Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Communication and consciousness: A neural network conjecture.N. A. Schmajuk & E. Axelrad - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):695-696.
    The communicative aspects of the contents of consciousness are analyzed in the framework of a neural network model of animal communication. We discuss some issues raised by Gray, such as the control of the contents of consciousness, the adaptive value of consciousness, conscious and unconscious behaviors, and the nature of a model's consciousness.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Analogy in Terms of Identity, Equivalence, Similarity, and Their Cryptomorphs.Marcin J. Schroeder - 2019 - Philosophies 4 (2):32.
    Analogy belongs to the class of concepts notorious for a variety of definitions generating continuing disputes about their preferred understanding. Analogy is typically defined by or at least associated with similarity, but as long as similarity remains undefined this association does not eliminate ambiguity. In this paper, analogy is considered synonymous with a slightly generalized mathematical concept of similarity which under the name of tolerance relation has been the subject of extensive studies over several decades. In this approach, analogy can (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wollheim on Collingwood.R. Scalafani - 1976 - Philosophy 51 (197):353-359.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Beauvoir-in-America: Understanding, Concrete Experience, and Beauvoir's Appropriation of Heidegger in America Day by Day.Alexander Ruch - 2009 - Hypatia 24 (4):104 - 129.
    This paper reads Simone de Beauvoir's travel journal "America Day by Day" for its philosophical content. I argue that this work provides a unique approach to feminist, embodied philosophy, one that has been overlooked by the categorization of her writing into philosophical works and feminist ones. Such an approach, I contend, is enacted here through her use of Heidegger's concept of the everyday to inform her own treatment of understanding and experience.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein and Friendship.Beth Savickey - 2014 - Philosophical Investigations 37 (3):185-194.
    In his article “It's a Wonderful Life,” Ronald Hall connects Wittgenstein's last words with Frank Capra's 1946 film. His analysis focuses on the concept of wonder, but he misses one of the most important aspects of both the film and Wittgenstein's last words: the significance of friendship. This is philosophically (and biographically) important because it raises questions about aspect-seeing, friendship and everyday life. Wittgenstein's final words provide a striking example of the philosophical complexity of his life and work.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Searle's demon and the brain simulator.Steven F. Savitt - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):342-343.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Postmodernism and Philosophy of Science: A Critical Engagement.Raphael Sassower - 1993 - Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23 (4):426-445.
    This essay examines critically two related claims: first, that postmodernism and philosophy of science depend on each other in a manner similar to the Enlightenment and Romanticism, that is, they respond and dispute each other's claims; and second, that what underlies and emanates from both postmodernism and philosophy of science is a political perspective and commitment. These claims suggest not only the possibility of translating from one area to the other when they are critically engaged with each other but also (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Theoretical Childhood and Adulthood: Plato’s Account of Human Intellectual Development.Susanna Saracco - 2016 - Philosophia 44 (3):845-863.
    The Platonic description of the cognitive development of the human being is a crucial part of his philosophy. This account emphasizes not only the existence of phases of rational growth but also the need that the cognitive progress of the individuals is investigated further. I will reconstruct what rational growth is for Plato in light of the deliberate choice of the philosopher to leave incomplete his schematization of human intellectual development. I will argue that this is a means chosen by (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Psyches Therapeia: Therapeutic Dimensions in Heidegger and Wittgenstein.Robert Sanchez Jr & Robert Stolorow - 2013 - Comparative and Continental Philosophy 5 (1):67-80.
    This article explores the philosophies of Heidegger and Wittgenstein to illustrate the thesis that philosophy is a human activity exhibiting a unity of investigative and therapeutic aims. For both philosophers, the purpose of philosophical concepts is to point toward a path of transformation rather than to explain. For both, a first step on this path is the recognition of constraining illusions, whether conventional or metaphysical. For both, such illusions are sedimented in linguistic practices, and for both, philosophical investigation is a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • In Defence of Four Socratic Doctrines.Constantine Sandis - 2008 - Think 6 (17-18):85-98.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • What Is Wrong with Hacker's Wittgenstein? On Grammar, Context and Sense‐Determination.Tamara Dobler - 2013 - Philosophical Investigations 36 (3):231-250.
    Peter Hacker defends an interpretation of the later Wittgenstein's notion of grammar, according to which the inherently general grammatical rules are sufficient for sense-determination. My aim is to show that this interpretation fails to account for an important contextualist shift in Wittgenstein's views on sense-determination. I argue that Hacker attributes to the later Wittgenstein a rule-based, combinatorial account of sense, which Wittgenstein puts forward in the Tractatus. I propose that this is not how we should interpret the later Wittgenstein because (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • A tale of two intentions: Intending what an utterance means and intending what an utterance achieves.Robert E. Sanders - 2015 - Pragmatics and Society 6 (4):475-501.
    Speaker intention is conceptualized as a property of utterances in context, not speakers; it is based on communally shared knowledge of discursive means to ends. The article’s main theoretical claim is that utterances, in addition to being produced with an intention about their pragmatic meaning, are also produced with an intention to bring about some post-interactional end result. Both types of intention bear on the utterance’s pragmatic meaning. Empirical aspects of the theoretical difference between these two types of speaker intention (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arguing with Images as Extended Cognition.Cristián Santibáñez - 2018 - Informal Logic 38 (4):531-549.
    In this paper the role of images in argumentative settings is analyzed from a cognitive angle. In particular, the proposal of this paper is to see visual argumentation as a specific form of extended and distributed cognition. In order to develop this idea, some of Wittgenstein’s insights are used to put evidence produced by research on temporal-spatial reasoning processes into philosophical perspective. Some contemporary argumentative analyses of visual argumentation are also discussed using commercial and political examples. The paper finishes with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • An Inquiry into a Normative Concept of Legal Efficacy.Andre Santos Campos - 2016 - Ratio Juris 29 (4):460-477.
    This essay argues that legal efficacy understood as existent binding force and as dominance of a system of coercion vis-à-vis competing systems is not strictly a matter of fact, but involves what can be termed justified normativity in a factual context. The argument is divided into four sections. The first three sections describe different dimensions of a normative concept of legal efficacy applied to legal systems: efficacy as persuasiveness, as indirect communication, and as constitutive obedience. The final section focuses on (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Understanding and integration.Jerry Samet - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (2):341-342.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • How do we know when private events control behavior?Kurt Salzinger - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (4):660-661.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy, Translation and the Anxieties of Inclusion.Naoko Saito - 2018 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 52 (2):197-215.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Glauben, wissen und wahrscheinlichkeit. Systeme der epistemischen logik.Kazem Sadegh-Zadeh - 1982 - Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 3 (2):297-307.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Being-on-the-bench: An existential analysis of the substitute in sport.Emily Ryall - 2008 - Sport, Ethics and Philosophy 2 (1):56 – 70.
    Being a substitute in sport appears to contradict the rationale behind being involved in that sport, especially in those sports whereby substitutes frequently remain unused or are brought on to the field of play for the final moments of that game. For the coach or manager, substitutes function as a way to improve the team achieving a particular end, namely to win the game; whether to replace an injured or tired player, to change a team’s structure or tactics, to complete (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • The Linguistic Linkage Compulsion: A Phenomenological Account.Horst Ruthrof - 2023 - Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 54 (2):203-220.
    Although the semantic insights about natural language produced so far by neuroscientific research have been meagre, (Pulvermüller 2010) they have provided one important empirical finding which lang...
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Species as individuals: Logical, biological, and philosophical problems.Michael Ruse - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):299-300.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • On leaving your children wrapped in thought.James Russell - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):76-77.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Verbal hallucinations and information processing.Bjørn Rishovd Rund - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):531-532.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   48 citations  
  • The logic of representation.William W. Rozeboom - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):385-386.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The dark side of Skinnerian epistemology.William W. Rozeboom - 1984 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 7 (4):533-535.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Average behaviorism is unedifying.William W. Rozeboom - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):712-714.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arguing for the Natural Ontological Attitude.Joseph Rouse - 1988 - PSA Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1988 (1):294-301.
    In several recent papers, Arthur Fine has developed a far-reaching attack upon both the standard realist interpretations of science and their most prominent anti-realist alternatives (1986a, 1986b, 1986c). In their place, Fine proposes not another position on the realist/anti-realist axis, but an attitude toward science, the “natural ontological attitude” (NOA), which is supposed to remove any felt need for a philosophical interpretation of science.In this paper I will be concerned with Fine’s reasons for adopting NOA rather than his arguments against (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Typologies: Obstacles and opportunities in scientific change.Alexander Rosenberg - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):298-299.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Review of Rationality in economics. [REVIEW]Don Ross - 2009 - Economics and Philosophy 25 (3):403-410.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Rationality and Common Sense.Jacob Joshua Ross - 1978 - Philosophy 53 (205):374-381.
    In everyday arguments we often meet with such phrases as ‘That's rational, it is mere common sense’ used in conjunction to approve of or back up some particular statement. The juxtaposition of these everyday locutions embodies a profound truth, the truth, namely, that the basis of rational communication between human beings is plain common sense. I call this point profound because it has been missed in all the discussions about rationality and its basis that I know; certainly its elusiveness thus (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy in Law? A Legal‐Philosophical Inquiry.Michel Rosenfeld - 2014 - Ratio Juris 27 (1):1-20.
    Going beyond the debate between positivists and proponents of natural law, there is a controversy over whether there can or ought to be “philosophy in law” (i.e., whether anything within the subject‐matter of philosophy can also become part of the subject‐matter of law). According to Luhmann's autopoietic theory, law is a normatively closed system and accordingly remains completely independent from philosophy. Dworkin, on the other hand, asserts that constitutional law depends for its coherence and integrity on being encompassed within a (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On being accessible to consciousness.David M. Rosenthal - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):621-621.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   13 citations  
  • On Creation, Cave Art and Perception: a Doxological Approach.Mats Rosengren - 2007 - Thesis Eleven 90 (1):79-96.
    The discovery of Palaeolithic cave art in the late 19th century entails many problems, some of which are perceptual. Presenting doxology as a post-phenomenological way of approaching epistemic and perceptual questions, this article draws on the problematics of cave art and contemporary cognitive science to discuss the process of perception — what it takes to see what one sees — in caves (and elsewhere). The article concludes that in order to see and perceive anything at all, both our physical and (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Many a slip 'twixt external and internal representation.David Rose - 1989 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12 (1):93-93.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Eidetic imagery is not a ghost.Paul A. Roodin & Erol F. Giray - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):614-615.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Gendered Reason: Sex Metaphor and Conceptions of Reason.Phyllis Rooney - 1991 - Hypatia 6 (2):77 - 103.
    Reason has regularly been portrayed and understood in terms of images and metaphors that involve the exclusion or denigration of some element-body, passion, nature, instinct-that is cast as "feminine." Drawing upon philosophical insight into metaphor, I examine the impact of this gendering of reason. I argue that our conceptions of mind, reason, unreason, female, and male have been distorted. The politics of "rational" discourse has been set up in ways that still subtly but powerfully inhibit the voice and agency of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   22 citations  
  • Tractatus 6 Reconsidered: An Algorithmic Alternative to Wittgenstein's Trade-Off.A. Roman & J. Gomułka - forthcoming - History and Philosophy of Logic:1-18.
    Wittgenstein's conception of the general form of a truth function given in thesis 6 can be presented as a sort of a trade-off: the author of the Tractatus is unable to reconcile the simplicity of his original idea of a series of forms with the simplicity of his generalisation of Sheffer's stroke; therefore, he is forced to sacrifice one of them. As we argue in this paper, the choice he makes – to weaken the logical constraints put on the concept (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Representations and cognition.H. L. Roitblat - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):394-406.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein's Critique of Set Theory.Victor Rodych - 2000 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 38 (2):281-319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  • Misunderstanding Gödel: New Arguments about Wittgenstein and New Remarks by Wittgenstein.Victor Rodych - 2003 - Dialectica 57 (3):279-313.
    The long‐standing issue of Wittgenstein's controversial remarks on Gödel's Theorem has recently heated up in a number of different and interesting directions [,, ]. In their, Juliet Floyd and Hilary Putnam purport to argue that Wittgenstein's‘notorious’ “Contains a philosophical claim of great interest,” namely, “if one assumed. that →P is provable in Russell's system one should… give up the “translation” of P by the English sentence ‘P is not provable’,” because if ωP is provable in PM, PM is ω ‐inconsistent, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Gödel's ‘Disproof’ of the Syntactical Viewpoint.Victor Rodych - 2001 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (4):527-555.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Action in Law’s Empire: Judging in the Deliberative Mode.Veronica Rodriguez-Blanco - 2016 - Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 29 (2):431-456.
    Dworkin advances the view that judges decide legal cases according to constructive interpretation. The aim of constructive interpretation is to justify the coercion of the State. A trivial implication of this view is that officials and citizens will comply with the law because of the justification that has been advanced by judges in their exercise of constructive interpretation. Consequently, neither officials nor citizens comply with the law because they have been coerced or because they have been simply told to do (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The visualization continuum.Cynthia Roberts-Gray - 1979 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 2 (4):614-614.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Demography of the Kingdom of Ends.Daniel N. Robinson - 1994 - Philosophy 69 (267):5-19.
    In the Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals' Kant is explicit, sometimes to the point of peevishness, in denying anthropology and psychology any part or place in his moral science. Recognizing that this will strike many as counterintuitive he is unrepentant: ‘We require no skill to make ourselves intelligible to the multitude once we renounce all profundity of thought’. That the doctrine to be defended is not exemplified in daily experience or even in imaginable encounters is necessitated by the very (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Premature closure of controversial issues concerning animal memory representations.William A. Roberts - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):384-385.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Emerging in the image of God to know good and evil.Jason P. Roberts - 2011 - Zygon 46 (2):471-481.
    Abstract. Found in the Primeval History in Genesis, the biblical concepts of the “image of God” and the “knowledge of good and evil” remain integral to Christian anthropology, especially with regard to the theologoumena of “fall” and “original sin.” All of these symbols are remained important and appropriate descriptors of the human condition, provided that contemporary academic theological anthropology engages in constructive dialogue with the natural and social sciences. Using Paul Ricoeur's notion of “second naïveté experience,” I illustrate the hermeneutical (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • International plovers or just dump brids?Carolyn A. Ristau - 1983 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 6 (3):373-375.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Deception: A need for theory and ethology.Carolyn A. Ristau - 1988 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 11 (2):262-263.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Arbitrariness no argument against adaption.Mark Ridley - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):756-756.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Winch on Understanding Other People.Duncan Richter - 2018 - Philosophical Investigations 41 (4):399-417.
    This paper aims to identify the main points that Peter Winch makes, or reminders that he offers, about understanding ourselves and others. It would no doubt be possible to construct a theory out of these ideas, but I try to avoid giving the impression that Winch does so. Instead, the most Wittgensteinian approach to the subject is, as Winch does, to describe, remind and thereby clarify, without putting forward any kind of questionable hypothesis. Winch's work brings out the fact that (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation