Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Consciousness and motor control.Arthur C. Danto - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):540-541.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The ability versus intentionality aspects of unconscious mental processes.Maria Czyzewska, Thomas Hill & Pawel Lewicki - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):602-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Aspects and algorithms.Andy Clark - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):601-602.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Accessibility “in principle”.Noam Chomsky - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):600-601.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Conscious mental episodes and skill acquisition.Richard A. Carlson - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):599-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Intention itself will disappear when its mechanisms are known.Bruce Bridgeman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):598-599.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Free will and the functions of consciousness.Bruce Bridgeman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):540-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   35 citations  
  • Problems with the psychophysics of intention.Bruno G. Breitmeyer - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):539-540.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   53 citations  
  • Consciousness and accessibility.Ned Block - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):596-598.
    This is my first publication of the distinction between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness, though not using quite those terms. It ends with this: "The upshot is this: If Searle is using the access sense of "consciousness," his argument doesn't get to first base. If, as is more likely, he intends the what-it-is-like sense, his argument depends on assumptions about issues that the cognitivist is bound to regard as deeply unsettled empirical questions." Searle replies: "He refers to what he calls (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   125 citations  
  • Ontogeny and intentionality.Philip David Zelazo & J. Steven Reznick - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):631-632.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • Consciousness, historical inversion, and cognitive science.Andrew W. Young - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):630-631.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Pardon, your dualism is showing.Charles C. Wood - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):557-558.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Neural/mental chronometry and chronotheology.Gerald S. Wasserman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):556-557.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Is the mind conscious, functional, or both?Max Velmans - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):629-630.
    What, in essence, characterizes the mind? According to Searle, the potential to be conscious provides the only definitive criterion. Thus, conscious states are unquestionably "mental"; "shallow unconscious" states are also "mental" by virtue of their capacity to be conscious (at least in principle); but there are no "deep unconscious mental states" - i.e. those rules and procedures without access to consciousness, inferred by cognitive science to characterize the operations of the unconscious mind are not mental at all. Indeed, according to (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   105 citations  
  • Nineteenth-century psychology and twentieth-century electrophysiology do not mix.C. H. Vanderwolf - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):555-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conscious wants and self-awareness.Robert Van Gulick - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):555-556.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  • Mind before matter?Geoffrey Underwood & Pekka Niemi - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):554-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Conscious and unconscious representation of aspectual shape in cognitive science.Geoffrey Underwood - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):628-629.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Unintended thought and nonconscious inferences exist.James S. Uleman & Jennifer K. Uleman - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):627-628.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The possibility of irreducible intentionality.Charles Taylor - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):626-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The uncertainty principle in psychology.John S. Stamm - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):553-554.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • The neurophysiology of consicousness and the unconscious.Christine A. Skarda - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):625-626.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unconscious mental states do have an aspectual shape.Howard Shevrin - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):624-625.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Who is computing with the brain?John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):632-642.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   58 citations  
  • Consciousness, explanatory inversion and cognitive science.John R. Searle - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):585-642.
    Cognitive science typically postulates unconscious mental phenomena, computational or otherwise, to explain cognitive capacities. The mental phenomena in question are supposed to be inaccessible in principle to consciousness. I try to show that this is a mistake, because all unconscious intentionality must be accessible in principle to consciousness; we have no notion of intrinsic intentionality except in terms of its accessibility to consciousness. I call this claim the The argument for it proceeds in six steps. The essential point is that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   282 citations  
  • When functions are causes.Jonathan Schull - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):622-624.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious intention is a mental fiat.Eckart Scheerer - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):552-553.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Are the origins of any mental process available to introspection?Michael D. Rugg - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):552-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On being accessible to consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):621-621.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • Sensory events with variable central latencies provide inaccurate clocks.Gary B. Rollman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):551-552.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Timing volition: Questions of what and when about W.James L. Ringo - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):550-551.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  • Constituent causation and the reality of mind.Georges Rey - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):620-621.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  • Somebody flew over Searle's ontological prison.Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):618-619.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Brain physiology and the unconscious initiation of movements.R. Näätänen - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):549-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Libet's dualism.R. J. Nelson - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):550-550.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • The concept of consciousness: The personal meaning.Thomas Natsoulas - 1991 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour 21 (September):339-67.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • The concept of consciousness: The personal meaning.Thomas Natsoulas - 1991 - Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour (September) 339 (September):339-367.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Conscious decisions.Chris Mortensen - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):548-549.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • The causal capacities of linguistic rules.Alice ter Meulen - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):626-627.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Conscious and unconscious processes: Same or different?Philip M. Merikle & Jim Cheesman - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):547-548.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Zombies are people, too.Drew McDermott - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):617-618.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Does cognitive science need “real” intentionality?Robert J. Matthews - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):616-617.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Toward a psychophysics of intention.Lawrence E. Marks - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):547-547.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Do we “control” our brains?Donald M. MacKay - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):546-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   38 citations  
  • Loose connections: Four problems in Searie's argument for the “Connection Principle”.Dan Lloyd - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):615-616.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • What's it like to be a gutbrain?John Limber - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):614-615.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Unconscious cerebral initiative and the role of conscious will in voluntary action.Benjamin Libet - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):529-66.
    Voluntary acts are preceded by electrophysiological (RPs). With spontaneous acts involving no preplanning, the main negative RP shift begins at about200 ms. Control experiments, in which a skin stimulus was timed (S), helped evaluate each subject's error in reporting the clock times for awareness of any perceived event.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   760 citations  
  • Theory and evidence relating cerebral processes to conscious will.Benjamin Libet - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):558-566.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Consciousness as an experimental variable: Problems of definition, practice, and interpretation.Richard Latto - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):545-546.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   33 citations  
  • Is Searle conscious?John C. Kulli - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):614-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark