Minds as connoting systems: Logic and the language of thought. [REVIEW]V. Rantala & Tere Vaden - 1997 - Erkenntnis 46 (3):315-334.
    The principal aim of this essay is to discuss some logical features of the so-called Classical model of cognitive architecture as it is advocated by J. Fodor and Z. Pylyshyn in their much discussed article 'Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis'. It is pointed out that their structural assumptions have consequences of a logical kind which call into question the view that the Classical architecture (in their sense) can be employed to model human cognition. It seems that the consequences (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Knowledge Representation: Two Kinds Of Emergence.Veikko Rantala - 2001 - Synthese 129 (2):195-209.
    Two different but closely related issues in current cognitive science will be considered in this essay. One is the controversial and extensively discussed question of how connectionist and symbolic representations of knowledge are related to each other. The other concerns the notion of connectionist learning and its relevance for the understanding of the distinction between propositional and nonpropositional knowledge. More specifically, I shall give an overview of a result in Rantala and Vadén (1994) establishing a limiting case correspondence between symbolic (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Prototypes and conceptual analysis.William Ramsey - 1992 - Topoi 11 (1):59-70.
    In this paper, I explore the implications of recent empirical research on concept representation for the philosophical enterprise of conceptual analysis. I argue that conceptual analysis, as it is commonly practiced, is committed to certain assumptions about the nature of our intuitive categorization judgments. I then try to show how these assumptions clash with contemporary accounts of concept representation in cognitive psychology. After entertaining an objection to my argument, I close by considering ways in which conceptual analysis might be altered (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  • Do connectionist representations earn their explanatory keep?William Ramsey - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):34-66.
    In this paper I assess the explanatory role of internal representations in connectionist models of cognition. Focusing on both the internal‘hidden’units and the connection weights between units, I argue that the standard reasons for viewing these components as representations are inadequate to bestow an explanatorily useful notion of representation. Hence, nothing would be lost from connectionist accounts of cognitive processes if we were to stop viewing the weights and hidden units as internal representations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   25 citations  
  • Do Connectionist Representations Earn Their Explanatory Keep?William Ramsey - 1997 - Mind and Language 12 (1):34-66.
    In this paper I assess the explanatory role of internal representations in connectionist models of cognition. Focusing on both the internal‘hidden’units and the connection weights between units, I argue that the standard reasons for viewing these components as representations are inadequate to bestow an explanatorily useful notion of representation. Hence, nothing would be lost from connectionist accounts of cognitive processes if we were to stop viewing the weights and hidden units as internal representations.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   19 citations  
  • Belief and cognitive architecture.William Ramsey - 1992 - Dialogue 31 (1):115-120.
    Considerable debate in philosophy of psychology has recently focussed upon two central themes. One concerns the ontological status of propositional attitudes like beliefs and desires, the other on the proper computational account of cognitive architecture. In the ontological debate, the two most prominent positions are eliminativism, which claims that commonsense psychology is false because there are no such things as beliefs and desires; and versions of intentional realism, which counters that beliefs and desires actually do exist in the mind/brain. In (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Outflanking the mind-body problem: Scientific progress in the history of psychology.Sam S. Rakover - 1992 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 22 (2):145–173.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the Validity of Simulating Stagewise Development by Means of PDP Networks: Application of Catastrophe Analysis and an Experimental Test of Rule‐Like Network Performance.Maartje E. J. Raijmakers, Sylvester Koten & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (1):101-136.
    This article addresses the ability of Parallel Distributed Processing (PDP) networks to generate stagewise cognitive development in accordance with Piaget's theory of cognitive epigenesis. We carried out a replication study of the simulation experiments by McClelland (1989) and McClelland and Jenkins (1991) in which a PDP network learns to solve balance scale problems. In objective tests motivated from catastrophe theory, a mathematical theory of transitions in epigenetical systems, no evidence for stage transitions in network performance was found. It is concluded (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  • On the Validity of Simulating Stagewise Development by Means of PDP Networks: Application of Catastrophe Analysis and an Experimental Test of Rule‐Like Network Performance.Maartje E. J. Raijmakers, Sylvester von Koten & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1996 - Cognitive Science 20 (1):101-136.
    This article addresses the ability of Parallel Distributed Processing (PDP) networks to generate stagewise cognitive development in accordance with Piaget's theory of cognitive epigenesis. We carried out a replication study of the simulation experiments by McClelland (1989) and McClelland and Jenkins (1991) in which a PDP network learns to solve balance scale problems. In objective tests motivated from catastrophe theory, a mathematical theory of transitions in epigenetical systems, no evidence for stage transitions in network performance was found. It is concluded (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • How to decide whether a neural representation is a cognitive concept?Maartje E. J. Raijmakers & Peter C. M. Molenaar - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):641-642.
    A distinction should be made between the formation of stimulus-driven associations and cognitive concepts. To test the learning mode of a neural network, we propose a simple and classic input-output test: the discrimination shift task. Feed-forward PDP models appear to form stimulus-driven associations. A Hopfield network should be extended to apply the test.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Recombinant Enaction: Manipulatives Generate New Procedures in the Imagination, by Extending and Recombining Action Spaces.Jeenath Rahaman, Harshit Agrawal, Nisheeth Srivastava & Sanjay Chandrasekharan - 2018 - Cognitive Science 42 (2):370-415.
    Manipulation of physical models such as tangrams and tiles is a popular approach to teaching early mathematics concepts. This pedagogical approach is extended by new computational media, where mathematical entities such as equations and vectors can be virtually manipulated. The cognitive and neural mechanisms supporting such manipulation-based learning—particularly how actions generate new internal structures that support problem-solving—are not understood. We develop a model of the way manipulations generate internal traces embedding actions, and how these action-traces recombine during problem-solving. This model (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The analysis of the learning needs to be deeper.John E. Rager - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (3):505-506.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark