Switch to: References

Add citations

You must login to add citations.
  1. Consciousness and its (dis)contents.Jeffrey A. Gray - 1995 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18 (4):703-722.
    The first claim in the target article was that there is as yet no transparent, causal account of the relations between consciousness and brain-and-behaviour. That claim remains firm. The second claim was that the contents of consciousness consist, psychologically, of the outputs of a comparator system; the third consisted of a description of the brain mechanisms proposed to instantiate the comparator. In order to defend these claims against criticism, it has been necessary to clarify the distinction between consciousness-as-such and the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Beyond Burrhus and behaviorism: Dennett defused.Thomas Gray - 1985 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 8 (4):762-763.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Teaching critical thinking: The struggle against dogmatism.Cristiane Maria Cornelia Gottschalk - 2018 - Educational Philosophy and Theory 50 (5):469-477.
    From a Wittgensteinian point of view, my goal is to argue against the idea that teaching critical thinking should have as one of its aims the possibility of changing or adapting our deeply held beliefs. As pointed out by the Austrian philosopher in On Certainty, we have a world-picture which is neither true nor false, but above all, ‘it is the substratum of all my enquiring and asserting’. Besides that, in his remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough, Wittgenstein insists on the (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The Experience of Perceptual Familiarity.Gordon Lyon - 1996 - Philosophy 71 (275):83 - 100.
    Psychologists have recently turned their attention to the nature of the recognition involved in judgment of familiarity. It has been suggested that, apart from judging a stimulus to be familiar when one is able to recall a context in which it was previously perceived, subjects are also able to judge that something is familiar merely on the basis of its faster perceptual processing.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Teleology and agency in speech production.Robert M. Gordon - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):525-525.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Self-ascription of belief and desire.Robert M. Gordon - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):45-46.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Scientism, interpretation, and criticism.Philip S. Gorski - 1990 - Zygon 25 (3):279-307.
    What is the relationship between natural science, social science, and religion? The dominant paradigm in contemporary social science is scientism, the attempt to apply the methods of natural science to the study of society. However, scientism is problematic: it rests on a conception of natural science that cannot be sustained. Natural scientific understanding emerges from an instrumental and objectifying relation to the world; it is oriented toward control and manipulation of the physical world. Social‐scientific understanding, by contrast, must begin with (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • First person representations need a methodology based on simulation or theory.Robert M. Gordon - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):130-131.
    Although their thesis is generally sound, Barresi & Moore give insufficient attention to the need for a methodology, whether simulation based or theory-based, for choosing among alternative possible matches of first person and third person information. This choice must be sensitive to contextual information, including past behavior. Moreover, apart from simulation or theory, first person information would not help predict future behavior.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Some distinctions among representations.M. Gopnik - 1982 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 5 (3):378-379.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Theories and illusions.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):90-100.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  • Theories and qualities.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):44-45.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • How we know our minds: The illusion of first-person knowledge of intentionality.Alison Gopnik - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):1-14.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   260 citations  
  • A Rube Goldberg machine par excellence.Myrna Gopnik - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):734-735.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Reasoning About Relations.Geoffrey P. Goodwin & Philip Johnson-Laird - 2005 - Psychological Review 112 (2):468-493.
    Inferences about spatial, temporal, and other relations are ubiquitous. This article presents a novel model-based theory of such reasoning. The theory depends on 5 principles. The structure of mental models is iconic as far as possible. The logical consequences of relations emerge from models constructed from the meanings of the relations and from knowledge. Individuals tend to construct only a single, typical model. They spontaneously develop their own strategies for relational reasoning. Regardless of strategy, the difficulty of an inference depends (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   30 citations  
  • One statistician's perspective.Colin Goodall - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):133-134.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • On the relativity of quantitative genetic variance components.Charles J. Goodnight - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (1):134-135.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • A Rational Analysis of Rule-Based Concept Learning.Noah D. Goodman, Joshua B. Tenenbaum, Jacob Feldman & Thomas L. Griffiths - 2008 - Cognitive Science 32 (1):108-154.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   66 citations  
  • XII—Is There a Problem of Other Minds?Anil Gomes - 2011 - Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 111 (3pt3):353-373.
    Scepticism is sometimes expressed about whether there is any interesting problem of other minds. In this paper I set out a version of the conceptual problem of other minds which turns on the way in which mental occurrences are presented to the subject and situate it in relation to debates about our knowledge of other people's mental lives. The result is a distinctive problem in the philosophy of mind concerning our relation to other people.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  • Second person intentional relations and the evolution of social understanding.Juan Carlos Gomez - 1996 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 19 (1):129-130.
    Second person intentional relations, involving intentional activities directed at the perceptor, are qualitatively different from first and third person relations. They generate a peculiar, bidirectional kind of intentionality, especially in the realm of visual perception. Systems specialized in dealing with this have been selected by evolution. These systems can be considered to be the evolutionary precursors to the human theory of mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • McDowell’s disjunctivism and other minds.Anil Gomes - 2011 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 54 (3):277-292.
    John McDowell’s original motivation of disjunctivism occurs in the context of a problem regarding other minds. Recent commentators have insisted that McDowell’s disjunctivism should be classed as an epistemological disjunctivism about epistemic warrant, and distinguished from the perceptual disjunctivism of Hinton, Snowdon and others. In this paper I investigate the relation between the problem of other minds and disjunctivism, and raise some questions for this interpretation of McDowell.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Los cinco sexos, o cómo establecemos fronteras categoriales moralmente relevantes en un mundo difuso y continuo.Antoni Gomila - 2013 - Arbor 189 (762):a050.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Semiophors and sexual systems: The circulation of words and women.Ruth Goldstein - 2015 - Pragmatics and Society 6 (2):217-239.
    This article examines physical and linguistic sites through which women and words about women circulate along Latin America’s Interoceanic Road, running from the Brazilian to the Peruvian coast. I argue that the discourse on women circulates with specific linguistic-packaging, made and remade at different sites. In analyzing how these sites form ‘cartographies of communicability’, this article engages Marilena Chauí’s discussion of the ‘semiophor’ to refer to people and things that once pulled out of daily circulation, take on new meanings beyond (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Functionalism, the theory-theory and phenomenology.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):101-108.
    The ordinary understanding and ascription of mental states is a multiply complex subject. Widely discussed approaches to the subject, such as functionalism and the theory-theory (TT), have many variations and interpretations. No surprise, then, that there are misunderstandings and disagreements, which place many items on the agenda. Unfortunately, the multiplicity of issues raised by the commentators and the limitations of space make it impossible to give a full reply to everyone. My response is divided into five topics: (1) Which version(s) (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Competing accounts of belief-task performance.Alvin I. Goldman - 1993 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16 (1):43-44.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  • Unconscious mental processes.Clark Glymour - 1990 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13 (4):606-607.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Complementing explanation with induction.Clark Glymour - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (4):655-656.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Philosophy, Thought and Language.Hans-Johann Glock - 1997 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 42:151-.
    One of the most striking features of twentieth-century philosophy has been its obsession with language. For the most part, this phenomenon is greeted with hostile incredulity by external observers. Surely, they say, if philosophy is the profound and fundamental discipline which it has purported to be for more than two millennia, it must deal with something more serious than mere words, namely the things they stand for, and ultimately the essence of reality or of the human mind.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Settled-There: Heidegger on the work of art as the cultivation of place.Simon Glendinning - 2014 - Journal of Aesthetics and Phenomenology 1 (1):7-31.
    ABSTRACTThere is only one reference to art in Heidegger’s Being and Time but art is to the fore in his later writings. In this article the path from the earlier to the later writings is traced such that two surprising conclusions can be drawn: first, that Heidegger’s later thinking about art is powerfully pre-figured in the single reference to poetry in Being and Time; and, second, that Heidegger’s later thinking about art does not develop a new discourse on aesthetics but, (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Derrida and the Philosophy of Law and Justice.Simon Glendinning - 2016 - Law and Critique 27 (2):187-203.
    Readings of Derrida’s work on law and justice have tended to stress the distinction between them. This stress is complicated by Derrida’s own claim that it is not ‘a true distinction’. In this essay I argue that ordinary experiences of the inadequacy of existing laws do indeed imply a claim about what would be more just, but that this claim only makes sense insofar as one can appeal to another more adequate law. Exploring how Derrida negotiates a subtle path between (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  • Against Thatcherite Linguistics: Rule‐following, Speech Communities, and Biolanguage.Shane N. Glackin - 2018 - Southern Journal of Philosophy 56 (2):163-192.
    According to Chomsky and his followers, language as a biological phenomenon is a property of individual minds and brains; its status as a social phenomenon is merely epiphenomenal and not a proper object of scientific study. On a rival view, the individual's biological capacity for language cannot be properly understood in isolation from the linguistic environment, which it both depends on for its operation and—in collaboration with other speakers—builds and shapes for future generations. I argue here for the rival view (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Arousal and the disruption of language production processes in schizophrenia.Per F. Gjerde - 1986 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 9 (3):524-524.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Experience.Olav Gjelsvik - 2004 - Theoria 70 (2-3):167-191.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • Wittgenstein on Going On.Hannah Ginsborg - 2020 - Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50 (1):1-17.
    In a famous passage from the Philosophical Investigations, Wittgenstein describes a pupil who has been learning to write out various sequences of numbers in response to orders such as “+1” and “+2”. He has shown himself competent for numbers up to 1000, but when we have him continue the “+2” sequence beyond 1000, he writes the numerals 1004, 1008, 1012. As Wittgenstein describes the case: We say to him, “Look what you’re doing!” — He doesn’t understand us. We say “You (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  • On how to legitimately constrain a semantic theory.Joan Gimeno-Simó - 2021 - Semiotica 2021 (240):97-127.
    Semanticists often restrict their theories by imposing constraints on the parameters that can be employed for interpreting the expressions of a language. Such constraints are based on non-logical features of actual contexts of utterance, but they often have important effects on issues that do pertain to logic, like analyticity or entailment. For example, Kaplan’s restriction to so-called “proper contexts” was required in order to count “I am here now” as valid. In this paper I argue that constraints of this kind (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • When the Music’s Over” then “Dancing with a Partner Will Help You Find the Beat.Grant Gillett & Mary Butler - 2021 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 30 (4):631-636.
    Responses to brain injury sit in the intersection between neuroscience and an ethic of care, and require sensitive and dynamic indicators of how an individual with brain injury can learn how to live in the context of a changing environment and multiple timescales. Therapeutic relationships and rhythms underpinning such a dynamic approach are currently obscured by existing models of brain function. Something older is required and we put forward narrative types articulating outcomes of brain injury over various periods and starting (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  • The neurophilosophy of pain.Grant R. Gillett - 1991 - Philosophy 66 (April):191-206.
    The ability to feel pain is a property of human beings that seems to be based entirely in our biological natures and to place us squarely within the animal kingdom. Yet the experience of pain is often used as an example of a mental attribute with qualitative properties that defeat attempts to identify mental events with physiological mechanisms. I will argue that neurophysiology and psychology help to explain the interwoven biological and subjective features of pain and recommend a view of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  • Lessons from the History and Philosophy of Science regarding the Research Assessment Exercise.Donald Gillies - 2007 - Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 61:37-73.
    The Research Assessment Exercise was introduced in 1986 by Thatcher, and was continued by Blair. So it has now been running for 21 years. During this time, the rules governing the RAE have changed considerably, and the interval between successive RAEs has also varied. These changes are not of great importance as far as the argument of this paper is concerned. We will concentrate on the main features of the RAE which can be summarised as follows.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Justice and Beneficence.Pablo Gilabert - 2016 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 19 (5):508-533.
    What is a duty of justice? And how is it different from a duty of beneficence? We need a clear account of the contrast. Unfortunately, there is no consensus in the philosophical literature as to how to characterize it. Different articulations of it have been provided, but it is hard to identify a common core that is invariant across them. In this paper, I propose an account of how to understand duties of justice, explain how it contrasts with several proposals (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Informational Realism and World 3.Donald Gillies - 2010 - Knowledge, Technology & Policy 23 (1-2):7-24.
    This paper takes up a suggestion made by Floridi that the digital revolution is bringing about a profound change in our metaphysics. The paper aims to bring some older views from philosophy of mathematics to bear on this problem. The older views are concerned principally with mathematical realism—that is the claim that mathematical entities such as numbers exist. The new context for the discussion is informational realism, where the problem shifts to the question of the reality of information. Mathematical realism (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Hegel's Therapeutic Conception of Philosophy.Paul Giladi - 2015 - Hegel Bulletin (Special Issue on Idealism and Pragmatism) 36 (02): 248-267.
    The aim of this paper is to argue that Hegel has a therapeutic conception of philosophy, and also to argue that in significant respects this anticipates the classical pragmatist position, which is also interpreted as offering a therapeutic approach. In the first section, I introduce Hegel’s views on how theoretical reasoning has an important connection with practical life. I argue that this important connection between theoretical reason and the practical establishes Hegel as a member of the therapeutic tradition – broadly (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  • Existence, reality, and God in Peirce's metaphysics: The exquisite aesthetics of the real.Richard Gilmore - 2006 - Journal of Speculative Philosophy 20 (4):308 - 319.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Effaced Enigmata.Grant Gillett - 2017 - Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (4):616-627.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Butler and Postanalytic Philosophy.Paul Giladi - 2021 - Hypatia 36 (2):276-301.
    This article has two aims: to bring Judith Butler and Wilfrid Sellars into conversation; and to argue that Butler's poststructuralist critique of feminist identity politics has metaphilosophical potential, given her pragmatic parallel with Sellars's critique of conceptual analyses of knowledge. With regard to, I argue that Butler's objections to the definitional practice constitutive of certain ways of construing feminism is comparable to Sellars's critique of the analytical project geared toward providing definitions of knowledge. Specifically, I propose that moving away from (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • ‘What Makes My Image of Him into an Image of Him?’: Philosophers on Film and the Question of Educational Meaning.Alexis Gibbs - 2016 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 50 (4).
    This paper proceeds from the premise that film can be educational in a broader sense than its current use in classrooms for illustrative purposes, and explores the idea that film might function as a form of education in itself. To investigate the phenomenon of film as education, it is necessary to first address a number of assumptions about film, the most important of which is its objective character under study. The objective study of film holds that the meaning of film (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • ‘What Makes My Image of Him into an Image of Him?’: Philosophers on Film and the Question of Educational Meaning.Alexis Gibbs - 2017 - Journal of Philosophy of Education 51 (1):267-280.
    This paper proceeds from the premise that film can be educational in a broader sense than its current use in classrooms for illustrative purposes, and explores the idea that film might function as a form of education in itself. To investigate the phenomenon of film as education, it is necessary to first address a number of assumptions about film, the most important of which is its objective character under study. The objective study of film holds that the meaning of film (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Once Bitten: Defection And Reconciliation In A Cooperative Enterprise.Kevin Gibson, William Bottom & J. Keith Murnighan - 1999 - Business Ethics Quarterly 9 (1):69-85.
    Abstract:Business negotiations often involve cooperative arrangements. Sometimes one party will renege on a cooperative enterprise for short-term opportunistic gain. There is a common assumption that such behavior necessarily leads to a spiral of mutual antagonism. We use some of the philosophical literature to frame general research questions and identify relevant variables in dealing with defection. We then describe an experimental approach for examining the possibility of reconciliation and discuss the results of one such experiment where participants were the victims of (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  • Alternative Philosophical Models of Experience and Authenticity and their Relevance to Marketing Practices.Matteo Giannasi & Francesco Casarin - 2023 - Philosophy of Management 22 (3):395-418.
    This article answers the question raised by the special issue of this journal in a positive way: managerial practices do need philosophy. In particular, it argues for a more concrete claim: managerial practices have needed philosophy in the past to develop some important intellectual tools, and today they still need to be open to the continuous conceptual and methodological innovations introduced by competing philosophical research programmes, because loyalty to just one favourite philosophical paradigm can hinder the ability of managerial practices (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  • Taxa, life, and thinking.Michael T. Ghiselin - 1981 - Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (2):303-313.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  • Wittgenstein, Korsgaard and the Publicity of Reasons.Joshua Gert - 2013 - Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy (5):1-21.
    Wittgenstein, Korsgaard and the Publicity of Reasons. . ???aop.label???. doi: 10.1080/0020174X.2013.776297.
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  • Taking a social perspective on moral disgust.Joshua Gert - 2021 - Metaphilosophy 52 (5):530-540.
    Research on moral disgust suffers from a methodological bias. The bulk of such investigation focuses almost exclusively on the operation of moral disgust within the psychology of a single individual, or as involving an interaction between two people. This leads to certain questions being salient, while other phenomena, which emerge only at the level of an entire community or society, are largely hidden from view. The present paper explains and defends a perspective that emphasizes the role of moral disgust within (...)
    Download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark