Switch to: References

Citations of:

A History of the Mathematical Theory of Probability From the Time of Pascal to That of Laplace

Cambridge and London: Macmillan and Company: London (1865)

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Three pseudo-paradoxes in?quantum? decision theory: Apparent effects of observation on probability and utility.Louis Marinoff - 1993 - Theory and Decision 35 (1):55-73.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Statistics — a child of eugenics?Hans Kalmus - 1987 - Biology and Philosophy 2 (1):107-115.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Logic with numbers.Colin Howson - 2007 - Synthese 156 (3):491-512.
    Many people regard utility theory as the only rigorous foundation for subjective probability, and even de Finetti thought the betting approach supplemented by Dutch Book arguments only good as an approximation to a utility-theoretic account. I think that there are good reasons to doubt this judgment, and I propose an alternative, in which the probability axioms are consistency constraints on distributions of fair betting quotients. The idea itself is hardly new: it is in de Finetti and also Ramsey. What is (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • On de Movire's solutions of the problem of duration of play 1708–1718.A. Hald - 1988 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 38 (2):109-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Paradigm transitions in mathematics.Claire L. Parkinson - 1987 - Philosophia Mathematica (2):127-150.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Resolving conflicting information.John Cantwell - 1998 - Journal of Logic, Language and Information 7 (2):191-220.
    Information received from different sources can be inconsistent. Even when the sources of information can be ordered on the basis of their trustworthiness, it turns out that extracting an acceptable notion of support for information is a non-trivial matter, as is the question what information a rational agent should accept. Here it is shown how a support ordering on the information can be generated and how it can be used to decide what information to accept and what not to accept. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • The framing of the fundamental probability set: A historical case study on the context of mathematical discovery.Daniel G. Campos - 2009 - Perspectives on Science 17 (4):pp. 385-416.
    I address the philosophical debate over whether the mathematical theory of probability arose on the basis of empirical observations or of purely theoretical speculations. The debate tends to pose a strict dichotomy between empirical problem-solving and pure theorizing. I alternatively suggest that, in the case of mathematical probability, an empirical problem-context acted as an enabling condition for the possibility of mathematical innovation, but that the activity of the early mathematical probabilists gradually became the study of a theoretical system of ideas. (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Burnside’s engagement with the “modern theory of statistics”.John Aldrich - 2008 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 63 (1):51-79.
    The group theorist William Burnside devoted much of the last decade of his life to probability and statistics. The work led to contact with Ronald Fisher who was on his way to becoming the leading statistician of the age and with Karl Pearson, the man Fisher supplanted. Burnside corresponded with Fisher for nearly three years until their correspondence ended abruptly. This paper examines Burnside’s interactions with the statisticians and looks more generally at his work in probability and statistics.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Genius in science.Joseph Agassi - 1975 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5 (2):145-161.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • ‘Everybody makes errors’: The intersection of De Morgan's Logic and Probability, 1837 – 1847.Adrian Rice - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (4):289-305.
    For Ivor Grattan-Guinness on the occasion of his retirement. The work of Augustus De Morgan on symbolic logic in the mid-nineteenth century is familiar to historians of logic and mathematics alike. What is less well known is his work on probability and, more specifically, the use of probabilistic ideas and methods in his logic. The majority of De Morgan's work on probability was undertaken around 1837???1838, with his earliest publications on logic appearing from 1839, a period which culminated with the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Diseño epistémico de métodos de votación: lecciones matemáticas para la democracia.Marc Jiménez-Rolland - 2021 - In Anna Estany & Mario Gensollen (eds.), Diseño institucional e innovaciones democráticas. UAA-UAB. pp. 99-121.
    Frente a problemas de decisión colectiva de cierta complejidad, distintos métodos de votación pueden considerarse igualmente democráticos. Ante esta situación, argumento que es posible investigar cuáles de esos métodos producen mejores resultados epistémicos sobre asuntos fácticos. Comienzo ilustrando la relación entre democracia y métodos de votación con un sencillo ejemplo. Muestro cómo el uso de modelos idealizados permite descubrir algunas propiedades de los métodos de votación; varios de estos descubrimientos muestran que, frente a problemas de cierta complejidad, no hay una (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Truthlikeness.Ilkka Niiniluoto - 1987 - Dordrecht: Reidel.
    The modern discussion on the concept of truthlikeness was started in 1960. In his influential Word and Object, W. V. O. Quine argued that Charles Peirce's definition of truth as the limit of inquiry is faulty for the reason that the notion 'nearer than' is only "defined for numbers and not for theories". In his contribution to the 1960 International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science at Stan­ ford, Karl Popper defended the opposite view by defining a compara­tive (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • On the normative dimension of the St. Petersburg paradox.David Teira - 2006 - Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 37 (2):210-223.
    In this paper I offer an account of the normative dimension implicit in D. Bernoulli’s expected utility functions by means of an analysis of the juridical metaphors upon which the concept of mathematical expectation was moulded. Following a suggestion by the late E. Coumet, I show how this concept incorporated a certain standard of justice which was put in question by the St. Petersburg paradox. I contend that Bernoulli would have solved it by introducing an alternative normative criterion rather than (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Philosophy as conceptual engineering: Inductive logic in Rudolf Carnap's scientific philosophy.Christopher F. French - 2015 - Dissertation, University of British Columbia
    My dissertation explores the ways in which Rudolf Carnap sought to make philosophy scientific by further developing recent interpretive efforts to explain Carnap’s mature philosophical work as a form of engineering. It does this by looking in detail at his philosophical practice in his most sustained mature project, his work on pure and applied inductive logic. I, first, specify the sort of engineering Carnap is engaged in as involving an engineering design problem and then draw out the complications of design (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Representation and Invariance of Scientific Structures.Patrick Suppes - 2002 - CSLI Publications (distributed by Chicago University Press).
    An early, very preliminary edition of this book was circulated in 1962 under the title Set-theoretical Structures in Science. There are many reasons for maintaining that such structures play a role in the philosophy of science. Perhaps the best is that they provide the right setting for investigating problems of representation and invariance in any systematic part of science, past or present. Examples are easy to cite. Sophisticated analysis of the nature of representation in perception is to be found already (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   143 citations  
  • The Enigma Of Probability.Nick Ergodos - 2014 - Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics 2 (1):37-71.
    Using “brute reason” I will show why there can be only one valid interpretation of probability. The valid interpretation turns out to be a further refinement of Popper’s Propensity interpretation of probability. Via some famous probability puzzles and new thought experiments I will show how all other interpretations of probability fail, in particular the Bayesian interpretations, while these puzzles do not present any difficulties for the interpretation proposed here. In addition, the new interpretation casts doubt on some concepts often taken (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a Grammar of Bayesian Confirmation.Vincenzo Crupi, Roberto Festa & Carlo Buttasi - 2009 - In M. Suàrez, M. Dorato & M. Rèdei (eds.), EPSA Epistemology and Methodology of Science: Launch of the European Philosophy of Science Association. Springer. pp. 73--93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • The rule of succession.Sandy L. Zabell - 1989 - Erkenntnis 31 (2-3):283 - 321.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   27 citations  
  • Les risques majeurs et l'action publique.Céline Grislain-Letremy, Reza Lahidji & Philippe Mongin - 2012 - Paris: La Documentation Française.
    Par risques majeurs, on entend ceux qui s’attachent à des événements dont les conséquences défavorables, pour l’humanité ou pour l’environnement, sont d’une gravité exceptionnelle. On n’ajoutera ni que ces événements sont d’une intensité physique extrême, ni qu’ils surviennent rarement, car ce n’est pas toujours le cas. Seuls des risques majeurs de nature civile seront considérés dans cet ouvrage, et il s'agira, plus limitativement, de risques naturels, comme ceux d’inondation et de submersion marine, illustrés par la tempête Xynthia en 2010, de (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Density curves in the theory of Errors.Oscar Sheynin - 1995 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 49 (2):163-196.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The special status of mathematical probability: a historical sketch.Xavier De Scheemaekere & Ariane Szafarz - 2008 - Epistemologia 32 (1):91.
    The history of the mathematical probability includes two phases: 1) From Pascal and Fermat to Laplace, the theory gained in application fields; 2) In the first half of the 20th Century, two competing axiomatic systems were respectively proposed by von Mises in 1919 and Kolmogorov in 1933. This paper places this historical sketch in the context of the philosophical complexity of the probability concept and explains the resounding success of Kolmogorov’s theory through its ability to avoid direct interpretation. Indeed, unlike (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Buffon, Price, and Laplace: Scientific attribution in the 18th century.S. L. Zabell - 1988 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 39 (2):173-181.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Pascal. Entre la geometría y la filosofía natural.Carlos M. Madrid Casado - 2019 - Metatheoria – Revista de Filosofía E Historia de la Ciencia 10:27--44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Bertrand's work on probability.Oscar Sheynin - 1994 - Archive for History of Exact Sciences 48 (2):155-199.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • A List of Books on the History of Science. January, 1911.Aksel G. S. John Crerar Library, Reginald Broderick Josephson & Gordon - 1911 - Printed by Order of the Board of Directors.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark